1 Introduction

By an Abel-Grassmann’s groupoid (briefly an AG-groupoid) we shall mean any groupoid which satisfies the identity (xy)z=(zy)x. Such a groupoid is also called a left almost semigroup (briefly an LA-semigroup) or a left invertive groupoid or a right modular groupoid (cf. [4, 5, 7]). This structure is closely related to a commutative semigroup, because if an AG-groupoid contains a right identity, then it becomes a commutative monoid. Also, if an AG-groupoid A with a left zero z is finite, then (under certain conditions) A∖{z} is a commutative group [8].

The name Abel-Grassmann’s groupoids was suggested by Stojan Bogdanović at a seminar in Niš. The first time that this name appeared was in the paper [15] and in the book [2].

An AG-groupoid A satisfying the identity x(yz)=y(xz) is called an AG ∗∗-groupoid. Such groupoids were studied by many authors. For example, in [6] it has been proved that an AG ∗∗-groupoid containing a left cancellative AG ∗∗-subgroupoid can be embedded in a commutative monoid whose cancellative elements form a commutative group whose identity coincides with the identity of the commutative monoid. Also, each AG ∗∗-groupoid satisfying the identity (xx)x=x(xx) can be uniquely expressed as a semilattice of certain Archimedean AG ∗∗-groupoids [10]. Some other decompositions of certain AG ∗∗-groupoids are given in [12, 16]. Further, certain fundamental congruences on AG ∗∗-groupoids are described in [9, 14]. Finally, the kernel normal system of an inversive AG ∗∗-groupoid has been studied in [1].

In this paper we investigate completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoids, i.e., AG ∗∗-groupoids in which every element a has a unique inverse a −1 such that aa −1=a −1 a. In Sect. 2 we establish some necessary definitions and facts concerning AG ∗∗-groupoids. In Sect. 3 we give a few interesting results about completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoids. Recall from [3] that any completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid satisfies Lallement’s lemma for regular semigroups. Using this fact, we describe the maximum idempotent-separating congruence μ (which is equal to the least semilattice congruence) on a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid A. In particular, A is a semilattice E A of AG-groups (eE A ). Also, we show that the interval [1 A ,μ] is a modular lattice. The main result of this section says that any AG-groupoid A is a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid if and only if A is a strong semilattice of AG-groups. On the one hand, in the light of this fact, we are able to construct completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoids. On the other hand, completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoids are very similar to Clifford semigroups (i.e., (strong) semilattices of groups).

At the beginning of Sect. 4 we prove that any congruence ρ on a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid is uniquely determined by (i) its kernel and trace; (ii) the set of ρ-classes containing idempotents. Furthermore, we determine the least AG-group congruence σ and describe all AG-group congruences in terms of their kernels. Also, we give some equivalent conditions for a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid A to be E-unitary and we describe all E-unitary congruences on A.

In Sect. 5 we characterize abstractly congruences on an arbitrary completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid A via the so-called congruences pairs for A. Furthermore, we study the trace classes of the complete lattice \(\mathcal{C}(A)\) of all congruences on A. The main result of this section says that the map ρ→tr(ρ) (\(\rho\in \mathcal{C}(A)\)) is a complete lattice homomorphism of \(\mathcal{C}(A)\) onto the lattice of all congruences on the semilattice E A . Also, if θ denotes the congruence on \(\mathcal{C}(A)\) induced by this map, then for every \(\rho\in\mathcal{C}(A)\), ρθ is a modular lattice (with commutating elements). Moreover, ρθ=[ρ θ ,μ(ρ)]. If in addition, A is E-unitary, then ρ θ =ρσ, and the mapping ρρσ (\(\rho\in\mathcal {C}(A)\)) is a complete lattice homomorphism of \(\mathcal{C}(A)\) onto the lattice of idempotent pure congruences. Finally, we investigate the lattice \(\mathcal{FC}(A)\) of all fundamental congruences on A. We prove that \(\mathcal{FC}(A)=\{\mu(\rho):\rho\in\mathcal{C}(A)\}\cong \mathcal{C}(E_{A})\).

In Sect. 6 we show first that each completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid A possesses a largest idempotent pure congruence τ. Also, we study the kernel classes of \(\mathcal {C}(A)\). We prove a result analogous to a result from the previous section. In particular, we show that the interval [ρμ,τ(ρ)] consist of all congruences on A such that their kernels are equal to ker(ρ). Further, we go back to study E-unitary congruences. We determine all E-unitary congruences on A; that is, we show that a congruence is E-unitary if and only if its kernel is equal to the kernel of some AG-group congruence on A. Finally, we give once again necessary and sufficient conditions for a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid to be E-unitary.

The terminology used in this paper coincides with semigroup terminology (see the book [11]).

2 Preliminaries

One can easily check that in an arbitrary AG-groupoid A, the medial law is valid, that is, the equality

(1)

holds for all a,b,c,dA.

Recall from [16] that an AG-band A is an AG-groupoid satisfying the identity x 2=x. If in addition, ab=ba for all a,bA, then we say that A is an AG-semilattice.

Let A be an AG-groupoid and BA. Denote the set of all idempotents of B by E B , that is, E B ={bB:b 2=b}. From (1) it follows that if E A ≠∅, then E A E A E A , therefore, E A is an AG-band.

An AG-groupoid satisfying the identity x(yz)=y(xz) is said to be an AG ∗∗-groupoid. Any AG ∗∗-groupoid is paramedial, i.e., it satisfies the identity

(2)

Notice that each AG-groupoid with a left identity is an AG ∗∗-groupoid. Further, observe that if A is an AG ∗∗-groupoid, then (2) implies that if E A ≠∅, then E A is an AG-semilattice. Indeed, in this case E A is an AG-band and ef=(ee)(ff)=(fe)(fe)=fe for all e,fE A . Moreover for a,bA and eE A , using (1) and (2) we have

$$e(ab)=(ee)(ab)=(ea)(eb)=(ba)e=(ea)b. $$

We have just proved the following result (its second part was proved earlier in [14]).

Proposition 2.1

Let A be an AG ∗∗-groupoid. Then

$$ e\cdot ab=ea\cdot b $$
(3)

for all a,bA and eE A .

In particular, the set of all idempotents of an arbitrary AG ∗∗-groupoid is either empty or a semilattice.

We say that an AG ∗∗-groupoid A is completely regular if for every aA there exists xA such that a=(ax)a and ax=xa. Observe that in such a case,

$$(ax)(ax)=(aa)(xx)=x(aa\cdot x)=x(xa\cdot a)=x(ax\cdot a)=xa=ax\in E_A, $$

therefore, E A forms a semilattice.

Let A be an AG-groupoid with a left identity e and aA. An element a of A is said to be a left (right) inverse of a if a a=e (resp. aa =e), and an element of A which is both a left and right inverse of a is called an inverse of a. Let a be a left inverse of a. Then aa =(ea)a =(a a)e=e. It follows that any left inverse a of a is also its right inverse, therefore, it is its inverse. In particular, if a ∗∗ is another left inverse of a, then a =(a a)a =(a ∗∗ a)a =(a a)a ∗∗=(a ∗∗ a)a ∗∗=a ∗∗. The conclusion is that each left inverse of a is its unique inverse. Further, if f is a left identity of A, then fe=e=ee, so e=f, i.e., e is a unique left identity of A. Dually, any right inverse of a is its unique inverse. Denote as usual the inverse of a by a −1. Finally, it is clear that a=(a −1)−1, (ab)−1=a −1 b −1.

An AG-groupoid with a left identity in which every element has a left inverse is called an AG-group.

Proposition 2.2

Let A be an AG-groupoid with a left identity e. Then the following conditions are equivalent:

  1. (a)

    A is an AG-group;

  2. (b)

    every element of A has a right inverse;

  3. (c)

    every element a of A has a unique inverse a −1;

  4. (d)

    the equation xa=b has a unique solution for all a,bA.

Proof

By above (a) ⇒ (b) ⇒ (c).

(c) ⇒ (d). Let a,bA. Then b=eb=(aa −1)b=(ba −1)a, i.e., ba −1 is a solution of the equation xa=b. Also, if c and d are solutions of this equation, then

$$c=ec=(a^{-1}a)c=(ca)a^{-1}=(da)a^{-1}=d. $$

(d) ⇒ (a). This is obvious. □

Notice that if g is an arbitrary idempotent of an AG-group A with a left identity e, then gg=g=eg. Hence e=g, therefore, E A ={e}.

Denote by V(a) the set of all inverses of a, that is,

$$V(a)=\{a^{*}\in A:a=(aa^{*})a, \ a^{*}=(a^{*}a)a^{*}\}. $$

An AG-groupoid A is called regular (in [1] it is called inverse) if V(a)≠∅ for all aA. Note that AG-groups are of course regular AG-groupoids, but the class of all regular AG-groupoids is vastly more extensive than the class of all AG-groups. For example, every AG-band A is evidently regular, since a=(aa)a for every aA. In [1] it has been proved that in any regular AG ∗∗-groupoid, |V(a)|=1 (aA), therefore, we call it an inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid. In that case, we denote a unique inverse of aA by a −1. Furthermore, recall from [1] that in any regular AG-groupoid A, V(a)V(b)⊆V(ab) for all a,bA. Indeed, let a V(a) and b V(b). Then

so

$$(ab)(a^{*}b^{*})\cdot ab=(ba)(aa^{*})=(aa^{*}\cdot a)b=ab. $$

By symmetry, a b =(a b )(ab)⋅(a b ), as exactly required. Finally, there are regular AG-groupoids without idempotents. On the other hand, if a V(a) and aa =a a in the AG-groupoid A, then aa E A (cf. [1]).

3 Completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoids

One can prove (cf. [1]) that in an inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid A, aa −1=a −1 a if and only if aa −1,a −1 aE A . Also, in [1] the authors studied congruences on inverse AG ∗∗-groupoids satisfying the identity xx −1=x −1 x. We will call such groupoids completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoids. Each AG-group is a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid.

Example 3.1

Let A be a commutative inverse semigroup. Put ab=a −1 b for all a,bA, where a −1 is a unique inverse of a in the inverse semigroup A. Then it is easy to check that (A,⋅) is an AG ∗∗-groupoid and E (A,⋅)=E A . Furthermore, (aa)⋅a=a, so a is its own unique inverse in (A,⋅) for every aA, so aaE (A,⋅) for all aA and (A,⋅) is a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid. Also, we have that a −1⋅(ab)=a −1a −1 b=aa −1 b. Hence

$$a^{-1}\cdot(a^{-1}\cdot(a\cdot b))=a^{-1}\cdot aa^{-1}b=aaa^{-1}b=aa^{-1}ab=ab, $$

that is,

$$ab=a^{-1}\cdot(a^{-1}\cdot(a\cdot b))=a\cdot(a^{-1}\cdot (a^{-1}\cdot b)) $$

for all a,bA.

Let ρ be a congruence on (A,⋅). From the above equalities follows easily that ρ is a congruence on the commutative inverse semigroup A. Also, if (a,aa)∈ρ in (A,⋅), then (a,a −1 a)∈ρ in A, since aa=a −1 a. Thus (a 2,aa −1 a)∈ρ in A, so (a 2,a)∈ρ in A. Lallement’s Lemma implies that there exists eE A and so eE (A,⋅). On the other hand, trivially aaE in (A,⋅).

Conversely, one can easily see that if ρ is a congruence on A, then ρ is also a congruence on (A,⋅). Further, if (a,a 2)∈ρ in A, then (a,e)∈ρ in A for some eE A . Since ee=e, then (a,aa)∈ρ in (A,⋅).

A groupoid A is said to be idempotent-surjective if for each congruence ρ on A, every idempotent ρ-class contains an idempotent of A.

The following theorem was proved in [3]. Now we give another proof.

Theorem 3.2

Completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoids are idempotent-surjective.

Proof

Let ρ be a congruence on a completely inversive AG ∗∗-groupoid A, aA and aρa 2. We know that there exists an element xA such that a 2=(a 2 x)a 2, x=(xa 2)x and a 2 x=xa 2E A . Note that

$$(a^2x)(aa)=a(a^2x\cdot a)=a(xa^2\cdot a)=a(aa^2\cdot x)=(aa^2)(ax)=a^2(a^2x)=a^2(xa^2), $$

that is, a 2=a 2(xa 2). Put e=a(xa). Then eρa 2(xa 2)=a 2 ρa. Also,

$$e^2=(a\cdot xa)(a\cdot xa)=a\cdot(a\cdot xa)(xa)=a\cdot(ax)(xa\cdot a)=a\cdot(ax)(a^2x). $$

Furthermore, using (2)

$$(ax)(a^2x)=(ax)(xa^2)=(a^2x)(xa)=(xa^2)(xa)=(xa^2\cdot x)a $$

by (3), since xa 2E A . Hence (ax)(a 2 x)=xa. Consequently,

$$e^2=a(xa)=e\in E_A, $$

as required. □

Let ρ be a congruence on a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid A and a,bA. It is evident that ()−1=a −1 ρ. Hence if (a,b)∈ρ, then (a −1,b −1)∈ρ. Moreover, A/ρ is a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid.

Further, let A be an arbitrary groupoid and \(\mathcal{V}\) be a fixed class of groupoids. We say that a congruence ρ on A is a \(\mathcal{V}\)-congruence if \(A/\rho\in\mathcal{V}\). For example, if \(\mathcal{V}\) is the class of all semilattices, then ρ is a semilattice congruence on A if A/ρ is a semilattice. Moreover, A is called a semilattice A/ρ of AG-groups if there is a semilattice congruence ρ on A such that every ρ-class is an AG-group. In that case, A is a semilattice Y=A/ρ of AG-groups A α , αY, where A α are the ρ-classes of A, or briefly a semilattice Y=A/ρ of AG-groups A α . Notice that in such a case, A α A β A αβ , where αβ is the product of α and β in Y. Also, A αβ =A βα and A (αβ)γ =A α(βγ).

Finally, we say that a congruence ρ on a groupoid A is idempotent-separating if every ρ-class contains at most one idempotent of A.

The following simple result will at times be useful.

Lemma 3.3

A completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid containing only one idempotent is an AG-group.

Proof

Let E A ={e},aA. Then e=aa −1=a −1 a. Hence ea=(aa −1)a=a. Thus A is an AG-group. □

For elementary facts about (inverse) semigroups the reader is referred to the book of Petrich [11]. It is well known that each completely regular inverse semigroup is a semilattice of groups. We prove now an analogous result.

Theorem 3.4

Let A be a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid. Define on A the relation μ by

$$(a,b)\in\mu\quad\iff\quad aa^{-1}=bb^{-1} $$

for all a,bA. Then:

  1. (a)

    μ is the least semilattice congruence on A;

  2. (b)

    every μ-class is an AG-group;

  3. (c)

    μ is the maximum idempotent-separating congruence on A;

  4. (d)

    A is a semilattice A/μ of AG-groups;

  5. (e)

    E A A/μ.

Hence A is a semilattice E A of AG-groups G e , where G e ={aA:aa −1=e} for eE A .

Proof

(a) Clearly, μ is an equivalence relation on A. Let (a,b)∈μ and cA. Then

$$(ca)(ca)^{-1}=(ca)(c^{-1}a^{-1})=(cc^{-1})(aa^{-1})=(cc^{-1})(bb^{-1})=(cb)(cb)^{-1} $$

and similarly (ac)(ac)−1=(bc)(bc)−1. Hence μ is a congruence on A. Also,

$$(aa^{-1})(aa^{-1})^{-1}=(aa^{-1})(a^{-1}(a^{-1})^{-1})=(aa^{-1})(a^{-1}a)=(aa^{-1})(aa^{-1})=aa^{-1}, $$

so (a,aa −1)∈μ, where aa −1E A . Since E A is a semilattice, then S/μ is a semilattice, too. Consequently, μ is a semilattice congruence on A. Moreover, since e −1=e for every eE A , then μ is idempotent-separating.

Finally, suppose that there is a semilattice congruence ρ on A such that μρ. Then the relation μρ is a semilattice congruence on A which is properly contained in μ, so not every (μρ)-class contains an idempotent of A, since each μ-class contains exactly one idempotent, a contradiction with Theorem 3.2. Consequently, μ must be the least semilattice congruence on A.

(b) We have noticed above that μ is idempotent-separating. It is evident that every μ-class is itself a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid, since a −1 for all aA. In view of Lemma 3.3, every μ-class is an AG-group.

(c) Let ρ be an idempotent-separating congruence on A,(a,b)∈ρ. Then a −1 ρb −1. It follows that (aa −1,bb −1)∈ρ. Thus aa −1=bb −1, so (a,b)∈μ. Consequently, ρμ.

The rest is obvious. □

Let \(\mathcal{C}(A)\) denote the complete lattice of all congruences on a groupoid A. It is well known that if a sublattice \(\mathcal{L}\) of \(\mathcal{C}(A)\) has the property that αβ=βα for all \(\alpha,\beta\in\mathcal{L}\), then \(\mathcal{L}\) is a modular lattice.

Let A be a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid. Consider the complete lattice [1 A ,μ] of all idempotent-separating congruences on A (see Theorem 3.4(c)). Let ρ 1,ρ 2∈[1 A ,μ] and (a,b)∈ρ 1 ρ 2. Then there is cA such that 1 2 b. In particular, (a,c),(c,b)∈μ. Hence

$$a=aa^{-1}\cdot a = cc^{-1}\cdot a \rho_2 bc^{-1}\cdot a=ac^{-1}\cdot b \rho_1 cc^{-1}\cdot b=bb^{-1}\cdot b=b, $$

so (a,b)∈ρ 2 ρ 1. Thus ρ 1 ρ 2ρ 2 ρ 1. By symmetry, ρ 2 ρ 1ρ 1 ρ 2. We have just shown the following theorem.

Theorem 3.5

Let A be a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid. Then the interval [1 A ,μ], consisting of all idempotent-separating congruences on A, is a modular lattice.

Corollary 3.6

The lattice of congruences on an AG-group is modular.

A completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid A is a semilattice E A of AG-groups G e (eE A ), where G e ={aA:aa −1=e} (Theorem 3.4). The relation ≤ defined on the semilattice E A by efe=ef is the so-called natural partial order on E A .

Let ef and a e G e . Then fa e G f G e G fe =G f . Hence we may define a map ϕ e,f :G e G f by

$$a_e\phi_{e,f}=fa_e \quad(a_e\in G_e). $$

Also, for all a e ,b e G e , (fa e )(fb e )=(ff)(a e b e )=f(a e b e ), so

(4)

i.e., ϕ e,f is a homomorphism between the AG-groups G e and G f . In particular, e,f =f (this follows also from ef). Observe that ϕ e,e is the identical automorphism of the AG-group G e .

Suppose now that efg. Then for every a e G e ,

$$(a_e\phi_{e,f})\phi _{f,g}=g(fa_e)=(gg)(fa_e)=(gf)(ga_e)=g(ga_e)=ga_e=a_e\phi_{e,g}, $$

since ga e G g G e G ge =G g , that is,

(5)

for every e,f,gE A such that efg.

Finally, let a e G e and a f G f (and so a e a f G ef ; also e,fef). Then we get a e a f =(ef)(a e a f )=(efef)(a e a f )=((ef)a e )((ef)a f ), i.e.,

(6)

Remark that we have used only the medial law in the proof of the equalities (4), (5) and (6), therefore, if an AG-groupoid A is a semilattice E A of the AG-groups G e (eE A ), then these equalities hold true.

Let now Y be a semilattice, \(\mathcal{F}=\{A_{\alpha}:\alpha\in Y\}\) be a family of disjoint AG-groupoids of type \(\mathcal{T}\), indexed by the set Y (\(\mathcal{F}\) may be a family of disjoint AG-groups). Suppose also that for each pair (α,β)∈Y×Y such that αβ there is an associated homomorphism ϕ α,β :A α A β such that

  1. (a)

    ϕ α,α is the identical automorphism of A α for every αY, and

  2. (b)

    ϕ α,β ϕ β,γ =ϕ α,γ for all α,β,γY such that αβγ.

Put A=⋃{A α :αY}, and define a binary operation ⋅ on A by the rule that if a α A α and a β A β , then

$$a_\alpha\cdot a_\beta=(a_\alpha\phi_{\alpha,\alpha\beta})(a_\beta\phi _{\beta,\alpha\beta}), $$

where the multiplication on the right side takes place in the AG-groupoid A αβ .

It is a matter of routine to check that (A,⋅) is an AG-groupoid. If in addition, each AG-groupoid A α is an AG ∗∗-groupoid (in particular, an AG-group), then (A,⋅) is itself an AG ∗∗-groupoid. Finally, in the light of the condition (a), the new multiplication coincides with the given of each A α , so A is certainly a semilattice Y of AG-groupoids A α . We usually denote the product in A also by juxtaposition, and write A=[Y;A α ;ϕ α,β ].

We call the AG-groupoid [Y;A α ;ϕ α,β ] a strong semilattice of AG-groupoids A α .

In fact, we have proved the following theorem (see (4), (5) and (6)).

Theorem 3.7

Let an AG-groupoid A be a semilattice A/ρ of AG-groups. Then A is a strong semilattice of AG-groups. In fact,

$$A=[E_A;G_e;\phi_{e,f}], $$

where for all e,fE A , G e =; ϕ e,f :G e G f is given by

$$a_e\phi_{e,f}=fa_e \quad(a_e\in G_e), $$

and

$$a_ea_f=(a_e\phi_{e,ef})(a_f\phi_{f,ef}) \quad(a_e\in G_e,a_f\in G_f). $$

In particular, A is an AG ∗∗-groupoid.

Proof

Let A be a semilattice A/ρ of AG-groups, then ρ is idempotent-separating. Hence E A A/ρ, so E A is necessarily a semilattice. Thus A is a semilattice E A of AG-groups G e = (eE A ). This implies the thesis of the theorem. □

It is well known that if a semigroup S is a semilattice of groups, then its idempotents are central, that is, se=es for all sS and eE S . The following proposition says particularly that there is no non-associative AG-groupoids which are a semilattice of AG-groups and their idempotents are central.

Proposition 3.8

Let A be an AG-groupoid which is a semilattice of AG-groups. If the idempotents of A are central, then A is a strong semilattice of Abelian groups. In particular, A is a commutative semigroup.

Proof

Let A=[E A ;G e ;ϕ e,f ]. If the idempotents of A are central, then particularly for all eE A , ae=ea for every aG e . This implies that every G e is a commutative group, so A is a strong semilattice of Abelian groups. From the definition of the multiplication in [E A ;G e ;ϕ e,f ] and from the fact that Abelian groups are commutative semigroups follows that A is a commutative semigroup. □

Remark 1

Let A be a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid. Then ae=ea for all aA, eE A if and only if a=a(a −1 a) for every aA. Indeed,

$$ea=e(aa^{-1}\cdot a)=(e\cdot aa^{-1})a=(a\cdot aa^{-1})e=(a(a^{-1}a))e. $$

This implies that if a=a(a −1 a), then the idempotents of A are central. The converse implication is obvious.

In the proof of Theorem 3.2 we have shown that a 2=a 2(xa 2) for every aA, where xV(a 2). Furthermore, A (2)={a 2:aA} is an AG ∗∗-groupoid, since a 2 b 2=(ab)2 for all a,bA. Also, (a −1)2V(a 2) for every aA. Evidently, E A A (2). Consequently, A (2) is a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid in which the idempotents are central. From Proposition 3.8 we obtain the following theorem.

Theorem 3.9

If A is a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid, then A (2) is a strong semilattice of Abelian groups with semilattice E A of idempotents.

The next theorem gives necessary and sufficient conditions for an AG-groupoid to be a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid.

Theorem 3.10

The following conditions concerning an AG-groupoid A are equivalent:

  1. (a)

    A is a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid;

  2. (b)

    A is a semilattice of AG-groups;

  3. (c)

    A is a strong semilattice of AG-groups.

Proof

(a) ⇒ (b) by Theorem 3.4 and (b) ⇒ (c) by Theorem 3.7.

(c) ⇒ (a). In that case, A is an AG ∗∗-groupoid (see again Theorem 3.7). Also, let aA. Then a belongs to some AG-group G e , where e is a left identity of G e . Consider now a unique inverse a −1 of a in G e . Then evidently a=(aa −1)a, a −1=(a −1 a)a −1 and aa −1=a −1 a=e. Consequently, A is a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid. □

Remark 2

In view of the above theorem, we are able to construct completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoids.

Let A be a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid. The relation ≤ A defined on A by a A b if aE A b is the natural partial order on A. Notice the restriction of ≤ A to E A is equal to the natural partial order ≤ on E A , therefore, we will be write briefly ≤ instead of ≤ A .

The following result can be deduced from [12].

Lemma 3.11

In any completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid A, the relationis a compatible partial order on A. Also, ab implies a −1b −1 for all a,bA.

Proof

We include a simple proof. It is evident that ≤ is reflexive and preserves inverses. Let ab and ba, i.e., a=eb and b=fa for some e,fE A . Then by Proposition 2.1, ea=a. Using again Proposition 2.1, a=eb=e(fa)=(ef)a=(fe)a=f(ea)=fa=b. Hence ≤ is antisymmetric. From Proposition 2.1 it follows also that ≤ is transitive. Finally, if ab and cd, that is, a=eb and c=fd for some e,fE A , then we obtain that ac=(eb)(fd)=(ef)(bd). Thus acbd. □

For some equivalent definitions of the relation ≤, consult [12]. Moreover, we have the following proposition.

Proposition 3.12

In any completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid A, ≤∩ μ=1 A , that is, if A=[E A ;G e ;ϕ e,f ], then \(\leq _{|G_{e}}=1_{G_{e}}\) for every eE A .

Proof

Let a(≤∩μ)b. Then aa −1=bb −1 and a=eb for some eE A , therefore we get aa −1=(eb)(eb −1)=(ee)(bb −1)=e(bb −1)=(eb)b −1=ab −1. Consequently,

$$a=(aa^{-1})a=(bb^{-1})a=(ab^{-1})b=(aa^{-1})b=(bb^{-1})b=b, $$

as required. □

Finally, for any nonempty subset B of a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid A, we call

$$B\omega=\{a\in A:\exists (b\in B)\ b\leq a\} $$

the closure of B in A; if B=, then B is closed in A. Note that is closed in A.

It is clear that a subgroupoid B of a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid A is itself a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid if and only if bB implies b −1B for every bB. In such a case, B is a completely inverse AG ∗∗-subgroupoid of A. Using Lemma 3.11, one can prove the following proposition.

Proposition 3.13

If B is a completely inverse AG ∗∗-subgroupoid of a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid A, then is a closed completely inverse AG ∗∗-subgroupoid of A.

In particular, E A ω is a closed completely inverse AG ∗∗-subgroupoid of A. It is easy to see that

$$E_A\omega=\{a\in A:(\exists e\in E_A)\ ea\in E_A\}. $$

4 Certain E-unitary congruences

Let ρ be a congruence on a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid A. By the kernel ker(ρ) (respectively the trace tr(ρ)) of ρ we shall mean the set {aA:(a,a 2)∈ρ} (respectively the restriction of ρ to the set E A ). Note that tr(ρ) is a congruence on the semilattice E A . Also, in the light of Theorem 3.2,

$$\ker(\rho)=\{a\in A:\exists (e\in E_A)\ (a,e)\in\rho\}=\bigcup\{e\rho :e\in E_A\}. $$

The following proposition may be sometimes useful.

Proposition 4.1

Let A=[E A ;G e ;ϕ e,f ] be a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid and let a,bA be such that abE A . Then ab=ba.

Proof

Let ab=eE A . Then

$$ba=b(aa^{-1}\cdot a)=(aa^{-1})(ba)=(ab)(a^{-1}a)\in E_A. $$

Since ab,baG e , then ab=ba. □

The following theorem says particularly that each congruence on a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid is uniquely determined by its kernel and trace.

Theorem 4.2

If ρ is a congruence on a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid A, then

$$(a,b)\in\rho\quad\iff\quad(aa^{-1},bb^{-1})\in\mathrm{tr}(\rho)\ \&\ ab^{-1}\in\ker (\rho). $$

Thus for all \(\rho_{1},\rho_{2}\in\mathcal{C}(A)\),

$$\rho_1\subseteq\rho_2\quad\iff\quad\mathrm{tr}(\rho_1)\subseteq\mathrm{tr}(\rho_2)\ \&\ \ker(\rho_1)\subseteq\ker(\rho_2). $$

In particular, each congruence on a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid is uniquely determined by its kernel and trace.

Proof

Let (a,b)∈ρ. Then evidently (a −1,b −1),(ab −1,bb −1)∈ρ, so (aa −1,bb −1)∈tr(ρ) and ab −1∈ker(ρ).

Conversely, let now (aa −1,bb −1)∈tr(ρ),ab −1∈ker(ρ). In view of Theorem 3.4, (,)∈μ S/ρ , so ((ab −1)ρ,(bb −1)ρ)∈μ S/ρ . Since ab −1∈ker(ρ), then (ab −1)ρE A/ρ . Evidently, (bb −1)ρE A/ρ . Hence (ab −1)ρ=(bb −1)ρ (by Theorem 3.4(c)). Thus

$$a\rho=(aa^{-1}\cdot a)\rho=(bb^{-1}\cdot a)\rho=(ab^{-1}\cdot b)\rho =(bb^{-1}\cdot b)\rho=b\rho, $$

as required. The rest of the theorem follows from the first equivalence. □

Remark 3

Note that the first part of the above theorem is true for an arbitrary Clifford semigroup, the proof is very similar. In fact, if ab −1∈ker(ρ), then

$$(ab^{-1})\rho=(b^{-1}a)\rho=(b^{-1}b)\rho, $$

so =(aa −1a)ρ=(bb −1a)ρ=(bb −1 a)ρ=(bb −1 b)ρ=.

Clearly, the condition ab −1∈ker(ρ) from Theorem 4.2 is equivalent to the condition a −1 b∈ker(ρ). In the light of Proposition 4.1, it is also equivalent to b −1 a∈ker(ρ).

Theorem 4.3

Let ρ 1,ρ 2 be congruences on a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid A. Then the following statements are equivalent:

  1. (a)

    1 2 for every eE A ;

  2. (b)

    ρ 1ρ 2.

In particular, every congruence ρ on a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid is uniquely determined by the set of ρ-classes containing idempotents.

Proof

(a) ⇒ (b). Let a 1. Then

$$aa^{-1}\in(bb^{-1})\rho_1\subseteq(bb^{-1})\rho_2\quad \&\quad ab^{-1}\in (bb^{-1})\rho_1\subseteq(bb^{-1})\rho_2. $$

In the light of Theorem 4.2, a 2, that is, ρ 1ρ 2.

(b) ⇒ (a). This is trivial. □

In Sect. 5 we shall characterize abstractly the congruences on a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid A via the congruence pairs for A.

A nonempty subset B of a groupoid A is called left (right) unitary if baB (resp. abB) implies aB for every bB,aA. Also, we say that B is unitary if it is both left and right unitary. Finally, a groupoid A is said to be E-unitary if E A is unitary.

Proposition 4.4

Let E A be a left unitary subset of an AG-groupoid. Then E A is also right unitary. If in addition, A is an AG ∗∗-groupoid, then the following conditions are equivalent:

  1. (a)

    A is E-unitary;

  2. (b)

    E A is left unitary;

  3. (c)

    E A is right unitary.

Proof

(a) ⇒ (b), (c). Obvious.

(b) ⇒ (a). Let aA,eE A and let ae=fE A . Then (ae)fE A , therefore, (fe)aE A . Thus aE A , since feE A and E A is left unitary.

(c) ⇒ (a). Let aA,eE A and ea=fE A . Then, using (3),

$$f=f(ea)=(fe)a=(ae)f. $$

Hence aeE A . Thus aE A . □

AG-groups are examples of E-unitary completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoids.

A congruence ρ on a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid is a AG-group congruence if A/ρ is an AG-group. By Lemma 3.3, ρ is an AG-group congruence if and only if tr(ρ)=E A ×E A . Since A×A is an AG-group congruence on A, then the intersection of all the AG-group congruences on A is the least AG-group congruence on A.

A more useful characterization of the least AG-group congruence on A is given in the following theorem.

Theorem 4.5

In any completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid A,

$$\sigma=\{(a,b)\in A\times A:(\exists e\in E_A)\ ea=eb\} $$

is the least AG-group congruence with the kernel E A ω.

Proof

It is evident that σ is reflexive and symmetric. Let (a,b),(b,c)∈σ, so that ea=eb and fb=fc for some e,fE A . Using Proposition 2.1, we have that

$$(fe)a=f(ea)=f(eb)=(fe)b=(ef)b=e(fb)=e(fc)=(ef)c=(fe)c, $$

where feE A . Thus (a,c)∈σ. Consequently, σ is an equivalence relation on A. Further, let (a,b)∈σ, that is, ea=eb, where eE A , and let cA. Then again in the light of Proposition 2.1, e(ac)=(ea)c=(eb)c=e(bc). Also,

$$(cc^{-1})e\cdot ca=(cc^{-1})c \cdot ea =(cc^{-1})c \cdot eb=(cc^{-1})e \cdot cb, $$

where (cc −1)eE A . Hence σ is a congruence on A. Since (ef)e=(ef)f and efE A for all e,fE A , then σ is an AG-group congruence on A. Also, let ρ be an AG-group congruence on A and (a,b)∈σ. Then ea=eb, where eE A , so ()()=()(). Hence =, since is a left identity of the AG-group A/ρ. Thus σρ. Consequently, σ is the least AG-group congruence on A. Finally,

as required. □

From Theorem 4.2 follows that (a,b)∈σab −1E A ω. Also, in the light of the end of Sect. 5, E A ω is a closed completely inverse AG ∗∗-subgroupoid of A. Evidently, E A E A ω and if abE A ω, then baE A ω.

A nonempty subset B of a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid A is called:

  1. (F)

    full if E A B;

  2. (S)

    symmetric if xyB implies yxB for all x,yA.

A completely inverse AG ∗∗-subgroupoid N of A is said to be normal if it full, closed and symmetric. In that case, we shall write NA.

Denote the set of all AG-group congruences on a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid A by \(\mathcal{GC}(A)\). It is clear that \(\mathcal{GC}(A)=[\sigma,A\times A]\) is a complete sublattice of \(\mathcal{C}(A)\). Note that \(\mathcal{GC}(A)\cong\mathcal{C}(A/\sigma)\) and so the lattice \(\mathcal{GC}(A)\) is modular (by Corollary 3.6). Further, let \(\mathcal{N}(A)\) be the set of all normal completely inverse AG ∗∗-subgroupoids of A. It is obvious that E A ωN for every NA, and if \(\emptyset\neq \mathcal{F}\subseteq\mathcal{N}(A)\), then \(\bigcap\{B : B\in\mathcal {F}\}\in\mathcal{N}(A)\). Consequently, \(\mathcal{N}(A)\) is a complete lattice.

The following theorem (proved in [13]) describes the AG-group congruences on a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid in the terms of its normal completely inverse AG ∗∗-subgroupoids.

Theorem 4.6

Let A be a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid, NA. Then the relation

$$\rho_N=\{(a,b)\in A\times A:ab^{-1}\in N\} $$

is the unique AG-group congruence ρ on A for which ker(ρ)=N.

Conversely, if \(\rho\in\mathcal{GC}(A)\), then \(\ker(\rho)\in\mathcal {N}(A)\) and ρ=ρ N for N=ker(ρ).

Consequently, the map \(\phi:\mathcal{N}(A)\to\mathcal{GC}(A)\) given by =ρ N \((N\in\mathcal{N}(A))\) is a complete lattice isomorphism of \(\mathcal{N}(A)\) onto \(\mathcal{GC}(A)\). In particular, the lattice \(\mathcal{N}(A)\) is modular.

We say that a congruence ρ on a groupoid A is idempotent pure if E A for all eE A . Notice that any idempotent pure congruence ρ on an arbitrary completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid A is contained in σ. Indeed, if (a,b)∈ρ, then (ab −1,bb −1)∈ρ, so ab −1E A E A ω. Thus (a,b)∈σ, as required.

The following theorem gives necessary and sufficient conditions for a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid to be E-unitary.

Theorem 4.7

Let A=[E A ;G e ;ϕ e,f ] be a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid. Then the following conditions are equivalent:

  1. (a)

    A is E-unitary;

  2. (b)

    ker(σ)=E A ;

  3. (c)

    σ is the maximum idempotent pure congruence on A;

  4. (d)

    σμ=1 A ;

  5. (e)

    ϕ e,f is a monomorphism for all e,fE A such that ef.

Proof

In view of Proposition 4.4, (a) and (b) are equivalent, since ker(σ)=E A ω.

(b) ⇒ (c). This follows from the preceding remark.

(c) ⇒ (d). Indeed, tr\((\sigma\cap\mu)\subseteq\text{tr}(\mu )=1_{E_{A}}\) (by Theorem 3.4(c)). Furthermore, ker(σμ)⊆ker(σ)=E A . In the light of Theorem 4.2, σμ=1 A .

(d) ⇒ (e). Let a e ,b e G e be such that a e ϕ e,f =b e ϕ e,f . Then fa e =fb e , therefore, (a e ,b e )∈σ. Since clearly (a e ,b e )∈μ, then a e =b e .

(e) ⇒ (a). Let a f G f be such that ea f =g (e,f,gE A ). Then ef=g. Hence eg=g, that is, eg, so a f ϕ e,g = e,g , therefore, a f =gE A . Thus A is E-unitary (by Proposition 4.4). □

Let ρ,υ be congruences on A such that ρυ. Then the map Φ:A/ρA/υ, where ()Φ= for every aA, is a well-defined epimorphism between these groupoids. Denote its kernel by

$$\upsilon/\rho= \{(a\rho, b\rho)\in A/\rho\times A/\rho: (a,b)\in \upsilon\}. $$

Then (A/ρ)/(υ/ρ)≅A/υ. Moreover, every congruence α on A/ρ is of the form υ/ρ, where υρ is a congruence on A. Indeed, the relation υ, defined on A by: (a,b)∈υ if and only if (,)∈α, is a congruence on A such that ρυ and α=υ/ρ.

We are able now to determine all E-unitary congruences on any completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid.

Theorem 4.8

The intersection of an AG-group congruence and a semilattice congruence on a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid A is an E-unitary congruence on A. Moreover, any E-unitary congruence on a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid A can be expressed uniquely in this way.

Proof

Let ρ N be an AG-group congruence (NA) and υ be a semilattice congruence on A. Put for simplicity ρ=ρ N υ, and observe that ρ N /ρ is an AG-group congruence on A/ρ and υ/ρ is a semilattice congruence on A/ρ. Since ρ N /ρυ/ρ=1 A/ρ , then σ A/ρ μ A/ρ =1 A/ρ (see Theorem 3.4(a)). In the light of Theorem 4.7, ρ is an E-unitary congruence on A.

Conversely, let ρ be an E-unitary congruence on A, ρ N /ρ=σ A/ρ and let υ/ρ=μ A/ρ , where ρρ N ,υ. Then ρ N is an AG-group congruence and υ is a semilattice congruence on A. Also, (ρ N υ)/ρ=σ A/ρ μ A/ρ =1 A/ρ (again by Theorem 4.7). Thus ρ=ρ N υ, as required.

Finally, let \(\rho=\rho_{N_{1}}\cap\upsilon_{1}=\rho_{N_{2}}\cap\upsilon_{2}\), where N i A and υ i is a semilattice congruence on A (i=1,2). Let (a,b)∈υ 1. Since υ 1υ 2 is a semilattice congruence on A, then there exists e,fE A such that (a,e)∈υ 1υ 2, \((e, f)\in \rho_{N_{1}},(f, b)\in\upsilon_{1}\cap\upsilon_{2}\) (Theorem 3.2), so \((e, f)\in\upsilon_{1}\cap\rho_{N_{1}} =\upsilon_{2}\cap\rho_{N_{2}}\subseteq \upsilon_{2}\). Hence (a,b)∈υ 2, i.e., υ 1υ 2. By symmetry, we deduce that υ 1=υ 2. Put υ 1=υ 2=υ, so that \(\rho=\rho_{N_{1}}\cap \upsilon=\rho_{N_{2}}\cap\upsilon\). If \((a, b)\in\rho_{N_{1}}\), then \((aab, abb)\in\upsilon\cap\rho_{N_{1}}\subseteq\rho_{N_{2}}\), therefore, \((a, b)\in\rho_{N_{2}}\) (by cancellation). Hence \(\rho_{N_{1}}\subseteq\rho _{N_{2}}\). By symmetry, \(\rho_{N_{2}}\subseteq\rho_{N_{1}}\). Thus \(\rho _{N_{1}}=\rho_{N_{2}}\), as required. □

Corollary 4.9

In any completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid A, the relation

$$\pi=\sigma\cap\mu $$

is the least E-unitary congruence on A.

Observe that if ρ is an E-unitary congruence on A, then ker(ρ)=ker(ρ N ) for some NA. In the last section we will show that the converse implication is also true, that is, for any AG-group congruence ρ N on A (NA), the family

$$\mathcal{U}_{N}=\{\rho_N\cap\upsilon:\mu\subseteq\upsilon\} $$

coincides with the set of all (E-unitary) congruence ρ on A such that

$$\text{ker}(\rho)=\text{ker}(\rho_N). $$

Finally, denote by \(\mathcal{U}(A)\) the set of all E-unitary congruences on a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid A. Since the intersection of an arbitrary nonempty family of E-unitary congruences on A is again an E-unitary congruence on A, and \(\mathcal{U}(A)\) has a least element, then the following corollary is valid.

Corollary 4.10

Let A be a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid. Then the set \(\mathcal{U}(A)\) is a complete ∩-sublattice of \(\mathcal{C}(A)\) with the least element π and the greatest element A×A.

Moreover, \(\mathcal{U}_{N}=\{\rho_{N}\cap\upsilon:\mu\subseteq\upsilon\}\) (NA) is a complete sublattice of \(\mathcal{U}(A)\) with the least element ρ N μ and the greatest element ρ N .

In view of the corollary, for each \(\rho\in\mathcal{C}(A)\), there is the least E-unitary congruence π ρ containing ρ. We will show in Sect. 6 that π ρ =σρσμρμ.

5 The trace classes of \(\mathcal{C}(A)\)

Let ρ be a congruence on A, where A denotes (unless otherwise stated) an arbitrary completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid. Put K=ker(ρ). It is immediate that K is a full completely inverse AG ∗∗-subgroupoid of A. In the light of Proposition 4.1, K is also symmetric. Finally, put ρ (K,τ)=ρ, where τ=tr(ρ). Theorem 4.2 states that

$$ (a,b)\in\rho_{(K,\tau)}\quad\iff\quad(aa^{-1},bb^{-1})\in\tau \ \&\ ab^{-1}\in K. $$
(7)

Notice that if a∈ker(ρ (K,τ)), that is, (a,e)∈ρ (K,τ), where eE A , then

$$ea\in K \ \& \ (e,aa^{-1})\in\text{tr}(\rho_{(K,\tau)}). $$

Observe further that if eaK and (e,aa −1)∈tr(ρ), then a=(aa −1)aρea, therefore, aK.

Also, the following special case is of particular interest.

Proposition 5.1

Let A be a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid. Then \(\rho\in\mathcal{U}(A)\) if and only if ker(ρ) is closed in A.

Proof

Let \(\rho\in\mathcal{U}(A)\) and a∈(ker(ρ))ω. Then b=ea for some b∈ker(ρ) and eE A . Hence =()(), where ,E A/ρ and so E A/ρ , since A/ρ is E-unitary. Thus a∈ker(ρ). Consequently, (ker(ρ))ω=ker(ρ).

Conversely, let ()()=, where aA and e,fE A , then ea∈ker(ρ). Hence a∈(ker(ρ))ω=ker(ρ), that is, E A/ρ . Thus ρ is E-unitary. □

In Sect. 3 we have called a completely inverse AG ∗∗-subgroupoid of A normal if it is full, symmetric and closed in A. Also, we say that a completely inverse AG ∗∗-subgroupoid K is seminormal if K is full and symmetric.

Finally, for any ordered pair (K,τ), where K is a seminormal completely inverse AG ∗∗-subgroupoid of A and τ is a congruence on E A such that

(CP) if eaK and (e,aa −1)∈τ, then aK (aA,eE A ),

define a relation ρ (K,τ) like the above. In that case, (K,τ) is a congruence pair for A and we can define a relation ρ (K,τ) as in (7) above.

The following theorem together with the above consideration and Theorem 4.2 says that any congruence on A is of the form ρ (K,τ), where (K,τ) is a congruence pair for A, and this expression is unique.

Theorem 5.2

If (K,τ) is a congruence pair for a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid A, then ρ (K,τ) is the unique congruence on A with ker(ρ (K,τ))=K and tr(ρ (K,τ))=τ.

Conversely, if ρ is a congruence on A, then (ker(ρ),tr(ρ)) is a congruence pair for A and ρ (ker(ρ),tr(ρ))=ρ.

Proof

It is sufficient to show the direct part of the theorem. Put ρ=ρ (K,τ). It is clear that ρ is reflexive and symmetric. Let now (a,b),(b,c)∈ρ. Then (aa −1,cc −1)∈τ and (b −1 a)(bc −1)=(b −1 b)(ac −1)=(bb −1)(ac −1)∈K. Also,

$$bb^{-1} \tau (aa^{-1})(c^{-1}c)=(ac^{-1})(a^{-1}c)=(ac^{-1})(ac^{-1})^{-1}. $$

In the light of the condition (CP), ac −1K. Thus ρ is transitive. Let (a,b)∈ρ and cA. Then

Also,

Consequently, ρ is a congruence on A.

Finally, let a∈ker(ρ), that is, (a,e)∈ρ for some eE A . Then clearly eaK and (e,aa −1)∈τ. Hence aK (by (CP)). Thus ker(ρ)⊆K. Conversely, let aK. Then a −1K. Hence (a −1 a,a)∈ρ and so a∈ker(ρ). Thus ker(ρ)=K. Evidently, tr(ρ)=τ. In view of Theorem 4.2, ρ (K,τ) is uniquely determined by the congruence pair (K,τ). □

It is easy to see that if K is closed in A, then the condition (CP) is not necessary in the proof of the direct part of Theorem 5.2. Combining this fact with Proposition 5.1 and Theorem 4.2 we obtain the following corollary.

Corollary 5.3

Each E-unitary congruence ρ on a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid A is of the form ρ (K,τ), where KA and \(\tau\in\mathcal{C}(E_{A})\), and this expression is unique.

Remark 4

One can modify Proposition III.2.3 [11] for completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoids.

Further, let ρ be a congruence on A. Put

$$\mu(\rho)=\{(a,b)\in A\times A:(a\rho,b\rho)\in\mu_{A/\rho}\}. $$

Clearly, \(\mu(\rho)\in\mathcal{C}(A)\) and ρμ(ρ). From Theorem 3.4 follows that

$$(a,b)\in\mu(\rho)\quad\iff\quad(aa^{-1},bb^{-1})\in\rho. $$

Put μ(ρ)=ρ θ. It is clear that tr(ρ)=tr(ρ θ). Also, if tr(ρ 1)=tr(ρ 2) (\(\rho_{1},\rho_{2}\in\mathcal{C}(A)\)), then from the above equality follows that \(\rho_{1}^{\theta}=\rho_{2}^{\theta}\). Consequently, ρ θ is the maximum congruence with respect to tr(ρ). Also, put (see Theorem 4.5)

$$\rho_\theta=\{(a,b)\in A\times A:(aa^{-1},bb^{-1})\in\rho \ \& \ (\exists e\in E_{(aa^{-1})\rho})\ ea=eb\}. $$

Since a=(aa −1)a, then ρ θ is reflexive. Obviously, ρ θ is symmetric. The proof that ρ θ is transitive and left compatible is closely similar to the corresponding proof for the relation σ (see Theorem 4.5). Let (a,b)∈ρ θ and cA. Then

$$(ac)(ac)^{-1}=(ac)(a^{-1}c^{-1})=(aa^{-1})(cc^{-1}) \rho (bb^{-1})(cc^{-1})=(bc)(bc)^{-1}. $$

Also, e(cc −1)ρ(aa −1)(cc −1)=(ac)(ac)−1 and

$$e(cc^{-1})\cdot ac = ea\cdot(cc^{-1})c= eb\cdot (cc^{-1})c=e(cc^{-1})\cdot bc. $$

Consequently, ρ θ is a congruence on A. Finally, from the definition of ρ θ follows that tr(ρ)=tr(ρ θ ), and since the definition of ρ θ depends only on idempotents, then ρ θ is the minimum congruence with respect to tr(ρ).

We have just proved part of the following theorem.

Theorem 5.4

Let A be an arbitrary completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid. Define a map \(\varTheta:\mathcal{C}(A)\to \mathcal{C}(E_{A})\) by

$$\rho\varTheta=\mathrm{tr}(\rho) \quad (\rho\in\mathcal{C}(A)). $$

Then Θ is a complete lattice homomorphism of \(\mathcal{C}(A)\) onto \(\mathcal{C}(E_{A})\). Also, if θ denotes the congruence on \(\mathcal{C}(A)\) induced by Θ, that is,

$$\theta=\{(\rho_1,\rho_2)\in\mathcal{C}(A)\times\mathcal{C}(A):\mathrm{tr}(\rho_1)=\mathrm{tr}(\rho_2)\}, $$

then for every \(\rho\in\mathcal{C}(A)\),

$$\rho\theta=[\rho_\theta,\rho^\theta] $$

is a complete modular sublattice (with commuting elements) of \(\mathcal{C}(A)\).

Proof

The proof that Θ is a complete homomorphism is closely similar to the corresponding proof of Theorem III.2.5 [11], since the join of any nonempty family \(\mathcal{F}\) of congruences in an arbitrary universal algebra is given by \(\bigcup _{n\in\mathbb{N}}(\bigcup\mathcal{F})^{n}\). Further, let τ be a congruence on E A . Define an equivalence relation ρ on A by

$$\rho=\{(a,b)\in A\times A:(aa^{-1},bb^{-1})\in\tau\}. $$

It is easy to check that ρ is compatible with the operation on A. Consequently, \(\rho\in\mathcal{C}(A)\). Obviously, tr(ρ)=τ. Thus Θ maps \(\mathcal{C}(A)\) onto \(\mathcal{C}(E_{A})\).

Finally, ρθ is an interval of a complete lattice, so it is itself a complete lattice. Let ρ 1,ρ 2ρθ and a(ρ 1 ρ 2)b. Then 1 2 b, where cA, so (aa −1)ρ 1(cc −1)ρ 2(bb −1). Hence (aa −1)ρ 2(cc −1)ρ 1(bb −1), since tr(ρ 1)=tr(ρ 2). Moreover, (cc −1)ρ 2(bc −1). It follows that (aa −1)ρ 2(bc −1). Consequently,

$$a=(aa^{-1}\cdot a)\rho_2(bc^{-1}\cdot a)=(ac^{-1})b. $$

Further, (ac −1)ρ 1(cc −1) and so (ac −1)ρ 1(bb −1). Hence (ac −1b)ρ 1(bb −1b)=b. We have just shown that 2(ac −1b)ρ 1 b, that is, ρ 1 ρ 2ρ 2 ρ 1. By symmetry, we deduce that ρ 1 ρ 2=ρ 2 ρ 1, therefore, the lattice ρθ is modular. □

We call the classes of θ in the above theorem, the trace classes of A.

Lemma 5.5

Let A be a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid. Then

$$\rho_\theta\subseteq\gamma_\theta\quad\iff\quad\mathrm{tr}(\rho)\subseteq\mathrm{tr}(\gamma)\quad\iff\quad\rho^\theta\subseteq\gamma^\theta $$

for all \(\rho,\gamma\in\mathcal{C}(A)\). Also, if ργ, then ρ θ γ θ and ρ θγ θ.

Proof

This follows directly from the definitions of ρ θ and ρ θ. □

Lemma 5.6

Let \(\mathcal{F}\) be an arbitrary nonempty family of congruences on a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid. Put

$$\mathcal{F}_\theta=\{\rho_\theta:\rho\in\mathcal{F}\}, \quad\quad \mathcal {F}^\theta=\{\rho^\theta:\rho\in\mathcal{F}\}. $$

Then

$$\bigvee\mathcal{F}_\theta=\Big(\bigvee\mathcal{F}\Big)_\theta \quad\& \quad\bigcap\mathcal{F}^\theta=\Big(\bigcap\mathcal{F}\Big )^\theta. $$

Proof

The proof is similar to the proof of Lemma III.2.9 [11]. □

Lemma 5.7

Let A a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid. Then σ=(A×A) θ .

Proof

This is obvious. □

The following corollary gives another equivalent conditions for a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid to be E-unitary.

Corollary 5.8

Let A be a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid. The following conditions are equivalent:

  1. (a)

    A is E-unitary;

  2. (b)

    ρ θ =ρσ for every \(\rho\in\mathcal{C}(A)\);

  3. (c)

    ρ θ is an idempotent pure congruence on A for every \(\rho\in\mathcal{C}(A)\).

Proof

Recall that A is E-unitary if and only if σ is the maximum idempotent pure congruence on A (Theorem 4.7).

(a) ⇒ (b). If \(\rho\in\mathcal{C}(A)\), then ρ θ ρ∩(A×A) θ =ρσ (Lemmas 5.5, 5.7). On the other hand,

$$\text{tr}(\rho\cap\sigma)=\text{tr}(\rho)\cap\text{tr}(\sigma)=\text {tr}(\rho)\cap(E_A\times E_A)=\text{tr}(\rho)=\text{tr}(\rho_\theta) $$

and

$$\text{ker}(\rho\cap\sigma)=\text{ker}(\rho)\cap\text{ker}(\sigma)=\text {ker}(\rho)\cap E_A=E_A\subseteq\text{ker}(\rho_\theta). $$

Thus ρσρ θ (Theorem 4.2). Consequently, ρ θ =ρσ.

(b) ⇒ (a). Clearly, μ θ =1 A . Moreover, μ θ =μσ=π (Corollary 4.9), therefore, π=1 A , so A is E-unitary.

It is now clear that (a) implies (c). We show the opposite implication. Indeed, if (c) holds, then (A×A) θ =σ is idempotent pure. Since ρ θ σ for every \(\rho \in\mathcal{C}(A)\), then each ρ θ is idempotent pure, too, as required. □

We have mentioned in the above proof that if A is E-unitary, then σ is the maximum idempotent pure congruence on A, therefore, the set of all idempotent pure congruences [1 A ,σ] on an E-unitary completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid A forms a complete sublattice of the lattice \(\mathcal{C}(A)\).

From the above corollary we obtain the following proposition.

Proposition 5.9

Let A be an E-unitary completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid. Then the mapping \(\chi:\mathcal{C}(A)\to \mathcal{C}(A)\) defined by

$$\rho\chi=\rho\cap\sigma \quad(\rho\in\mathcal{C}(A)) $$

is a complete lattice homomorphism of \(\mathcal{C}(A)\) onto the lattice of all idempotent pure congruences on A.

Proof

In view of Corollary 5.8, ρ θ =ρσ for every \(\rho\in\mathcal{C}(A)\). Hence χ is a complete ∨-homomorphism (by Lemma 5.6). It is evident that χ is a complete ∩-homomorphism. Finally, if ρ is idempotent pure, then ρσ and so ρχ=ρ. Thus χ maps \(\mathcal{C}(A)\) onto the lattice of all idempotent pure congruences on A, as exactly required. □

We now investigate the θ-classes of A.

Lemma 5.10

In any completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid A, μ A/ρ =μ(ρ)/ρ for every \(\rho\in\mathcal {C}(A)\). In particular, [ρ/ρ,ρ θ/ρ] is the modular lattice of all idempotent-separating congruences on A/ρ \((\rho\in \mathcal{C}(A))\).

Proof

It is easy to see that μ(ρ)/ρ is idempotent-separating, so μ(ρ)/ρμ A/ρ . On the other hand, if γ/ρ, where ργ, is an idempotent-separating congruence on A/ρ, then tr(γ)⊆tr(ρ) and so tr(γ)=tr(ρ). Hence ργμ(ρ), therefore, γ/ρμ(ρ)/ρ. Thus μ A/ρ =μ(ρ)/ρ. The second part of the lemma follows from Theorem 3.5. □

The following theorem follows easily from the above lemma.

Theorem 5.11

Let A be a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid, \(\rho\in\mathcal{C}(A)\). Define a map ϕ:[ρ θ ,ρ θ]→A/ρ θ by ρϕ=ρ/ρ θ for all ρ∈[ρ θ ,ρ θ]. Then ϕ is a complete isomorphism of the trace class [ρ θ ,ρ θ] onto the modular lattice of all idempotent-separating congruences on A/ρ θ .

Remark 5

Note that ϕ |[γ,μ(ρ)], where γρθ, is a complete isomorphism of the interval [γ,μ(ρ)] onto the lattice of all idempotent-separating congruences on A/γ.

Recall that A is fundamental if and only if μ=1 A . By the above remark we have the following corollary.

Corollary 5.12

Let ρ be a congruence on a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid A. Then A/ρ is fundamental if and only if ρ=μ(ρ).

Denote by \(\mathcal{FC}(A)\) the set of all fundamental congruences on A, that is,

$$\mathcal{FC}(A)=\{\mu(\rho):\rho\in\mathcal{C}(A)\}. $$

Since 1 A ρ, then μ=μ(1 A )⊆μ(ρ) for all \(\rho\in\mathcal{C}(A)\), what means that μ is the least fundamental congruence on A. Also, from Lemma 5.6 follows that \(\mathcal {FC}(A)\) is a complete ∩-sublattice of \(\mathcal{C}(A)\).

We have just proved a part of the following theorem.

Theorem 5.13

Let A be a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid. Then \(\mathcal{FC}(A)\) is a complete ∩-sublattice of \(\mathcal{C}(A)\) with the least element μ and the greatest element A×A. For any nonempty family {ρ i :iI} of fundamental congruences on A, the join of {ρ i :iI} in \(\mathcal{FC}(A)\) is given by μ(⋁{ρ i :iI}). Also, \(\mathcal{FC}(A)\cong\mathcal{C}(E_{A})\).

Proof

Let \(\emptyset\not=\{\rho_{i}: i\in I\}\subseteq\mathcal {FC}(A)\). Then

$$\Big(\bigvee\{\rho_i: i\in I\}, \mu\Big(\bigvee\{\rho_i: i\in I\}\Big )\Big)\in\theta. $$

On the other hand, if ρ∈[⋁{ρ i :iI},μ(⋁{ρ i :iI})], then μ(ρ)=ρ if and only if ρ=μ(⋁{ρ i :iI}). Consequently, μ(⋁{ρ i :iI}) is the join of {ρ i :iI} in \(\mathcal{F}(S)\).

Finally, if μ(ρ 1)≠μ(ρ 2), where \(\rho_{1},\rho_{2}\in \mathcal{C}(A)\), then tr(ρ 1)≠tr(ρ 2), therefore, the restriction of the map Θ from Theorem 5.4 to the set \(\mathcal{FC}(A)\) is the required complete lattice isomorphism. □

6 The kernel classes of \(\mathcal{C}(A)\)

Let A be an AG ∗∗-groupoid. For every nonempty subset Q of A there exists an associated equivalence relation \(\mathcal{Q}\) on A which is induced by the partition: {Q,AQ}. Define on A an equivalence relation τ Q by

$$\tau^Q=\{(a,b)\in A\times A:(\forall x,y\in A^{1}) x(ay)\in Q\iff x(by)\in Q\}, $$

where A 1=A∪{1}, \(1\not\in A\) and 1a=a1=a for all aA.

Observe that if (a,b)∈τ Q, then putting x=y=1 in the definition of τ Q, we obtain that either a,bQ or a,bQ. Thus \(\tau^{Q}\subseteq\mathcal{Q}\).

Proposition 6.1

Let Q be a nonempty subset of an AG ∗∗-groupoid A. Then τ Q is the largest congruence ρ on A for which Q is the union of some ρ-classes.

Proof

Let (a,b)∈τ Q,x,yA 1 and cA. Observe that

$$x(ac\cdot y)=(ac)(xy)=(xy\cdot c)a. $$

Hence if x(acy)∈Q, then (xyc)bQ, since (a,b)∈τ Q. Thus we get x(bcy)∈Q. By symmetry, we conclude that τ Q is right compatible. Further, the equality

$$x(ca\cdot y)=(ca)(xy)=(cx)(ay) $$

implies that τ Q is also left compatible. Consequently, τ Q is a congruence on A and Q is the union of some τ Q-classes, since \(\tau^{Q}\subseteq\mathcal{Q}\). Finally, if ρ is any congruence on A for which Q is the union of some ρ-classes, then \(\rho\subseteq\mathcal{Q}\). Hence if (a,b)∈ρ, then either a,bQ or a,bQ. Thus for all x,yA 1, x(ay)∈Qx(by)∈Q, so Q b. Consequently, ρτ Q. □

Corollary 6.2

In any completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid A, the relation \(\tau^{E_{A}}\) is the largest idempotent pure congruence on A.

We shall write τ instead of \(\tau^{E_{A}}\), or τ A if necessary.

Let ρ be a congruence on A, where A denotes (unless otherwise stated) an arbitrary completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid. Put

$$\tau(\rho)=\{(a,b)\in A\times A:(a\rho,b\rho)\in\tau_{A/\rho}\}. $$

Clearly, \(\tau(\rho)\in\mathcal{C}(A)\) and ρτ(ρ). Using Theorem 3.2, one can prove without difficulty that τ(ρ)=τ ker(ρ). Thus τ(ρ) is the maximum congruence with respect to ker(ρ). Denote it by ρ κ.

Further, put ρ κ =ρμ. Then ker(ρ κ )=ker(ρ), since μ is a semilattice congruence. On the other hand, μ is idempotent-separating, so ρ κ is the minimum congruence with respect to ker(ρ).

Finally if K is a seminormal completely inverse AG ∗∗-subgroupoid of A. Then the pair \((K,1_{E_{A}})\) is a congruence pair for A, since then the condition (CP) is trivially met for this pair, and \(\text {ker}(\rho_{(K,1_{E_{A}})})=K\). Consequently, K is seminormal if and only if K is a kernel of some congruence on A. Denote by \(\mathcal {SN}(A)\) the set of seminormal completely inverse AG ∗∗-subgroupoids of A. It is easy to see that \(\mathcal{SN}(A)\) is a lattice under inclusion.

It is clear that if \(\emptyset\not=\{\rho_{i}: i\in I\}\subseteq\mathcal {C}(A)\), then

$$\text{ker}\Big(\bigcap\{\rho_i:i\in I\}\Big)=\bigcap\{\text{ker}(\rho _i):i\in I\}, $$

therefore, we have just proved the following theorem.

Theorem 6.3

Let A be an arbitrary completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid. Define a map \(K:\mathcal{C}(A)\to\mathcal {P}(A)\) by

$$\rho K=\operatorname{ker}(\rho) \quad(\rho\in\mathcal{C}(A)). $$

Then K is a complete lattice ∩-homomorphism of \(\mathcal{C}(A)\) onto \(\mathcal{SN}(A)\). Also, if κ denotes the ∩-congruence on \(\mathcal{C}(A)\) induced by K, that is,

$$\kappa=\{(\rho_1,\rho_2)\in\mathcal{C}(A)\times\mathcal{C}(A):\ker(\rho _1)=\ker(\rho_2)\}, $$

then for ever \(\rho\in\mathcal{C}(A)\),

$$\rho\kappa=[\rho_\kappa,\rho^\kappa] $$

is a complete sublattice of \(\mathcal{C}(A)\).

We call the classes of κ in the above theorem, the kernel classes of A.

Example 6.4

The following example shows that ker(ρ)⊆ker(γ) (or even ργ) does not imply (in general) that ρ κγ κ. Indeed, let A={a,b,e,f} be a commutative inverse semigroup with the multiplication table given below:

Then clearly 1 A ρ=1 A ∪{(a,e),(e,a)}. On the other hand, ρ κ=ρ∪{(b,f),(f,b)} and \(1_{A}^{\kappa}= 1_{A} \cup\{(e, f), (f, e), (a, b), (b, a)\}\) and so \(1_{A}^{\kappa}= \tau\nsubseteq\rho^{\kappa}= \tau(\rho)\). Notice also that ττ(ρ)=1 A .

Using Theorem 4.2 one can easily prove the following proposition.

Proposition 6.5

If ρ is a congruence on a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid, then

$$\rho=\rho_\theta\vee\rho_\kappa=\rho^\theta\cap\rho^\kappa. $$

We now investigate the κ-classes of A.

Lemma 6.6

In any completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid A, τ A/ρ =τ(ρ)/ρ for every \(\rho \in\mathcal{C}(A)\). In particular, [ρ/ρ,ρ κ/ρ] is the lattice of all idempotent pure congruences on A/ρ \((\rho\in \mathcal{C}(A))\).

Proof

One can easily see that τ(ρ)/ρ is idempotent pure and so τ(ρ)/ρτ A/ρ . On the other hand, if γ/ρ, where ργ, is idempotent pure, then ker(γ)⊆ker(ρ), therefore, ker(γ)=ker(ρ). Hence ργτ(ρ), so γ/ρτ(ρ)/ρ. Consequently, τ A/ρ =τ(ρ)/ρ. □

From the above lemma follows the following theorem.

Theorem 6.7

Let A be a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid, \(\rho\in\mathcal{C}(A)\). Define a map ϕ:[ρ κ ,ρ κ]→A/ρ κ by ρϕ=ρ/ρ κ for all ρ∈[ρ κ ,ρ κ]. Then ϕ is a complete isomorphism of the kernel class [ρ κ ,ρ κ] onto the lattice of all idempotent pure congruences on A/ρ κ .

Note that ϕ |[γ,τ(ρ)], where γρκ, is a complete isomorphism of the interval [γ,τ(ρ)] onto the lattice of all idempotent pure congruences on A/γ.

Recall that A is E-disjunctive if and only if τ=1 A . By the above remark we have the following corollary.

Corollary 6.8

Let ρ be a congruence on a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid A. Then A/ρ is E-disjunctive if and only if ρ=τ(ρ).

Remark 6

Note that in view of the end of Example 6.4, the set of all E-disjunctive congruences on a commutative inverse semigroup (in particular, on a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid) A does not form (in general) a sublattice of \(\mathcal{C}(A)\).

Also, a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid A is an AG-group if and only if A is both E-unitary and E-disjunctive.

Finally, notice that a congruence ρ on A is idempotent pure if and only if ρμ=1 A . In particular, τμ=1 A , therefore, A is a subdirect product of A/τ and E A , where A/τ is an E-disjunctive completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid.

Finally, we go back to study the lattice \(\mathcal{U}(A)\) of all E-unitary congruences on a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid A. First, we prove the following useful result.

Lemma 6.9

The following conditions are valid for a congruence ρ on a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid A:

  1. (a)

    ρσ=σρσ;

  2. (b)

    a(ρσ)b⇔(ea)ρ(eb) for some eE A ;

  3. (c)

    ker(ρσ)=(ker(ρ))ω.

Proof

Using Proposition 2.1, we may show, in a very similar way like in the proof of Lemma III.5.4(i) [11], the condition (a). Furthermore, the condition (b) follows directly from Proposition 2.1 and (a). Finally, the proof of (c) is closely similar to the corresponding proof of Corollary III.5.5 [11]. □

Using Proposition 2.1 and Lemma 6.9(b), we are able to show the following theorem.

Theorem 6.10

Let A be an arbitrary completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid. Then the map \(\phi:\mathcal{C}(A)\to\mathcal{C}(A)\) defined by

$$\rho\phi=\rho\vee\sigma $$

is a homomorphism of \(\mathcal{C}(A)\) onto the lattice [σ,A×A] of all AG-group congruences on A.

Define the relation \(\bar{\sigma}\) on \(\mathcal{C}(A)\) by putting

$$(\rho_1, \rho_2) \in\bar{\sigma}\quad\iff\quad\rho_1\vee\sigma= \rho _2 \vee\sigma. $$

In the light of the above theorem, \(\bar{\sigma}\) is a congruence on \(\mathcal{C}(A)\), since \(\phi\phi^{- 1} = \bar{\sigma}\).

Proposition 6.11

Let A be a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid and \(\rho\in\mathcal{C}(A)\). Then the elements ρ,π ρ and ρσ are \(\bar{\sigma}\)-equivalent and ρπ ρ ρσ. Moreover, the element ρσ is the largest in the \(\bar{\sigma}\)-class \(\rho\bar{\sigma}\).

Proof

Since π ρ is the least E-unitary congruence containing ρ and ρσ is E-unitary, then ρπ ρ ρσ. Hence we get ρσπ ρ σρσ, so ρσ=π ρ σ, therefore, \((\rho, \pi_{\rho}) \in\bar{\sigma}\). Evidently, \((\rho, \rho\vee\sigma) \in \bar{\sigma}\). This implies the first part of the proposition. The second part is clear. □

Further, let a,bA and \(\rho\in\mathcal{C}(A)\). If (a,b)∈σ, then evidently ()σ() in S/ρ. If in addition, ρσ, then ()σ() in S/ρ implies that (a,b)∈σ in S. It follows that A/σ≅(A/ρ)/σ, i.e., A and A/ρ have isomorphic maximal AG-group homomorphic images. In that case, we may say that ρ preserves the maximal AG-group homomorphic images. Since for every \(\rho\in\mathcal{C}(A)\) we have ρ θ ρ, then we obtain the following factorization:

$$A\to A/\rho_\theta\to A/\rho\cong(A/\rho_\theta)/(\rho/\rho_\theta). $$

Using the obvious terminology, we have the following proposition.

Proposition 6.12

Every homomorphism of completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoids can be factored into a homomorphism preserving the maximal AG-group homomorphic images and an idempotent-separating homomorphism.

Proof

The proof is similar to the proof of Proposition III.5.10 [11]. □

The following theorem gives another equivalent conditions for a congruence to be E-unitary (cf. the end of Sect. 4).

Theorem 6.13

Let ρ be a congruence on a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid A. Then the following conditions are equivalent:

  1. (a)

    ρ is E-unitary;

  2. (b)

    ker(ρ) is closed;

  3. (c)

    ker(ρ)=ker(ρσ);

  4. (d)

    ρσ=τ(ρ);

  5. (e)

    \(\tau(\rho)\in\mathcal{GC}(A)\).

Proof

In the light of Proposition 5.1, (a) and (b) are equivalent.

(b) ⇒ (c). This follows from Lemma 6.9(c).

(c) ⇒ (d). Indeed, ker(τ(ρ))=ker(ρ)=ker(ρσ) and so ρστ(ρ), therefore, \(\tau(\rho)\in\mathcal{GC}(A)\).

(d) ⇒ (a). Let \(\tau(\rho)\in\mathcal{GC}(A)\). Then τ(ρ) is E-unitary. Since the conditions (a) and (b) are equivalent, we get ker(ρ)=ker(τ(ρ)) is closed. Thus ρ is E-unitary.

(c) ⇒ (d). By the above ρστ(ρ) and so \(\rho\lor\sigma, \tau(\rho)\in\mathcal{GC}(S)\). Furthermore, ker(τ(ρ))=ker(ρ)=ker(ρσ). Hence ρσ=τ(ρ) (by Theorem 4.6).

(d) ⇒ (e). This is trivial. □

In view of the above theorem, Theorem 6.3 and Corollary 4.10,

$$\rho_N\kappa=\{\rho_N\cap\nu:\mu\subseteq\nu\}=[\rho_N\cap\mu,\rho_N] $$

for every NA. Consequently,

$$\mathcal{U}(A)=\bigcup_{N\lhd A}\{\rho_N\cap \nu:\mu\subseteq\nu\}. $$

Thus we have the following statement (see the end of Sect. 4).

Proposition 6.14

Let ρ be a congruence on a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid A. Then:

  1. (a)

    ρμ=μρμ;

  2. (b)

    a(ρμ)b⇔(aa −1)ρ(bb −1);

  3. (c)

    π ρ =σρσμρμ.

Proof

(a) It is clear that μρμρμ is a reflexive, symmetric and compatible relation on A. We show that it is also transitive. Let a(μρμ)b(μρμ)c. Then there exist elements r,s,t,wA such that

Also, (rr −1)ρ(ss −1)=(tt −1)ρ(ww −1). Consequently,

$$a \mu(aa^{-1})=(rr^{-1})\rho(ww^{-1})=(cc^{-1})\mu c. $$

Hence (a,c)∈μρμ, as required, and so μρμ is a congruence on A contained in ρμ. Since evidently ρ,μμρμ, then (a) holds.

(b) (⟹) Let a(ρμ)b. Then by (a), aa −1=cc −1,(c,d)∈ρ and dd −1=bb −1 for some c,dA. Hence (cc −1)ρ(dd −1). Thus (aa −1)ρ(bb −1).

(⟸) If (aa −1)ρ(bb −1), then (aa −1)ρ(bb −1)μb. Thus a(ρμ)b.

(c) In the light of Lemma 6.9 (a) and the condition (b), α=σρσμρμ is a congruence on A. It is evident that ρα and ker(α)= ker(σρσ), therefore, α is an E-unitary congruence on A which contains ρ. Finally, let \(\rho \subseteq\beta=\rho_{N}\cap\nu\in\mathcal{U}(A)\), where NA and μν. Then ρσρ N σ=ρ N and ρμνμ=ν. It follows that αρ N ν=β, as required. □

Using the condition (b) one can prove the following theorem.

Theorem 6.15

Let A be an arbitrary completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid. Then the map \(\phi:\mathcal{C}(A)\to\mathcal{C}(A)\) defined by

$$\rho\phi=\rho\vee\mu $$

is a homomorphism of \(\mathcal{C}(A)\) onto the lattice [μ,A×A] of semilattice congruences on A.

Let \(\rho\in\mathcal{C}(A)\). Since ρA×A, then there is the least semilattice congruence μ ρ containing ρ (note that μ ρ =π ρ , see the proof of Proposition 6.14(c)).

Define the relation \(\overline{\mu}\) on \(\mathcal{C}(A)\) by putting

$$(\rho_1, \rho_2) \in\overline{\mu}\quad\iff\quad\rho_1\vee\mu= \rho _2 \vee\mu. $$

In view of the above theorem, \(\overline{\mu}\) is a congruence on \(\mathcal{C}(A)\).

Proposition 6.16

Let A be a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid, \(\rho\in\mathcal{C}(A)\). Then the elements ρ,μ ρ and ρμ are \(\overline{\mu}\)-equivalent and ρμ ρ ρμ. Moreover, the element ρμ is the largest in the \(\overline{\mu}\)-class \(\rho\overline{\mu}\).

Also, let a,bA and \(\rho\in\mathcal{C}(A)\). If (a,b)∈μ, then clearly ()μ() in S/ρ. If in addition, ρμ, then ()μ() in S/ρ implies that (a,b)∈μ, since μ is idempotent-separating. It follows that A/μ≅(A/ρ)/μ, that is, A and A/ρ have isomorphic minimal idempotent-separating homomorphic images. We may say that ρ preserves the minimal idempotent-separating homomorphic images. Since for all \(\rho\in\mathcal{C}(A)\), ρ κ ρ, then we have the following factorization:

$$A\to A/\rho_\kappa\to A/\rho\cong(A/\rho_\kappa)/(\rho/\rho_\kappa). $$

We get the following proposition.

Proposition 6.17

Every homomorphism of completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoids can be factored into a homomorphism preserving the minimal idempotent-separating homomorphic images and an idempotent pure homomorphism.

Proof

Let ρ be a congruence on a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid A. Then obviously ρ κ μ, and hence the canonical homomorphism of A onto A/ρ κ preserves the minimal idempotent-separating homomorphic images. Also, the mapping κ (aA) is an idempotent pure homomorphism of A/ρ κ onto A/ρ, since ker(ρ)=ker(ρ κ ). The thesis of the proposition follows now from the above factorization. □

Since μ is also the least semilattice congruence on A (Theorem 3.4), then we may replace in the above proposition the words “minimal idempotent-separating” by the words “maximal semilattice”.

Once again we prove some equivalent conditions for A to be E-unitary.

Theorem 6.18

Let A be a completely inverse AG ∗∗-groupoid. The following conditions are equivalent:

  1. (a)

    A is E-unitary;

  2. (b)

    σ=τ;

  3. (c)

    every idempotent pure congruence on A is E-unitary;

  4. (d)

    there exists an idempotent pure E-unitary congruence on A;

  5. (e)

    τ is E-unitary.

Proof

(a) ⇒ (b). Let π=1 A . Then σ=τ(π)=τ(1 A )=τ.

(b) ⇒ (a). Let σ=τ. Then π=σ κ =τ κ =1 A .

(a) ⇒ (c). Firstly, A/τ is E-unitary. Indeed, if ()()=E A/τ , where aA and e,fE A , then (ea,f)∈τ. Hence eaE A . Thus aE A . Secondly, if \(\rho\in\mathcal{C}(A)\) is idempotent pure, then ρτ. Consequently, ρ is E-unitary.

(c) ⇒ (d). Obvious.

(d) ⇒ (e). If ρ is an idempotent pure E-unitary congruence on A, then we get πρτσ, so τ is E-unitary (Theorem 6.13).

(e) ⇒ (a). Let ea=f, where aA and e,fE A . Then ()()= and so a∈ker(τ)=E A . Thus S is E-unitary. □