Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

The cognitive neuroscience revolution

  • S.I. : Neuroscience and Its Philosophy
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We outline a framework of multilevel neurocognitive mechanisms that incorporates representation and computation. We argue that paradigmatic explanations in cognitive neuroscience fit this framework and thus that cognitive neuroscience constitutes a revolutionary break from traditional cognitive science. Whereas traditional cognitive scientific explanations were supposed to be distinct and autonomous from mechanistic explanations, neurocognitive explanations aim to be mechanistic through and through. Neurocognitive explanations aim to integrate computational and representational functions and structures across multiple levels of organization in order to explain cognition. To a large extent, practicing cognitive neuroscientists have already accepted this shift, but philosophical theory has not fully acknowledged and appreciated its significance. As a result, the explanatory framework underlying cognitive neuroscience has remained largely implicit. We explicate this framework and demonstrate its contrast with previous approaches.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Daugman (1990) for more detailed discussion of the role of technology and metaphor in the study of the human mind and body.

  2. A computer is universal just in case it can compute any computable function until it runs out of memory and time. A computer is program-controlled just in case it computes different functions depending on which program it executes. Contemporary digital computers are both universal and program-controlled. Different kinds of analogies may be drawn between digital computers and brains, some of which are stronger than others (cf. Piccinini 2008, Sect. 5 for a more detailed discussion). At the same time, it was widely recognized that there are significant architectural and performance differences between artificial digital computers and natural cognitive systems.

  3. Some argue that at least some explanations in cognitive neuroscience are not mechanistic but are instead “dynamical” (e.g., Chemero and Silberstein 2008). We lack the space to discuss this putative alternative to mechanistic explanation, except to point out that mechanistic explanations are often dynamical in the relevant sense (cf. Bechtel and Abrahamsen 2013) and thus are consistent with describing the dynamics of a system, whereas dynamical descriptions may or may not be explanatory in the relevant sense (cf. Kaplan and Craver 2011).

  4. A recent example: “My key claim is that the use of the term ‘normalization’ in neuroscience retains much of its original mathematical-engineering sense. It indicates a mathematical operation—a computation—not a biological mechanism” (Chirimuuta 2014, p. 124). Chirimuuta also cites some neuroscientists who draw a similar contrast between computations and mechanisms.

  5. Not all mathematical models in cognitive neuroscience ascribe computations to the nervous system; only those that explain phenomena through computations performed by the target systems do so.

  6. In fairness to the critics, some mechanists may give the impression of advocating such a view: “the more accurate and detailed the model is for a target system or phenomenon the better it explains that phenomenon, all other things being equal” (Kaplan 2011, p. 347). Kaplan points out that some details may be omitted from a model either for reasons of computational tractability or because they are unknown. Similarly, Craver writes: “Between sketches and complete descriptions lies a continuum of mechanism schemata whose working is only partially understood” (Craver 2007, p. 114). To drive this point home, Craver aligns the sketch-schema-mechanism axis with the epistemic axis of “how possibly-plausibly-actually”: “Progress in building mechanistic explanations involves movement along both the possibly-plausibly-actually axis and along the sketch-schema-mechanism axis” (Craver 2007, p. 114). Contrary to what Craver appears to imply, progress may consist in abstracting away from irrelevant details to construct an appropriate schema, and in some epistemic contexts even a mechanism sketch may provide all the explanatory information that is needed (more on this in this section). And in fairness to Craver and Kaplan, we should note that there are also passages where they accept that abstraction and idealization play legitimate roles in explanation.

  7. Issues related to tractability and solubility of mathematical models quickly get into deeper philosophical water than can be adequately treated here. Such issues spread across most domains of scientific inquiry. For instance, foundational work in continuum mechanics—i.e. the Navier–Stokes equations—developed around failures to model the flows of fluids through containers as trajectories of point particles; rather, the Navier–Stokes equations describe velocity fields at given points in space and time (see Batterman 2013 for an extended discussion). The extent to which the successes of these “top-down” modeling strategies can be treated merely as idealizations and approximations rather than reflecting more fundamental differences in the phenomena under investigation and our understanding of those phenomena at different levels of analysis is currently a topic of rich philosophical debate.

  8. This is not to say that all analyses of neural computation or information-processing are mechanistic. Some focus only on the information content and efficiency of a neural code without saying anything about the processing mechanisms (Dayan and Abbott 2001, xiii; Chirimuuta 2014, p. 143ff). These models are not especially relevant here because they do not provide the kind of constitutive explanations that are the present topic, and that functional analysis and mechanistic explanation are competing accounts of.

  9. Bechtel and Shagrir (forthcoming) is a good entry into the extensive literature on Marr’s levels, including how they might fit within a mechanistic framework. We cannot do justice to that debate here.

  10. This point is reminiscent of Lycan’s underappreciated critique of “two-levelism” (Lycan 1990). But Lycan lacked the accounts of mechanistic explanation and computational explanation that have been developed in detail in the past decade, and that provide the foundation that we are building upon.

  11. Here we depart from Craver (2007, pp. 212ff.), who distinguishes between levels of mechanistic organization and levels of realization. Craver adopts the view that realization is a relation between two properties of one and the same whole system, not to be confused with the relation that holds between levels of mechanistic organization. (According to Craver, as according to us, levels of mechanistic organization are systems of components, their capacities, and their organizational relations, and they are related compositionally to other levels of mechanistic organization.) We reject the account of realization adopted by Craver; we hold that each level of mechanistic organization realizes the mechanistic level above it and is realized by the mechanistic level below it (Piccinini and Maley 2014). Realization, in its most useful sense, is precisely the relation that obtains between two adjacent mechanistic levels in a multi-level mechanism and is thus a compositional relation.

  12. The purely biophysical level is reached when our explanation of the processes no longer appeals solely to differences between different portions of the vehicles along relevant dimensions of variation—which in the case of neural vehicles are mostly spike frequency and timing—in favor of the specific biophysical properties of neurons, such as the flow of specific ions through their cell membranes.

  13. We are not committed to the adequacy of this particular explanation of visual processing, just to its exemplifying the explanatory strategy of iterated computational mechanisms that we are explicating here.

References

  • Anderson, J. R. (1978). Arguments concerning representations for mental imagery. Psychological Review, 85, 249–277.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, J. R. (1983). The architecture of cognition. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, J. R. (1993). Rules of the mind. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Attneave, F. (1961). In defense of homunculi. In W. Rosenblith (Ed.), Sensory communication (pp. 777–782). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barberis, S. D. (2013). Functional analyses, mechanistic explanations, and explanatory tradeoffs. Journal of Cognitive Science, 14(3), 229–251.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barrett, D. (2014). Functional analysis and mechanistic explanation. Synthese. doi:10.1007/s11229-014-0410-9.

  • Batterman, R. (2013). The tyranny of scales. In R. W. Batterman (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy of physics (pp. 255–286). New York: oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. (2015). Investigating neural representations: The tale of place cells. Synthese.

  • Bechtel, W. (2001). Cognitive neuroscience: Relating neural mechanisms and cognition. In P. Machamer, P. McLaughlin, & R. Grush (Eds.), Philosophical reflections on the methods of neuroscience. Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. (2008). Mental mechanisms: Philosophical Perspectives on cognitive neuroscience. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., & Abrahamsen, A. (2013). Thinking dynamically about biological mechanisms: Networks of coupled oscillators. Foundations of Science, 18, 707–723.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., & Shagrir, O. (forthcoming). The non-redundant contributions of Marr’s three levels of analysis for explaining information processing mechanisms. Topics in Cognitive Science.

  • Bickle, J. (2003). Philosophy and neuroscience: A ruthlessly reductive account. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bickle, J. (2006). Reducing mind to molecular pathways: Explicating the reductionism implicit in current cellular and molecular neuroscience. Synthese, 151, 411–434.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bogen, J. (2005). Regularities and causality: Generalizations and causal explanations. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 36, 397–420.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boone, W., & Piccinini, G. (unpublished). Mechanistic abstraction.

  • Burge, T. (2010). Origins of objectivity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Caianiello, E. R. (1961). Outline of a theory of thought processes and thinking machines. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 1(2), 204–235.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chemero, A., & Silberstein, M. (2008). After the philosophy of mind: Replacing scholasticism with science. Philosophy of Science, 75, 1–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chirimuuta, M. (2014). Minimal models and canonical neural computations: The distinctness of computational explanation in neuroscience. Synthese, 191(2), 127–154.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. M. (1981). Eliminative materialism and the propositional attitudes. Journal of Philosophy, 78, 67–90.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. S. (1986). Neurophilosophy: Toward a unified science of the mind/brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. (2007). Explaining the brain: Mechanisms and the mosaic unity of neuroscience. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, R. (1983). The nature of psychological explanation. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, R. (2000). ‘How does it work?’ vs. ‘What are the laws?’ Two conceptions of psychological explanation. In K. F. C. & W. R. A. (Eds.), Explanation and cognition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Daugman, J. G. (1990). Brain metaphor and brain theory. In E. L. Schwartz (Ed.), Computational neuroscience (pp. 9–18). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dayan, P., & Abbott, L. F. (2001). Theoretical neuroscience: Computational and mathematical modeling of neural systems. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  • Dennett, D. C. (1978). Brainstorms. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. I. (1981). Knowledge and the flow of information. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. I. (1988). Explaining behavior: Reasons in a world of causes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Egan, F., & Matthews, R. (2006). Doing cognitive neuroscience: A third way. Synthese, 153, 377–391.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ermentrout, G. B., & Terman, D. H. (2010). Mathematical foundations of neuroscience. New York: Springer.

  • Eliasmith, C. (2013). How to build a brain: A neural architecture for biological cognition. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Feldman, J. A., & Ballard, D. H. (1982). Connectionist models and their properties. Cognitive Science, 6, 205–254.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1968a). Psychological explanation. New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1968b). The appeal to tacit knowledge in psychological explanation. Journal of Philosophy, 65, 627–640.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1974). Special sciences. Synthese, 28, 77–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1997). Special sciences: Still autonomous after all these years. In J. Tomberlin (Ed.), Philosophical perspectives 11: Mind, causation, and world (pp. 149–163). Boston: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1998). Concepts. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fox, P. T., Minton, M. A., Raichle, M. E., Miezin, F. M., Allman, J. M., & Van Essen, D. C. (1986). Mapping human visual cortex with positron emission tomography. Nature, 323, 806–809.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fresco, N. (2014). Physical computation and cognitive science. New York: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Freud, S. (1895/1966). Project for a scientific psychology. In E. Jones (Ed.) & J. Strachey (Trans.), The standard edition of the complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud (Vol. 1, pp. 295–397). London: Hogarth Press.

  • Gallistel, R. G., & King, A. P. (2009). Memory and the computational brain: Why cognitive science will transform neuroscience. New York: Wiley/Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Glennan, S. (2002). Rethinking mechanistic explanation. Philosophy of Science, 69(3), S342–S353.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hodgkin, A. L., & Huxley, A. F. (1952). A quantitative description of membrane current and its application to conduction and excitation in nerve. Journal of Physiology, 117, 500–544.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Humphreys, P. (2004). Extending ourselves: Computational science, empiricism, and scientific method. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • James, W. (1890/1983). The principles of psychology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Jilk, D., Lebiere, C., O’Reilly, R., & Anderson, J. (2008). SAL: An explicitly pluralistic cognitive architecture. Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence, 20(3), 197–218.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson-Laird, P. N. (1983). Mental models: Towards a cognitive science of language, inference and consciousness. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. M. (2011). Explanation and description in computational neuroscience. Synthese, 183(3), 339–373.

  • Kaplan, D. M., & Craver, C. F. (2011). The explanatory force of dynamical models. Philosophy of Science, 78(4), 601–627.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knight, B. W. (1972). Dynamics of encoding in a population of neurons. Journal of General Physiology, 59, 734–766.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kosslyn, S. (1980). Image and mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kosslyn, S. (1994). Image and brain: The resolution of the imagery debate. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kosslyn, S., & Van Kleeck, M. H. (1990). Broken brains and normal minds: Why humpty–dumpty needs a skeleton. In E. L. Schwartz (Ed.), Computational neuroscience. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kosslyn, S., Thompson, W. L., & Ganis, G. (2006). The case for mental imagery. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Laird, J. E. (2012). The soar cognitive architecture. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laird, J. E., Newell, A., & Rosenbloom, P. S. (1987). Soar: An architecture for general intelligence. Artificial Intelligence, 33, 1–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levy, A. (2013). What was Hodgkin and Huxley’s achievement? British Journal for Philosophy of Science. doi:10.1093/bjps/axs043.

  • Levy, A., & Bechtel, W. (2013). Abstraction and the organization of mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 80(2), 241–261.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lycan, W. (1981). Form, function, and feel. Journal of Philosophy, 78, 24–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lycan, W. (1990). The continuity of levels of nature. In W. Lycan (Ed.), Mind and cognition. Malden, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machamer, P., Darden, L., & Craver, C. (2000). Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 67(1), 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maley, C., & Piccinini, G. (2013). Get the latest upgrade: Functionalism 6.3.1. Philosophia Scientiae, 17(2), 135–149.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marr, D. (1982). Vision. San Francisco: W. H. Freeman and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • McClelland, J. L., & Lambon Ralph, M. A. (Eds.). (2013). Cognitive neuroscience: Emergence of mind from brain. The biomedical & life sciences collection. London: Henry Stewart Talks Ltd.

  • McCulloch, W., & Pitts, W. (1943). A logical calculus of the ideas immanent in nervous activity. Bulletin of Mathematical Biophysics, 5, 115–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Milkowski, M. (2013). Explaining the computational mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, A. (2014). Representations gone mental. Synthese, 191(2), 213–244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newell, A. (1980). Physical symbol systems. Cognitive Science, 4, 135–183.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newell, A., & Simon, H. A. (1972). Human problem solving. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall.

  • Newell, A., & Simon, H. A. (1976). Computer science as an empirical enquiry: Symbols and search. Communications of the ACM, 19, 113–126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Doherty, J., Hampton, A., & Kim, H. (2007). Model-based fMRI and its application to reward learning and decision making. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 1104, 35–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Reilly, R. C., & Munakata, Y. (2000). Computational explorations in cognitive neuroscience: Understanding the mind by simulating the brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  • O’Reilly, R. C., Munakata, Y., Frank, M. J., Hazy, T. E., & Contributors. (2014). Computational cognitive neuroscience. Wiki Book (2nd ed.). http://ccnbook.colorado.edu.

  • Piccinini, G. (unpublished). Activities are manifestations of causal powers.

  • Piccinini, G. (2007). Computational modeling vs. computational explanation: Is everything a turing machine, and does it matter to the philosophy of mind? Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 85(1), 93–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piccinini, G. (2008). Computers. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 89(1), 32–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piccinini, G., & Bahar, S. (2013). Neural computation and the computational theory of cognition. Cognitive Science, 34, 453–488.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piccinini, G., & Craver, C. (2011). Integrating psychology and neuroscience: Functional analyses as mechanism sketches. Synthese, 183(3), 283–311.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piccinini, G., & Maley, C. (2014). The metaphysics of mind and the multiple sources of multiple realizability. In M. Sprevak & J. Kallestrup (Eds.), New waves in the philosophy of mind. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piccinini, G., & Scarantino, A. (2011). Information processing, computation, and cognition. Journal of Biological Physics, 37(1), 1–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Posner, M. I. (1976). Chronometric explorations of mind. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Posner, M. I., & Raichle, M. E. (1994). Images of mind. New York: Scientific American Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Povich, M. (forthcoming). Mechanisms and model-based fMRI. Philosophy of Science.

  • Putnam, H. (1967). Psychological predicates. Art, philosophy, and religion. Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975). Philosophy and our mental life. In H. Putnam (Ed.), Mind, language and reality: Philosophical papers (Vol. 2, pp. 291–303). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, Z. W. (1981). The imagery debate: Analogue media versus tacit knowledge. Psychological Review, 88, 16–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, Z. W. (1984). Computation and cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, Z. W. (2002). Mental imagery: In search of a theory. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 25(2), 157–237.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, Z. W. (2003). Return of the mental image: Are there really pictures in the head? Trends in Cognitive Science, 7(3), 113–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey, W. M. (2007). Representation reconsidered. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenblatt, F. (1962). Principles of neurodynamics: Perceptrons and the theory of brain mechanisms. Washington, DC: Spartan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roskies, A. (2009). Brain–mind and structure–function relationships: A methodological response to Coltheart. Philosophy of Science, 76(5), 927–939.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rumelhart, D. E., McClelland, J. M., & The PDP Research Group. (1986). Parallel distributed processing: Explorations in the microstructure of cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

  • Rusanen, A.-M., & Lappi, O. (2007). The limits of mechanistic explanation in cognitive science. In S. Vosniadou, D. Kayser, & A. Protopapas (Eds.), Proceedings of the European cognitive science conference 2007 (pp. 284–289). Howe: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

  • Scarantino, A. (2015). Information as a probabilistic difference maker. Australian Journal of Philosophy. doi:10.1080/00048402.2014.993665.

  • Schaffner, K. F. (2008). Theories, models, and equations in biology: The heuristic search for emergent simplifications in neurobiology. Philosophy of Science, 75, 1008–1021.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shagrir, O. (2010a). Brains as analog-model computers. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 41, 271–279.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shagrir, O. (2010b). Marr on computational-level theories. Philosophy of Science, 77, 477–500.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smart, J. J. C. (1959). Sensations and brain processes. The Philosophical Review, 68(2), 141–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smart, J. J. C. (2007). The mind/brain identity theory. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Summer 2007 ed.). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2007/entries/mind-identity/.

  • Stein, R. (1965). A theoretical analysis of neuronal variability. Biophysical Journal, 5(2), 173–194.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. (2007). Coherence, truth, and the development of scientific knowledge. Philosophy of Science, 74, 28–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Treisman, A. (1996). The binding problem. Current Opinion in Neurobiology, 6(2), 171–178.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Treisman, A. (2009). Attention: Theoretical and psychological perspectives. In M. Gazzaniga (Ed.), The cognitive neurosciences (4th ed., pp. 189–204). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Treisman, A., & Gelade, G. (1980). A feature integration theory of attention. Cognitive Psychology, 12, 97–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Eck, D., & Weber, E. (2014). Function ascription and explanation: Elaborating an explanatory utility desideratum for ascriptions of technical functions. Erkenntnis. doi:10.1007/s10670-014-9605-1.

  • Vartanian, A. (1973). In P. P. Wiener (Ed.), Dictionary of the history of ideas: Studies of selected pivotal ideas. New York: Scriners.

  • Waxman, S. (1972). Regional differentiation of the axon: A review with special reference to the concept of the multiplex neuron. Brain Research, 47, 269–288.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weber, M. (2005). Philosophy of experimental biology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, M. (2008). Causes without mechanisms: Experimental regularities, physical laws, and neuroscientific explanation. Philosophy of Science, 75(5), 995–1007.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M. (2013). Simulation and similarity: Using models to understand the world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Weiskopf, D. (2011). Models and mechanisms in psychological explanation. Synthese, 183(3), 313–338.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, H. R., & Cowan, J. D. (1972). Excitatory and inhibitory interactions in localized populations of model neurons. Biophysical Journal, 12, 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Winsberg, E. (2010). Science in the age of computer simulation. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Gualtiero Piccinini.

Additional information

The authors are listed alphabetically—the paper was thoroughly collaborative. Otávio Bueno graciously arranged for the double blind refereeing of this paper; thanks to him and the anonymous referees for helpful comments. Thanks to our audiences at Georgia State University, Washington University in St. Louis, the 2014 Society for Philosophy and Psychology meeting, 2014 Central APA meeting and to our APA commentator, Robert Rupert. Thanks to Sergio Barberis, Mazviita Chirimuuta, and Corey Maley for helpful comments. Thanks to Elliott Risch for editorial assistance. This material is based on work supported in part by a University of Missouri research award to Gualtiero Piccinini.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Boone, W., Piccinini, G. The cognitive neuroscience revolution. Synthese 193, 1509–1534 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0783-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0783-4

Keywords

Navigation