Skip to main content
Log in

Scalar consequentialism the right way

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Rightness and wrongness come in degrees that vary on a continuous scale. Examples in which agents have many options that morally differ from each other demonstrate this. I suggest ways to develop scalar consequentialism, which treats the rightness and wrongness of actions as matters of degree, and explains them in terms of the value of the actions’ consequences. Scalar consequentialism has a variety of linguistic resources for understanding unsuffixed “right.” It also has advantages over some deontological theories in accounting for rightness.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Aboodi, R., Borer, A., & Enoch, D. (2008). Deontology, individualism, and uncertainty, a reply to Jackson and Smith. Journal of Philosophy, 105(5), 259–272.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brink, D. O. (1989). Moral realism and the foundations of ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carbonell, V. (2013). De dicto desires and morality as fetish. Philosophical Studies, 163(2), 459–477.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dancy, J. (1999). Defending particularism. Metaphilosophy, 30(1&2), 25–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dancy, J. (2015). Review of British ethical theorists from Sidgwick to Ewing. In T. Hurka (Ed.), Notre dame philosophical reviews. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • DeRose, K. (2009). The case for contextualism: Knowledge, skepticism, and context (Vol. 1). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Driver, J. (2012). Consequentialism. Abingdon-on-Thames: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibbard, A. (1990). Wise choices, apt feelings: A theory of normative judgment. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawley, P. (2008). Moral absolutism defended. Journal of Philosophy, 105(5), 273–275.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (2003). A treatise of human nature. Project Gutenberg E-Text.

  • Hurd, H. M. (1999). Moral combat. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hurka, T. (2014). British ethical theorists from Sidgwick to Ewing. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hursthouse, R. (1999). On virtue ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutcheson, F. (2008). An inquiry into the original of our ideas of beauty and virtue: In two treatises. Carmel: Liberty Fund.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kamm, F. M. (2007). Intricate ethics: Rights, responsibilities, and permissible harm. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (2011). Groundwork of the metaphysics of morals: A German–English edition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy, C. (2006). Vagueness and grammar: The semantics of relative and absolute gradable adjectives. Linguistics and Philosophy, 30, 1–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lang, G. (2013). Should utilitarianism be scalar? Utilitas, 25(1), 80–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lawlor, R. (2009). The rejection of scalar consequentialism. Utilitas, 21(1), 100–116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1996). Elusive knowledge. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 74(4), 549–567.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacFarlane, J. (2014). Assessment sensitivity: Relative truth and its applications. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McElwee, B. (2010). The rights and wrongs of consequentialism. Philosophical Studies, 151, 393–412.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J. S. (1987). Utilitarianism and other essays. London: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norcross, A. (1997). Good and bad actions. Philosophical Review, 106(1), 1–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Norcross, A. (2005). Contextualism for consequentialists. Acta Analytica, 20(2), 80–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Norcross, A. (2006a). The scalar approach to utilitarianism. In H. West (Ed.), The Blackwell guide to Mill’s utilitarianism (pp. 217–232). Hoboken: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norcross, A. (2006b). Reasons without demands: Rethinking rightness. In J. L. Dreier (Ed.), Contemporary debates in moral theory (pp. 6–38). Hoboken: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norcross, A. (unpublished manuscript). Morality by degrees: Reasons without demands.

  • Scanlon, T. (1998). What we owe to each other. Cambridge: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2004). From contextualism to contrastivism. Philosophical Studies, 119(1–2), 73–104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P. (1972). Famine, affluence, and morality. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 1(3), 229–243.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sinhababu, N. (2017). Humean nature. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Slote, M., & Pettit, P. (1984). Satisficing consequentialism. Aristotelian Society Supplementary, 58(1), 139–176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, M. (1994). The moral problem. Hoboken: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J. (2006). Knowledge and practical interests. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, J. J. (2008). Turning the trolley. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 36(4), 359–374.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wedgwood, R. (2011). Defending double effect. Ratio, 24(4), 384–401.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I thank Robbie Williams and Mitchell Yoshitaka Erlewine for help with the semantics of gradable adjectives, Tomislav Janović and Matej Susnik for teaching me about Croatian grammar, Derek Baker for raising the issue of binary guidance, Peter Murphy for suggesting the notion of continuous right-making parameters, John Tilley for help with Hume, Samuel Kahn for help with Kant, and Daniel Muñoz for help with twentieth century British ethics scholarship. I also thank audiences at the University of Waikato, Massey University, Colorado State University, the University of Akron, Cleveland State University, the University of North Carolina at Asheville, Indiana University-Purdue University Indianapolis, the University of Surrey, and the University of Oslo for helpful feedback.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Neil Sinhababu.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Sinhababu, N. Scalar consequentialism the right way. Philos Stud 175, 3131–3144 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-017-0998-y

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-017-0998-y

Keywords

Navigation