Skip to main content
Log in

The Consistency of Arithmetic

  • Article
  • Published:
The Mathematical Intelligencer Aims and scope Submit manuscript

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Notes

  1. There is another version of the Peano axioms, usually known as the second-order Peano axioms, with the property that there is only one mathematical structure satisfying them (namely \(\mathbb {N}\)), which can be used as a definition of \(\mathbb {N}\). In contrast, there are many nonisomorphic structures, known as nonstandard models, that satisfy the first-order Peano axioms.

  2. As far as the consistency of first-order arithmetic is concerned, the distinction between intuitionistic logic and classical logic turns out not to matter too much. Gödel, and independently Gentzen [13], showed constructively that Heyting arithmetic, which is the intuitionistic counterpart of PA, is consistent if and only PA is consistent.

  3. Note in particular that the variables are not allowed to range over sets of elements; this restriction is what makes PA a first-order theory.

  4. For much more historical context, I recommend the article by Kahle [10].

  5. On the other hand, some people, such as Solomon Feferman [5], explicitly reject platonism but nevertheless find the argument that \(\mathbb {N}\) satisfies all the axioms of PA to be completely convincing.

  6. See, for example, Willard [18] for an explanation of how this might be possible.

  7. In fact, the theorem can be further weakened to assert the stabilization of all primitive recursive descending sequences of ordinals; see [17, Lemma 12.79] or [2, Theorem 4.6], for example. The fact that PRA plus Theorem 2 implies that PA is consistent is only implicit and not explicit in Gentzen’s original proof. I have chosen this way of presenting the argument rather than the more common approach of explaining what “induction up to \(\epsilon _0\)” is, because I believe that Theorem 2 is more accessible to the general reader without training in logic and set theory.

  8. A far stronger induction argument was used by Robertson and Seymour in their proof of the graph minor theorem [9], and nobody seems to have rejected that theorem on those grounds.

  9. Note that the unreasonable soundness of mathematics is not the same as Eugene Wigner’s unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics in the natural sciences. What Stefan cannot explain are mathematicians’ purely mathematical predictions rather than their scientific predictions.

References

  1. Jeremy Avigad and Solomon Feferman. Gödel’s functional (“Dialectica”) interpretation. In Handbook of Proof Theory, edited by S. R. Buss, Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, Book 137, Elsevier, 1998, Chapter V, pp. 337–406.

  2. Wilfried Buchholz. Notation systems for infinitary derivations. Archive for Mathematical Logic 30 (1991), 277–296.

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  3. Walter Carnielli and Marcelo Esteban Coniglio. Paraconsistent Logic: Consistency, Contradiction and Negation. Springer, 2018.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  4. Ted Chiang. “Division By Zero.” In Stories of Your Life and Others. Vintage, 2016.

  5. Solomon Feferman. Does reductive proof theory have a viable rationale? Erkenntnis 53 (2000), 63–96.

  6. Torkel Franzén. Inexhaustibility: A Non-exhaustive Treatment. A. K. Peters/CRC Press, 2004.

  7. Harvey Friedman. Concerning Con(PA). Foundations of Mathematics mailing list, 29 May 2015. Available online at https://cs.nyu.edu/pipermail/fom/2015-May/018752.html.

  8. Harvey Friedman. The inevitability of logical strength: strict reverse mathematics. In Logic Colloquium 2006, edited by S. Barry Cooper et al., Lecture Notes in Logic 32. Association for Symbolic Logic, 2009, pp. 135–183.

  9. Harvey Friedman, Neil Robertson, and Paul Seymour. The metamathematics of the graph minor theorem. In Logic and Combinatorics, edited by S. Simpson, Contemporary Mathematics 65. American Mathematical Society, 1987, pp. 229–261.

  10. Reinhard Kahle. Gentzen’s consistency proof in context. In Gentzen’s Centenary: The Quest for Consistency, edited by Reinhard Kahle and Michael Rathjen. Springer, 2015, pp. 3–24.

  11. Edward Nelson. Inconsistency of primitive recursive arithmetic. arXiv:1509.09209 [math.LO], 30 Sept. 2015.

  12. Edward Nelson. Taking formalism seriously. Math. Intelligencer 15 (1993), 8–11.

  13. Gerhard Gentzen. The Collected Papers of Gerhard Gentzen, edited by M. E. Szabo. North-Holland, 1969.

  14. Pavel Pudlák. Incompleteness in the finite domain. arXiv:1601.01487v2 [math.LO], 18 May 2017.

  15. Stephen G. Simpson. Subsystems of Second Order Arithmetic, 2nd edition. Cambridge University Press, 2009.

  16. W. W. Tait. Gödel’s reformulation of Gentzen’s first consistency proof for arithmetic: the no-counterexample interpretation. Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 11 (2005), 225–238.

  17. Gaisi Takeuti. Proof Theory, 2nd ed. Dover, 2013.

  18. Dan E. Willard. Self-verifying axiom systems, the incompleteness theorem and related reflection principles. Journal of Symbolic Logic 66 (2001), 536–596.

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank Anton Freund for pointing me to the work of Takeuti [17] and Buchholz [2], and Harvey Friedman, Sam Moelius, Joe Shipman, Bill Tait, and Bill Taylor for helpful comments on an earlier draft of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Timothy Y. Chow.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Chow, T.Y. The Consistency of Arithmetic. Math Intelligencer 41, 22–30 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00283-018-9837-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00283-018-9837-z

Navigation