1 Introduction

In recent years, a model of national constitutionalism has become widespread that deviates from classical patterns of constitution making. This new constitutional model is closely linked to the emergence of a global constitutional order, as it is characterized by the fact that domestic constitutional norms reflect international human rights law, and international norm setters often predefine the basic principles of the national constitution.Footnote 1 This model is marked, further, by the fact that, within the domestic polity, judicial bodies assume particular prominence, and they subject political institutions to strict control, at times curbing legislative activity, or even acquiring legislative responsibilities.Footnote 2 The acquisition of such authority by judicial institutions is normally justified on the grounds that they enforce norms based, either directly or indirectly, in international human rights law.Footnote 3 In this model, as a result, legislative force is not solely vested in agents of popular sovereignty, and the original authority to initiate legislative acts may reside in transnational organizations, supranational judicial organs, or domestic courts, applying international norms. Generally distinctive in this model of democracy is that the legal system operates at a high degree of autonomy in the national political order, and the relative power of legal institutions is sustained by the fact that national constitutional law is opened to a system of global norms. Overall, this model can be classified as judicial constitutionalism or even as transnational judicial constitutionalism.

The emergence of this constitutional model has stimulated a number of very critical commentaries. It is often asserted in such commentaries that the legal system in this model leads to the weakening of democracy, owing to the fact that it allows international norms externally to pre-construct the legislative decisions of sovereign populations.Footnote 4 In particular, it is claimed that this model relativizes the significance of national constituent power as the original source of constitutional law, as the popular will can only form a basis for government if proportioned to the existing corpus of hyper-entrenched international human rights law.Footnote 5 It is also argued that this model diminishes the importance of politics per se, as judicial intervention in political processes means that legislation loses its distinctive quality as politically legitimated. Theorists grouped together as exponents of political constitutionalism are outspoken in this line of critique, arguing that, in any legitimate political system, the decisions of strictly sovereign political subjects must form the premise for legislation, and these decisions must be expressed through a legislature.Footnote 6 These theorists thus immovably oppose polities with strongly autonomous legal systems. Some extreme perspectives view the judicial pattern of constitutionalism as facilitating the semi-tyrannical hegemony of powerful international actors, as it allows global elites to dictate policy constraints to populations with weaker positions within the global economy.Footnote 7

These critiques of transnational judicial constitutionalism are susceptible to query on a range of grounds. Increasingly, such critiques can be repudiated, simply, because they are politically irresponsible. In many contemporary societies, democracy is coming under attack from neo-nationalist governments, often appearing in varying shades of populism. This is visible for example in Hungary, Poland, Brazil, India, the UK, and the USA. In each of these polities, historically, the interaction between national institutions and global norm setters played an important role in stabilizing and expanding democracy. However, each polity is now experiencing a reduction in the quality of democracy. In each case, democratic crisis is reflected in hostility to global norms and scepticism towards domestic judicial institutions, at least to the extent that such institutions protect global normative principles. In some respects, advocates of emphatically political variants on constitutionalism have propagated a diction of political legitimation that favours the re-emergence of populist nationalism. The insistence of such theorists that legitimate government must be founded, simply, in the sovereign will of national citizens is close to some aspects of the populist stance, and it can easily unsettle the democratic systems of governance that constitutional theorists purport to defend.Footnote 8 When theoretical outlooks directly coincide with processes that lead to the negation of their own professed purpose, such outlooks, evidently, require urgent revision.

Critiques of judicial constitutionalism can be rejected, second, on the ground that they lack an adequate sociological understanding of democratic politics. In some ways, the political irresponsibility reflected in critiques of judicial constitutionalism is the product of their sociological insensitivity, which leads them to endorse simplified and counterfactual normative constructs. Such critiques presuppose, paradigmatically, that democracy is a polity type that is legitimated, invariably, by the fact that social agents participate equally in law making through legislative or other representative institutions.Footnote 9 In this regard, such critiques are inclined to apply the norms of classical democratic theory very literally, and they impute legitimational processes in democracy to a strictly construed set of norm-producing practices, expressed in concepts of popular sovereignty, citizenship, and collective will formation, and they presume that all societies contain political subjects able to construct legitimacy for legislation through such practices.Footnote 10 Moreover, such critiques presume that every society has the capacity to impose a representative structure on its articulations with such political subjects, so that the interests of sovereign citizens can be straightforwardly mediated through legislative institutions. In many settings, however, the vocabulary of democratic theory projects legitimational processes that cannot be aligned to actual conditions of government. In many societies, the legitimational forms imputed to democracy in conventional conceptual constructions of political subjectivity do not exist, and the political system cannot easily be articulated with the subjects from which it is expected to extract legitimacy. Even in classical democratic societies, the presumption that democratic institutions were legitimated by national populations formed as volitional subjects was a fiction, and the demos conceived as the source of institutional legitimacy had to be created by political institutions themselves.Footnote 11 In many contemporary democracies, the idea that the political system can obtain legitimacy through immediate exchanges with organized political subjects is plainly reductive. Accordingly, many critiques of judicial democracy, especially those that insist on legislative institutions as the necessary fulcrum of democracy, analyse the preconditions of legitimate democracy by fictitious standards, and their challenge to existing democratic polities promotes a deep simplification of democratic legitimation.

This article aims to add a new sociological analysis of democracy to debate about global-legal or global-judicial patterns of constitutionalism. It uses this analysis to assess this democratic model by criteria that are sensitively adapted to the societal conditions in which democratic polities are located, seeking, thus, to avoid the reductivism inherent in many critiques of judicial constitutionalism. More importantly, this article seeks to promote an understanding of democracy able to resist the current shift towards democratic simplification in constitutional theory and practice. It attempts to outline a complex framework for analysis of democracy, and, in this respect, it is guided by the conviction that adequate sociological comprehension of democracy is essential to its continued development. The categories in which democracy is typically analysed are not adequate to its factual foundations, and this contributes to the risks that frequently surround contemporary democracy. Above all, the fixation of democratic theory on static constructs of sovereignty and popular citizenship requires sharp correction if contemporary democracies are to be reliably interpreted and the case for democracy securely advanced.

Democracy, it is contended here, needs to be observed as a socially variable mode of political formation. In essence, democracy is a polity type that is oriented towards the production of consensual legitimacy for law, and in which law is distributed through society on premises created through broad consensus. Naturally, there are some conditions that all democracies need to satisfy, in order to qualify as such. The most indispensable amongst such conditions is full enfranchisement of the population in regular competitive elections, without exclusion from the exercise of electoral rights on grounds of ethnicity, socio-economic position, or gender.Footnote 12 Above this threshold, however, democratic systems need not presuppose one single legitimational process, and the lines of communication between the polity and subjects in society cannot be fixed to uniform categories of political agency and subjectivity. There is in fact no compelling reason why concepts of democracy should be configured around simple analyses of popular sovereignty. During the first emergence of democracy, it was widely intuited, especially amongst sociologists, that democratic polities had been brought into being by transpersonal processes of social transformation, and they evolved as variable instruments for creating legitimacy for law, under conditions of rising social complexity. On this account, the growth of democracy was driven by the integrational expansion of society as a whole, and democracy acquired legitimacy as a polity type able to produce consensus for law in a form adapted to the complex environments and the varied subjective forms that modern society increasingly contained.Footnote 13 On this view, democracy could emerge in highly contingent fashion, and it was not necessarily instituted by considered acts of rational, participatory, or eminently political subjects. On this view, further, citizens could create consensual premises for law in multiple roles, not all focused on conventional electoral activities, and the rights through which citizens shape legislative acts and bring legitimacy to law could be exercised in manifold, complex fashion.Footnote 14

This classical sociological analysis of democracy retains validity today. As mentioned, many democracies are confronted with deep challenges in constructing the subjects around which they are expected to explain their legitimacy. In many settings, even primary categories of democratic agency and personhood—the sovereign people, the national citizen—cannot easily be mapped onto factually existing subjects, and the capacity of the political system for articulating with and representing such subjects is minimal. In many settings, polities have been required to institutionalize legitimational practices, and even to construct democratic agents and subjects, in improvised adaptive processes, and atypical patterns of integration are needed before democratic legitimation can occur. If observed closely, in fact, many democracies have evolved, at least in part, around functional equivalents to classical democratic forms of legitimation and subject formation. Sociological attentiveness to such complex phenomena is vital for understanding the current realities of democracy. In particular, reflection on such phenomena is important for interpreting the prevalence of global-judicial models of constitutionalism in contemporary society. In many respects, this model has emerged as a system of equivalence, in which global human rights norms act as surrogates for classical patterns of norm production, allowing the political system to integrate social actors (citizens) persons in society and to legitimate legislation in a form that compensates for the weak formation of political subjects in national society. In this model, the legal system acts at a high level of autonomy specifically, not to reduce democracy, but to construct equivalents for classical democratic procedures, often in societies where such procedures do not gain immediate traction. A perspective that reflects on constitutional law, not solely as a normative order, but as an adaptive system for constructing legitimacy for law, is thus required to capture the present form of democracy.

This article develops these claims, specifically, by examining constitutional conditions in Colombia. Colombia is selected for analysis because, since 1991, its polity is one of the most extreme examples of transnational judicial constitutionalism. For this reason, some critics of judicial activism have singled out Colombia for admonishment, implying that more classical patterns of constitutional organization should be preferred.Footnote 15 Indeed, hostility to judicial power in Colombia has been sharply articulated in governmental policy. Colombia itself is now threatened by the anti-judicial tendencies seen in other countries, especially those that have embarked on the path to more populist governmental techniques.Footnote 16 On these grounds, Colombia provides a case study both for assessing the correlation between judicial influence and democratic institutionalization and for observing how democracy might be unsettled by more classical processes of political mobilization. Most importantly, Colombia is examined here as a society in which, for embedded historical reasons, the political system faced acute problems of socio-political integration and democratic subject construction. The study of Colombia shows emphatically that, in some settings, the basic subjects of democratic legitimation—including, even, the people themselves—do not exist as simply manifest entities. On the contrary, political institutions obtain legitimacy by devising equivalents to the subjects from which they are expected to extract legitimacy and through which they produce legislation. In consequence, the case of Colombia demands a deep revision of the ways in which classical principles of democracy are applied to material constitutional realities. Above all, it demands a sociological reconstruction of core categories of democratic theory, and it shows that, in some settings, democracy itself may need to be re-thought if it is to be sustainably defended.

This article is not alone in claiming that transnational constitutional norms have democracy-enhancing results. However, more favourable discussions of transnational judicial constitutionalism have usually proceeded from a position located within classical accounts of democracy.Footnote 17 Typically, such positive analyses claim that such constitutions improve the quality of democracy by stabilizing justified legislative outcomes;Footnote 18 by providing strong checks on political branches, averting uncontrolled executive enactment of global directives;Footnote 19 and by stimulating public deliberation on core executive decisions.Footnote 20 By contrast, using one empirical case study, this article argues that accurate analysis of judicial constitutional forms may require that we adopt a new sociological lens for understanding core democratic functions.

2 Colombia, Democracy and Global Human Rights Law

At one level, Colombia has a relatively long-standing and continuous history of competitive democracy, whose origins reach back to the middle of the nineteenth century. Unusually for Latin America, Colombia has only limited experience with military intervention in civil politics, and rotation of governmental office has only infrequently been interrupted.Footnote 21 Nonetheless, as discussed below, democracy in Colombia has a fragile history, and it has often possessed only formal or nominal character. Distinctive features in the structure of Colombian society—in particular, deep cultural fissures between different regions and extreme material variations between different groups, high prevalence of private power and patrimonialism, and low societal convergence around centralized institutions—have meant that, historically, democratic institutions could not easily be consolidated. As discussed below, this is reflected in the fact that formal state institutions have often been rivalled in force by other organizations, the political system was endemically porous to elite interests, societal antagonisms often resulted in seismic violence and protracted civil conflict between different socio-political groups, and democratically mandated governance bodies often relied on prerogative legislation to preserve their control. In each respect, the formation of Colombian democracy has been marked by acute problems in the integrational dimensions of the polity, and the basic structural inclusivity required to connect societal actors to democratic institutions has not been fully established. Overall, at key junctures, the public authority of the state was only patchily felt in society, and the ability of state institutions to attach their legitimacy to integrated citizens was weak.Footnote 22

Against this background, the current governmental order in Colombia can be seen, paradigmatically, as a polity that has been created through international human rights law. Indeed, it is a polity in which the global rise of human rights has helped to remedy deep-lying structural-integrational problems that impeded democratic institution building.

Important researchers are currently exploring the historical genealogies of human rights law in Colombia.Footnote 23 At an immediate level, however, human rights law began to gain impact in Colombia in the 1980s, during the extreme crisis of democracy caused by escalating civil conflict and acute state repression. In this period, proponents of rival ideologies in Colombia, attached to hostile positions in the civil conflict, began to explain their prerogatives in the register of international human rights.Footnote 24 Simultaneously, international organizations became increasingly engaged with the causes and consequences of the violence in Colombia, leading to the heightened domestic penetration of global instruments as means for conflict resolution. In 1985, the Colombian government accepted jurisdiction of the Inter-American Court of Human Rights (IACtHR), intensifying the enforcement of the American Convention on Human Rights (ACHR) within Colombia. However, the most important early step in the legal consolidation of human rights occurred in 1990, during a state of exception imposed because of the intensification of civil conflict. Responding to this situation, successive Presidents issued two emergency decrees, Decree 927/1990 and Decree 1926/1990, which led to the creation of a National Constitutional Assembly in early 1991 to draft a new constitution for the Republic.Footnote 25 The Constitution produced by the Constituent Assembly was adopted in 1991. The 1991 Constitution was conceived partly in conventional terms, as a formal document to regulate functions of state. But it was also conceived as a political pact or inter-group treaty. In particular, the new Constitution was designed to establish working arrangements between select parties in the civil conflict, to expand popular participation in public functions, and—by these means—to solidify the basic institutions of the state.Footnote 26 Different parties in the constitution-making process shared a strong orientation towards human rights, and human rights figured prominently in debates in the Constituent Assembly.Footnote 27

Ultimately, the prominence of human rights during the period of constitution making in 1991 was reflected in the final text of the Colombian Constitution, which forms a classical example of the rights-based, judicial constitutional model. This is visible both in the Constitution itself and in the strategies by means of which its core provisions were put into effect:

2.1 The Structure of the Constitution

The 1991 Constitution provides for different categories of rights, with varying status and enforceability. It establishes a series of fundamental rights, centred on classical rights and rights of personal dignity, which are immediately enforceable. However, it establishes a range of rights, albeit granted weaker protection, which extend beyond classical human rights. For instance, Article 49 determines that the state is responsible for organizing, directing and regulating the delivery of health services and environmental protection. Article 79 establishes certain environmental rights, declaring that the state has a duty to ‘protect the diversity and integrity of the environment, to conserve areas of special ecological importance, and to foster education for the achievement of these ends’. Art 67 declares that education is ‘an individual right and a public service that has a social function’. Alongside this, the Constitution emphasizes the importance of labour rights (Arts 53–57), indicating that private property implies inherent social and ecological obligations (Arts 58–60, 63–64). As part of its general guarantee of equality (Art 13), it recognizes the rights of vulnerable and historically discriminated groups, such as women (Art 43), children and adolescents (Arts 44 and 45), disabled people (Art 47), and ethnic minorities. Indigenous groups had three representatives in the Assembly that wrote the Constitution, and they obtained rights of representation, self-governance, and qualified judicial autonomy (Arts 171, 246, 329, 330, 356), most of which were already envisaged in existing international instruments.

Important in this respect is the fact that the Constitution promotes a two-level conception of human rights. It constructs a framework in which human rights can be viewed both as a set of strictly positive norms and as an autonomous and evolving sphere of the law. Distinctively, first, Article 94 states that ‘the rights and guarantees contained in the Constitution and in international conventions shall not be understood as a denial of other rights inherent in the human person, which are not expressly stipulated in those documents’. This Article was subsequently interpreted to imply that the catalogue of rights in the Constitution could be enlarged, or subject to enhanced judicial construction. As discussed below, this Article provided an important context, in which judicial actors could promote an expansionary approach to basic rights. Second, as examined below, the fact that it emphasizes post-classical rights means that historically vulnerable sectors of society have been able to engage directly with the political system through the medium of rights, and the societal reach of basic constitutional provisions has been augmented because of this.

2.2 The Structure of the Judiciary

In addition to consolidating basic rights, the 1991 Constitution provides a robust apparatus to ensure their protection, enforcement, and democratic elaboration, and it added new organs to the judiciary.

Significant amongst the judicial institutions created by the Constitution are the Constitutional Court, which, as the highest judicial organ, has constitutional jurisdiction; the Council of State (Consejo de Estado), which has administrative jurisdiction; the Supreme Court, with ordinary jurisdiction; and the Superior Council of the Judiciary, with disciplinary jurisdiction. In addition, the Constitution established a Human Rights Ombudsman (Defensoría del Pueblo). The Constitution also created specific organs to supervise branches of government, in response to human rights violations. After the Constitution entered force, additional human rights mechanisms were established, including bodies to deal with litigation before international courts, with the implementation of international judicial rulings, and with domestic reparation for breaches of human rights.Footnote 28 Alongside this, the Constitution sets out provisions for new types of legal action and representation in human rights cases. Amongst these are provisions for public interest litigation, designed to protect collective interests and fundamental rights (Art 88). Most importantly, the Constitution makes provision for the filing of tutelas (Art 86). Tutelas are petitions that allow an individual citizen to demand suspension of any action or omission of a governmental or private entity that threatens a fundamental right. Although the instrument of the tutela is not in itself new, it has acquired very distinctive implications in Colombia. In Colombia, a tutela can be filed in very informal manner, even in oral and handwritten form. As a result, tutelas have often been submitted by marginal subjects, relating to abuses of rights that afflict persons in disadvantaged social positions, and they have led to an exponential increase in access to law for such subjects. Tutelas can also be filed by proxies, through agencia oficiosa, to represent interests of a subject who cannot ‘promote his or her own defence’—that is, for instance, a subject whose immediate access to justice is restricted for literacy-related, cultural, or geographical reasons.Footnote 29 As discussed below, tutelas have acquired a central role in the promotion of fundamental rights and in the extension of the societal reach of legal organs, and they have often provided openings for legal actors to construct new rights or to extend existing rights to new subjects.

2.3 The Constitution and International Human Rights Law

The 1991 Constitution accords a privileged position to international human rights law in the domestic legal order. It states that international treaties ratified by the Congress that recognize human rights should have precedence over domestic norms; it forbids the limitation of these rights during states of emergency; and it stipulates that human rights treaties shall be used as interpretative guides for realizing the rights and duties defined in the Constitution (Art 93). The special position given to international human rights law has been strengthened by judgements of the Constitutional Court. Generally, the Court has adopted the principle that international human rights norms are identical with the values declared in domestic constitutional law,Footnote 30 so that domestic rights provisions need to be purposively aligned to international norms. It has also ruled that international norms prevail over domestic law in cases in which they give stronger protection to human rights.Footnote 31 Importantly, it has recently strengthened this line of jurisprudence, to argue that international human rights law must have higher standing than principles set out in other spheres of international law.Footnote 32

On this basis, the Court has tended to use international norms to harden its own power in relation to other branches of government in the elaboration of constitutional norms. At an early stage, the Court declared that the sovereignty of governmental institutions should be seen as strictly constrained by international human rights law, claiming that human rights ‘are too important for their protection to be left exclusively in the hands of states’.Footnote 33 In this, it proposed itself as the custodian of global human rights law, entitled to check the power of government bodies on globally authorized grounds. More specifically, in a ruling of 1992, the Court established criteria to determine whether a right has a fundamental character and is subject to petition by tutela. It decided that such criteria are met if the right in question is protected in an international human rights treaty.Footnote 34 In so doing, the Court significantly widened the scope of its own jurisdiction. In some cases, the Court has simply interpreted internationally defined rights as domestic constitutional rights. Relying on the Universal Declaration of Human Rights and the International Covenant on Economic and Social Rights, for example, the Court established a right to subsistence and a right to a minimum living standard, and these rights were subsequently used to prescribe public policies to the government.Footnote 35

As part of this commitment to domestic entrenchment of international human rights law, the Constitutional Court has established the core doctrine of the block of constitutionality, originally derived and modified from French public law. Central to this doctrine is the principle that some internationally recognized norms that are not expressly mentioned in the Constitution can be accorded near-constitutional rank, and they can be applied as ‘parameters for testing the constitutionality of laws’.Footnote 36 Ultimately, the Court extracted great latitude from this doctrine, and it incorporated a broad range of international norms in domestic public law. For example, it decided that international soft-law norms regarding the rights of displaced persons, especially the Deng and Pinheiro principles promulgated under UN auspices, should be construed as binding sources of domestic rights.Footnote 37 It also directly incorporated the ACHR, and, by extension, the rulings of the IACtHR. The jurisprudence of the IACtHR thus assumed a de facto constitutional position in Colombian public law.Footnote 38 In later cases, the Court imputed a special force to the jurisprudence of international human rights organs.Footnote 39 The international norms absorbed in the block of constitutionality have been defined as obligatory, not only for public entities, but also for non-state actors. Consequently, international human rights have been interpreted to form a binding legal/constitutional structure for all persons in society,Footnote 40 leading to the deep penetration of international law in the practices of everyday life.

2.4 The Constitutional Court

From the outset, overall, the Colombian Constitutional Court emerged as a highly activist Court, with a very distinctive constitutional role and a prominent position in the polity as a whole.Footnote 41 Notably, the fact that the National Constituent Assembly was established during a state of emergency had important immediate consequences for the Constitutional Court. The Constituent Assembly, convoked in February 1991, finished writing the Constitution in July 1991. With the support of the President César Gaviria (1990–1994), the Constituent Assembly dissolved the regular Congress, instituted a transitional legislative body known as El Congresito (‘the mini Congress’), and called elections to form a new Congress. During its limited mandate from July to November 1991, El Congresito formalized certain exceptional provisions enacted by the government during the state of emergency. This meant that, directly after ratification of the Constitution, emergency legislation was in force, which curtailed the effect of the human rights in the Constitution. The fact that, at its enactment, the new Constitution was subject to restrictive provisions meant that the Constitutional Court quickly assumed an activist role. In some of its earliest rulings, it nullified on grounds of unconstitutionality some acts introduced by the interim Congress,Footnote 42 claiming elevated powers to defend the Constitution.Footnote 43

Partly as a result of these factors, the Constitutional Court soon began to act as the repository of constituent power. Even before the drafting of the Constitution, in fact, the Supreme Court approved the Decrees that led to the convocation of the Constituent Assembly in 1991. It declared that these Decrees were legitimate because they ensured that the people were able to act as the ‘primary constituent’ of the state.Footnote 44 After 1991, the Constitutional Court construed the constituent power of the people and the normative force of human rights as essentially identical, and it assumed entitlement to act as protector of both. In one of its first decisions, the Court declared that it was entitled to decide which rights can be ranked as fundamental and to establish protection and remedies accordingly.Footnote 45 It also constructively interpreted the value of human dignity expressed in the Constitution as a meta-norm, which it construed as a teleological directive to enlarge the system of rights protecting human dignity, especially in the ‘social dimension’ of human life.Footnote 46 In both respects, the Court interpreted the human rights provisions in the Constitution as providing a broad warrant for its assumption of de facto constituent powers.

The distinctive position of the Constitutional Court is most evident in its tutela rulings, in which it has routinely performed functions that far exceed normal obligations for judicial scrutiny. In some cases, for example, the Court has decided that tutela cases have broad social implications, such that its decision in one case needs to be accorded a widened scope, setting precedents for parties other than the individuals directly involved in the given adjudicatory process: such decisions are ascribed inter comunis effect.Footnote 47 A decision was imputed inter comunis effect for the first time in 2001.Footnote 48 In some rulings with inter comunis effect, the Court has claimed that the case brought before it reflects a condition of structural unconstitutionality, or ‘an unconstitutional state of affairs’, and it has formulated its judgement in order to remedy a set of problems that resonate widely across society as a whole. Rulings of this kind include cases in which a violation of human rights reported in a tutela is judged by the Court to be the result of deep-rooted structural causes, not solely attributable to one entity or to one public authority, and requiring far-reaching solutions.Footnote 49 Early instances of such rulings can be found in prison law, social security law, health law, and in education law, which were focused on systemic, but relatively circumscribed institutional crises.Footnote 50 Instances of this are especially important in environmental law cases.Footnote 51 However, the most important cases of this kind relate to the conditions of population groups displaced by civil violence, in addressing which the Court has issued judgements with very broad implications for the normative structure of society in its entirety. In such cases, the Court has assumed authority to prescribe multiple remedies with binding effect for all parties implicated in the instant case and for all persons affected by conditions similar to those revealed in the given tutela. The leading cases of this kind are strongly supported by international law, and violation of international human rights law is often seen as grounds to justify the designation of a tutela as displaying structural unconstitutionality and to authorize the resultant attribution of inter comunis effect to the relevant decision.Footnote 52

In these respects, the Constitutional Court has clearly acted simultaneously as a constituent, legislative, and as a policymaking organ. Indeed, it is often motivated by the sense that it is obliged to assume broad powers of legislation, as it views other branches of government, especially Congress, as ineffective in the performance of political responsibilities.Footnote 53

3 Global Law, Democratic Citizenship and Structural Adaption

In these respects, the Colombian Constitution stands at an extreme position on the spectrum of judicial authority and activism. As mentioned, the distinctive position of legal institutions in the Colombian polity means that is often viewed as the leading example of judicial constitutionalism, in which judicial bodies that apply global norms usurp functions properly exercised by democratically mandated branches of government. However, this description is only sustainable from a perspective that adopts a sociologically static account of democracy. The relative autonomy of legal bodies can equally be viewed as forming a system of equivalence, in which the assimilation of global human rights law into Colombian society obtains deep structural impact, creating preconditions for democracy that compensate for weaknesses in national democratic formation. Such structural impact is evident in the fact that global law consolidates institutional foundations for democracy that had been absent as society persisted in its purely national form. Such structural impact is also manifest in the fact that global law generates surrogates for more conventional forms of political agency and subject formation, and it promotes consensus production for law in a form adapted to the material fabric of Colombian society.

3.1 Institutional Formation

The structural impact of global law in Colombian society can be observed, quite simply, at the level of institutional consolidation, as processes of judicial norm construction based in global law have clearly diminished the force of some historical obstructions to democracy.

As mentioned, the establishment of a robust democracy in Colombia was impeded, originally, by the fact that political institutions struggled to assert a monopoly of power in society. One reason for this was that societal elites tended to resist the formation of a strong national political system, preferring to safeguard their social positions by private means and refusing to invest monetary resources (taxation) required for effective building of state capacity.Footnote 54 This meant that the fiscal revenue needed to establish a strong overarching national state was not guaranteed. One further reason for this was that members of political elites tended to occupy strongly developed regional positions, and they often secured societal support, not through national political representation, but by localized patrimonial means. This meant that political organizations did not mediate effectively between national government and regional constituencies.Footnote 55 As a result, central institutions were often too weak to sustain a nationally overarching legal/political system,Footnote 56 and, in the absence of a strong state structure, essential public functions were often arrogated by actors outside the formal political domain, including guerrillas or paramilitaries.Footnote 57 One important analysis of the history of violence in Colombia has attributed the power of military organizations directly to the reduced integrative reach of formal institutions.Footnote 58 This set of factors necessarily meant that one core precondition of democracy—the presence of national institutions able to articulate closely with citizens in all parts of society—was absent.

In this context, the penetration of global norms into Colombian society played a key role in hardening the societal foundations of the political system and in creating structural foundations for democracy. Indicatively, the Constitutional Court has declared that its use of global law is driven by consciously ‘Weberian’ considerations, and its endeavour to solidify a body of human rights in society is part of a policy to elevate the state’s monopoly of force vis-à-vis other actors and organizations.Footnote 59

The Constitutional Court gave strongest expression to this state-building strategy in its most important tutela ruling, T-025/04. This ruling, which concerned victims of mass displacement caused by civil violence, formed a central pillar for the later jurisprudence of the Court, and it established parameters for the Court’s subsequent activism in policy questions. In this tutela, the Court declared that the displacement afflicting large numbers of Colombians indicated that the state itself was experiencing a deep structural crisis. Accordingly, it decided that the instant tutela reflected, not an isolated legal fact, but an unconstitutional state of affairs, to which the state itself had causally contributed.Footnote 60 In reaching this verdict, the Court argued that the structural crisis of the state was measurable in criteria derived from human rights law: that is, state failure was evident in the degree to which displaced population groups were deprived of their rights.Footnote 61 From this position, the Court concluded that provision of guarantees for basic rights was a vital aspect of effective state structure and protection of rights was a core measure of state capacity. From this position, then, it concluded that it was authorized to prescribe remedies to public agencies to ensure that they took measures to guarantee full enjoyment of basic rights amongst persons displaced by conflict. In this respect, the Court viewed its own promotion of human rights as an active contribution to the reinforcement of the state, serving to reinforce linkages between the state and persons at different points in society. Eventually, the Court drew up a series of indicators to evaluate the success of government bodies in resolving the structural crisis. These indicators were largely based in standards designed to measure the quality of human rights protection, partly drawn from international law.Footnote 62 As part of this process, international guidelines were invoked by the Court to enhance the fiscal performance of the government and to improve lines of communication between regional and national governmental bodies, both of which were seen as preconditions for protection of displaced persons.Footnote 63

In these respects, global law entered Colombian society as a medium of hard structural reinforcement, and it served to remedy historical weaknesses in the institutions required to sustain a democratic order. International human rights law acted to extend and stabilize an increasingly solid institutional structure across society, able to integrate societal groups in a setting in which national law had failed to accomplish this. Far from limiting the sovereign power of the national state, global law entered national society as the bedrock for the reinforcement of sovereign state institutions.

3.2 Citizenship Formation

The structural impact of global law in Colombia is also evident in other dimensions of society that are vital for the consolidation of democracy. Even the basic construct of the citizen, the primary fulcrum in the processes of integration and legitimation that sustain national democracy, has evolved, some respects, as an artefact of global law.Footnote 64

It is widely documented that in Colombia, as in many Latin American countries, the ideals of national citizenship and popular sovereignty projected in classical constitutionalism did not find a receptive environment. To be sure, both the Republic of New Granada (1831–1858) and, after 1886, the Republic of Colombia were founded around such ideals. Yet, a number of social factors meant that principles of national citizenship had restricted capacity to integrate society. In consequence, society as a whole did not acquire a fully nationalized shape and governmental legitimacy could not easily be attached to simple expressions of popular sovereignty.

First, during the nineteenth century, Colombian society possessed an extremely localized structure, and local sources of authority retained a dominant position as foci of socio-political co-ordination and obligation.Footnote 65 As mentioned, patronage widely stood in for national political participation as a source of political loyalty and authority.Footnote 66 One important account describes early Colombian citizenship as ‘hybrid citizenship’, containing disparate elements of local, clientelistic, and national obligations.Footnote 67 The Constitution of 1886 formally promoted rigidly centralized statehood and uniform citizenship, but, in reality, central institutions did not pierce deeply into the pluralistic fibre of society.Footnote 68 Second, as indicated, social elites in Colombia were often unwilling to support a nationally unifying political order, and one core precondition for a solid national political order (i.e. a sustainable fiscal system, to which citizens were willing to commit a portion of their income) was difficult to establish.Footnote 69 The material basis of citizenship was, therefore, always precarious. Most obviously, third, the intermittent periods of extremely high social violence reflected the weak articulation of citizenship. This violence had its origins in anti-colonial movements, and it was intensified by contests over land and resources beginning in the nineteenth century.Footnote 70 More structurally, however, violence was induced by the disjuncture between state and society, which meant that insurrectionist patterns of participation or citizenship often appeared more likely to yield benefits than formal or nationally institutionalized political interaction.Footnote 71 This violence exploded most catastrophically in the civil conflicts of the 1940s and 1950s and the 1980s and 1990s. In these periods, the insurgents and paramilitaries that took control of society often formed de facto governance regimes, establishing shadowy analogues to state institutions in some regions, even creating judicial orders and rudimentary fiscal systems.Footnote 72 Inevitably, this meant that national citizenship, based in territorially overarching claims to rights of inclusion and participation, possessed a fictional quality.Footnote 73 In each respect, the multi-polar form of citizenship militated against the consolidation of subjects able to sustain democracy.

The Constitution of 1991 marked a strategic response to these problems. In the first instance, the impetus for the writing of the new Constitution came, in part, from social movements and student groups, who saw the formation of a new trans-sectoral constitutional pact, designed to create robust and consensually founded institutions, as a pathway out of violence.Footnote 74 The writing of the Constitution involved representatives of different social groups, including some—although not all—of the actors in the civil violence, and during the drafting process consultation bodies were institutionalized to mobilize and coordinate civic engagement. Although written in a representative assembly, the Constitution was shaped by a multi-centric constituent power, in which previously marginalized factions, divided by their positions in the long-standing conflict, were integrated into core norm-setting activities. Once drafted, the Constitution endorsed a strong ethic of civil participation (Art 2). In each respect, the Constitution was driven by a pervasive affirmation of political citizenship, and it reflected an outlook that viewed intensified collective participation as a technique for galvanizing society as an aggregate of national citizens and, in so doing, for fortifying national political institutions.

Alongside this, significantly, the Constitution expressed a new ethic of national integration by constructing citizenship, in part, on the basis of global norms. Eventually, the Constitution contributed to the rise of national citizenship in Colombia because it located political participation within a global-legal framework, and it attached the exercise of national citizenship to the enactment of norms, with constitutional force, extracted from the international arena. This link between national citizenship and global law is manifest, as discussed, in the fact that the drafting of the Constitution was strongly influenced by rising international enthusiasm for human rights law. More particularly, however, this link became visible in patterns of constitutional practice that took hold after the Constitution entered force.

To be sure, the 1991 Constitution did not have an immediately solidifying impact on the rival constituencies in Colombian society. In fact, the years after 1991 were marked by the escalation of violence and by the assumption of increased autonomy by the local governance systems constructed by military units, guerrillas, and paramilitaries.Footnote 75 This period witnessed the persistence of clientelistic methods of political mobilization, in which patronage remained a key line of communication between society and government.Footnote 76 Moreover, this period witnessed continuing tendencies to very low electoral participation.Footnote 77 It is thus debatable whether, after the new Constitution took effect, Colombia became a fully nationalized society, with a nationally inclusive and integrative political system. Initially, the idea that the Constitution could imprint a unifying ethic of citizenship onto a deeply fissured society proved illusory.Footnote 78

Over a longer period of time, however, the socially consolidatory objectives of the 1991 Constitution acquired reality, in part at least. Crucially, these objectives were realized, to a large degree, not by decisively political processes, but by a mass of legal exchanges. In fact, the legal system itself began to frame and to facilitate patterns of citizenship practice, which, slowly, created a more generalized and robustly inclusive foundation for the political system in society, forming deepening articulations between the governmental order and actors at different social and regional locations. In this context, acts of citizenship were expressed, not solely—or even primarily—through classical patterns of political participation, but through legal appeals and acts of litigation, often involving reference to global legal principles. As a result, citizens engaged with the political system, not only as political agents, but also, in part, as litigants, closely linked to a global normative order, and interactions mediated through the legal system played a key role in constructing a basis of political integration and legitimation for society as a whole. The legal system began to operate as a semi-autonomous system, and, in so doing, it galvanized a series of equivalents to classical political citizenship roles.

3.2.1 Citizenship Formation 1: the Spread of Tutelas

This distinct form of inner-legal citizenship is seen, first, in the societal penetration of tutela litigation. As discussed, tutela litigation has emerged as a practice in which individual subjects obtain widened access to rights, often exercising tangible impact on legislation and policymaking. Such litigation forms a broad opening between the political system and societal actors, reaching deep into society and forming an expansive integrational base for the political system.

According to official data, more than 7 million tutelas were submitted between 1992 and 2018 in Colombia.Footnote 79 In 1997, tutelas represented 3% of the total of legal actions in Colombia. In 2018, they represented almost 28%, forming the main mechanism used by citizens to enforce their rights..Footnote 80 In this same year, it is calculated that a tutela was filed approximately every minute.Footnote 81 Furthermore, public awareness of tutelas is remarkable. More than 80% of the Colombians are aware of the existence of tutelas, whereas only 20–25% of people are aware of other instruments for collective litigation. Approximately 65.1% of Colombians have a favourable opinion of this mechanism.Footnote 82 Significantly, tutela litigation has broad geographical reach.Footnote 83 Most tutelas are filed in urban areas. However, the number of cases outside large population centres has also increased.Footnote 84 Tutelas address violations in a number of constitutional spheres. Historically, most tutelas have addressed the right to petition, the right to health, and a range of economic, social, and cultural rights. However, claims to other rights have given rise to many tutelas each year. In recent years, tutelas related to the right to petition and to humanitarian assistance have been decreasing. Allegedly, this reduction is due to the Peace Agreements and to measures implemented by institutions created to provide protection for victims of violence (for instance the Unidad para la Atención y Reparación a las Víctimas). Footnote 85 The creation of new mechanisms for pursuing remedies reveals the institutional strengthening of the Colombian legal system and indicates that tutelas may reveal priority areas for defence of rights. In these respects, tutelas have assumed unprecedented importance as a distinct pattern of citizenship practice, acting to create a unified normative and territorial environment for the national political system, linking actors at different societal locations to legislative processes. In view of the fact that, on average, only circa 40% of the population vote in general and plebiscitary elections, tutelas represent a primary channel of socio-political participation and incorporation.Footnote 86

3.2.2 Citizenship Formation 2: Tutelas and New Constitutional Subjects

This distinct form of inner-legal citizenship is evident, second, in the fact that tutela litigation creates political roles for a range of social groups who struggled historically to avail themselves of citizenship rights.Footnote 87 In particular, the Constitutional Court has ruled that, owing to their marginality and vulnerability, certain subjects need to be granted require heightened protection when they engage in legal process, and rights established in tutelas initiated by such subjects should be subject to particularly robust remedies, with strong guarantees for implementation. In the wake of T-025/04, the Constitutional Court elaborated the concept of the ‘subject of special constitutional protection’, which it used to designate groups whose rights require especially secure assurances.Footnote 88 Subjects placed in this category include inter alia displaced people, children, elderly people, prison detainees, women, and ethnic and indigenous groups. Recently, this designation has migrated beyond cases treated by the Constitutional Court, and it has become a maxim of administrative law, such that some collective groups now claim elevated protection from administrative violation.Footnote 89 There is a strong probability that tutelas and other claims filed by these subjects will trigger acts of public policy and legislation to guard their rights and avert further violations, and subjects assuming such protected form possess a legal personality that allows them to act, in effect, as constitutional subjects.

In such jurisprudence, the Court has attempted to fill the historical void of national citizenship, aiming to incorporate all subjects, at least minimally, in a shared structure of normative inclusion.Footnote 90 Indicatively, the Court has ruled that all citizens in Colombian society are entitled to enjoy certain rights, and, for persons whose enjoyment of such rights is impeded, the government has an obligation to take additional steps to facilitate the exercise of rights at the level of a universal minimum.Footnote 91 This concept of the universal minimum was derived, to a large degree, from international law.Footnote 92 In this respect, global law became a functional surrogate for the unifying effects of national citizenship. At the same time, the granting of special protection has meant that subjects in protected categories have been able to assume quite particular forms of constitutional subjectivity and even to use their protected status to generate new rights. For example, indigenous groups have been able to assert their legal personality, not only to preserve given basic rights, but to concretize additional or subsidiary rights—such as rights to indigenous identity, and rights to recognition and protection of traditional medicines.Footnote 93 Moreover, the granting of such protected rights has meant that rights can be transferred to social subjects living in situations analogous to those occupied by already protected subjects, so that the ascription of special protection to one group has generated parallel patterns of subjectivization or personhood amongst similar groups. In some cases, the Constitutional Court has decided that rights established for indigenous communities, as subjects of special constitutional protection, need to be broadened so that they cover other communities, such as African Colombians and even traditional mining communities.Footnote 94 Special protection jurisprudence has thus served to create common thresholds of inclusion for all society. However, this jurisprudence has also given rise to new forms of citizenship and it has allowed new actors to shape the legal form of society. In this respect, litigation formed a mode of citizenship that was specifically adapted to the structure of society. It helped to establish a uniform stratum of national norms to surmount the inherent polycentricity of society, yet it also allowed the exercise of citizenship rights in subjective forms reflecting society’s highly variable inner environments, enabling marginal subjects to obtain access to the political system.

3.2.3 Citizenship Formation 3: Tutelas and Sectoral Citizenship

This distinct form of inner-legal citizenship is seen, third, in the additional patterns of subject formation that occur in tutela litigation.

In some respects, tutelas do not only serve to articulate existing citizens with the political system. They also engender new patterns of political subjectivity and citizenship, and they allow the exercise of citizenship practices in quite spontaneous fashion, often giving rise to entirely new patterns of legal personhood. One result of human rights litigation in Colombia is that persons have begun to acquire a separate constitutional personality in the different functional domains contained in society, and they increasingly form articulations with the political system, not as generic citizens, but in particular sectors of societal interaction—as sectoral citizens. In some ways, the Constitutional Court has promoted tutela jurisprudence to craft a multi-centric sectoral constitution for society as a whole, in which many subjects, often lacking formal legal identity, acquire the force to consolidate constitutional norms with a differentiated, functionally specific emphasis, so that multiple, sectoral patterns of citizenship come into existence. In some such cases, the subject acquiring rights does not formally or materially exist prior to the recognition of the rights in questions, and the recognition of rights actually brings the rights-endowed subjects (citizens) into being.

The Constitutional Court began to construct sectoral constitutional norms in some of its first rulings. In early tutelas, it ruled that the Constitution of 1991 should not be interpreted as a document restricted to classical constitutional functions of placing limits on state power. On the contrary, it argued that the Constitution ‘contains the basic legal order for the diverse sectors of social and political life’. In particular, it stated that the Constitution provides elements of an economic constitution, based in ‘property, labour, enterprise’, which establishes elements of a ‘social constitution’, and it sets out principles for an ecological and a cultural constitution.Footnote 95 Over a longer period, the Court expanded this approach, and it elaborated a series of quite differentiated constitutional orders in separate parts of society. Importantly, these orders were not entirely separate, and all were connected and shaped by the transversal commitment of the Court to give effect to the value of human dignity. Nonetheless, these orders acquired striking autonomy in their own sphere of application.

This tendency can be seen, for example, in the sphere of healthcare. Originally, the right to health was not fully established as a fundamental right in the Constitution. Article 49 of the Constitution creates an obligation for the state to provide healthcare. However, this obligation did not originally create a right protectable by tutela: that is, a justiciable fundamental right. Indeed, the Constitutional Court opined in 1993 that the Constitution ‘does not directly recognize the right to health’.Footnote 96 However, in cases of tutela litigation concerning health rights in the 1990s, the Court established the principle that rights to health should be defined as fundamental and justiciable parts of the constitutional order. In reaching this conclusion, the Court promoted a deliberately constitutional approach to healthcare rights, stating that such rights are immediately enforceable, via tutelas, when they are connected with an ‘immediately applicable fundamental right’, such as, for example, the right to life.Footnote 97 In so doing, the Court constructed fundamental health rights using the principle of connectedness (conexidad). This principle was used to formulate the claim that there are some rights which, although not declared fundamental in the Constitution, are ‘fundamental rights by connectedness’: that is, rights that are constitutionally protected by virtue of their ‘intimate and ineradicable relation with other fundamental rights’.Footnote 98 Ultimately, the Constitutional Court intensified its protection of health rights to declare, simply, that the right to health is a fundamental right.Footnote 99 Such rulings were widely supported by international health law principles.Footnote 100

In these respects, the Constitutional Court established a set of rights that formed a distinct sectoral constitutional order—a health constitution. In so doing, it also promoted the presumption that the mass of exchanges relating to health contains multiple distinct subjects and multiple distinct legal communities, not all of which were initially covered by, or visible in, the formal law of the constitution. The Court expanded the right to health to establish differential rights, with gradations reflecting the vulnerability of implicated parties. It ruled, for instance, that the right to health required particular protection in cases where it was denied to children,Footnote 101 to the aged,Footnote 102 and to persons displaced by the civil conflict.Footnote 103 In these respects, the Court did not only create new constitutional rights: it created new constitutional subjects, health subjects, with distinct personality in the health constitution, able distinctively to claim rights and to affect legislation regarding health rights. The right to health has even been interpreted to recognize a river, the Atrato running through the Choco province, as entitled to protection from contamination, owing largely to its importance for the ecosystem of the region and the health of its inhabitants.Footnote 104 This ruling relied extensively on international norms regarding access to food, and international treaties regarding protection of biodiversity and rights of indigenous communities, especially Convention 169 of the International Labour Organization (ILO 169).

A related logic is evident in tutela cases concerning the environment. The Colombian Constitution contains some positive environmental provisions. However, it does not provide immediate justiciable guarantees for rights to environmental protection. At an early stage in the development of its jurisprudence, nonetheless, the Constitutional Court ruled that it could hear tutela cases regarding environmental damage if these cases addressed environmental questions that caused a potential ‘violation of a fundamental constitutional right, with respect to one or a number of determinate persons’.Footnote 105 In its rulings in environmental tutelas, the Court initially followed a conexidad line of reasoning to establish a right to a healthy environment, arguing that environmental pollution could lead to the denial of ‘fundamental rights’, such as rights to ‘life, personal integrity, intimacy’, or, by extension, ‘health’.Footnote 106 The Court found that, as a matter connected to life and health, the state had an obligation to introduce policies to reduce environmental damage as a ‘priority public service’.Footnote 107 Eventually, the Court declared that environmental rights were of a fundamental nature,Footnote 108 and even that they formed ‘rights of constitutional rank’.Footnote 109 Notably, the determination of such rights was supported by extensive citation from international law.Footnote 110

As in health law, the establishment of constitutional rights in environmental litigation gave rise to a line of jurisprudence, in which certain sectoral subjects acquired new legal visibility. Environmental obligations have acquired particular importance in cases affecting minority communities, such as indigenous populations, especially when their traditional lands are affected. In such cases, the Constitutional Court has found a heightened administrative duty for the government to prevent environmental damage.Footnote 111 In cases where building works, mining activities or developmental projects have risked causing environmental damage, the Court has dictated that there should be provisions for prior consultation with indigenous communities and that due recognition should be shown for their right to cultural integrity.Footnote 112 Notably, such rulings widely relied on international law, especially ILO 169. In some environmental cases, animals have also been configured as legal subjects, entitled to protection from cruelty.Footnote 113 These rights were deemed to flow from the basic constitutional right to ecological balance, from the character of animals as ‘sentient beings’, and from the general environmental interest in the maintenance of biodiversity and the natural equilibrium of species.Footnote 114

A similar sequence of steps can be seen in judicial constructions of the right to education. In the first instance, the 1991 Constitution did not place the right to education under fully enforceable constitutional protection. Article 67 states that education is an individual right. However, this right was not included in the list of rights subject to immediate and binding constitutional guarantees. Despite this, the Constitutional Court established the principle that the right to education possessed a fundamental quality, insisting on its ‘close linkage’ with the basic values enunciated in the Constitution, and it concluded that the right to education could be subject to tutela.Footnote 115 The Court also used the doctrine of the block of constitutionality to cement this right,Footnote 116 and relevant jurisprudence was marked by broad use of international law.Footnote 117 Over a longer period, the basic right to education was expanded to generate more differentiated rights, as the Court ruled that the government was under obligation to offer education that was available, accessible, acceptable, and adaptable: the right to education acquired four subsidiary characteristics.Footnote 118 This implied, for example, that the right to education was relatively neutral to the social location of the claimants to this right, and the government was expected to offer education to all social groups, even in remote regions.Footnote 119

As above, the emergent education constitution in Colombia provides recognition for new legal persons, as subjects of the education constitution, and it enables persons to shape and construct new constitutional rights. Naturally, the right to education is particularly entrenched for children. However, disabled persons and persons with learning difficulties are perceived as educational subjects with elevated constitutional protection, who require particularly strong guarantees of access to education.Footnote 120 Indigenous population groups have also acquired a distinct personality in this regard, and they are recognized as possessing a right to a ‘special system’ of education, tailored to their cultural needs, flowing from the right to identity.Footnote 121 In many instances, such rights were created through a direct articulation between national and international legal norms.Footnote 122

This list of sectoral constitutions and sectoral constitutional subjects in Colombian law is not exhaustive. However, developments in health law, environmental law, and education law have an exemplary quality. These constitutions have evolved in spontaneous fashion; in many cases, they have been developed on contingent foundations, and they do not extract authority from a clearly positivized set of legal norms. Above all, these constitutions have been created by acts of sectoral citizenship, in which litigation concerning domain-specific rights creates new avenues for legal inclusion and law production. In the construction of these constitutions, a condition of sectoral citizenship emerges alongside more classical majoritarian patterns of interest representation. In this process, the construction of sectoral norms by distinct functional subjects replaces the representation of the people as a collective actor, and persons enter the political system through multiple channels of articulation, usually linked to litigation for particular global rights. This enables rights and forms of subjecthood to appear that could not easily take hold in more conventional legislative systems. In the context of a society marked historically by uneven nationalization of citizenship practices and by weak capacity of state institutions to interact with citizens in unitary form, the sectoralization of citizenship creates compensatory, socially proportioned openings for legal recognition and participation in law making. The political form of the citizen thus emerges, eminently, through legal actions, and the representation of society through citizenship rights occurs, primarily, as an inner-legal process.

3.2.4 Citizenship Formation 4: Public Interest Litigation

This distinct form of inner-legal citizenship is seen, fourth, in the expansion of legal agency in Colombia. One implication of the growing autonomy of the legal system is that actors across society have recognized that litigation is a core domain of collective norm formation, and political groups and social movements increasingly engage in litigation to obtain legislative outcomes and to establish new rights of recognition. Consequently, the Constitutional Court has acted as a ‘catalyst’ for waves of legal mobilization—for example, for indigenous rights, gender rights, and ethnic rights.Footnote 123 Indicatively, T-025/04 was filed by a collective litigator, and other leading tutelas have been strategically filed to gain heightened recognition for collective subjects.

Alongside the growth of tutelas, the period since 1991, and especially up to 2010, saw a rise in public interest litigation, in administrative law.Footnote 124 Like tutelas, public interest litigation in Colombia now forms a core constitutional instrument for securing rights, especially historically unconsolidated rights, such as environmental rights and healthcare rights.Footnote 125 One environmental case, the famous Rio Bogotá case, led to a ruling with very broad legislative reach, which both instituted and financed an integrated and co-ordinated system for decontaminating and managing water supplies around Bogotá.Footnote 126 The importance of public interest litigation in Colombia is tied to the fact that, under Law 472, Art. 40 (1998), public agencies are required to act in accordance with broadly defined standards of administrative morality, which impose moral obligations on all organs of government.Footnote 127 On this basis, society is deemed to have a collective interest in the morality of governmental and quasi-governmental agents and even a right to moral administration. Litigation against public bodies can be initiated when this right is not recognized. This right has very broadly applicable force, and it provides wide standing for litigants in public interest cases. Moreover, this right provides substantial scope for litigants to affect public policies, as it presumes that policies must be sensitive to public interests and can be appealed on the grounds that they are not.Footnote 128 International law has been commonly invoked to strengthen claims made in public interest cases.Footnote 129

The democratically formative role of public interest litigation in Colombia has been accentuated by the Constitutional Court, which has accorded to such litigation a clearly political, constitutive force. In some leading opinions, which define the scope of public interest litigation, the Court has declared that public interest cases should be encouraged as an instrument for promoting ‘law based in participation and solidarity’. Most importantly, it has construed litigation of this type as a practice for protecting interests of a very strictly collective nature, of relevance for all citizens, not attached to specific subjects, and not registered through damages to clearly identified rights.Footnote 130 In leading relevant case law, it has been ruled that, in public interest cases, matters should be treated that do not have a ‘subjective or individual content’, and which do not relate to a ‘damage that can be repaired subjectively’.Footnote 131 In consequence, such cases are focused on ‘collective rights, in contrast to individual rights’: on rights that ‘belong to the entire community’, and whose holder ‘is a plurality of persons’.Footnote 132 Standing for filing such cases, consequently, depends solely on membership in the national community, and no other claim apart from interests inherent in citizenship is required to justify legal proceedings.Footnote 133 Collective litigation is thus clearly envisioned as a forum, in which uncertainly defined subjects can take legal shape, and emergent social concerns can be transmitted towards the political system. In some ways, it forms an ultra-sensitive channel of political communication, which promotes highly diffuse citizenship practices and opens the political system to interests not easily expressed by conventional political subjects.

None of these observations is intended to imply that judicial interactions devised a miraculous remedy for problems of weak institutional integration or incomplete elaboration of citizenship rights in Colombia. In some respects, however, the rise in litigation, especially in tutelas, can be seen to have modified, not only the legal system, but also the legitimational structure of the polity, creating compensatory conditions of national integration and national citizenship in a society historically marked by low inclusion of citizens. In particular, human rights, based in global norms but constructed and protected through tutelas, form an inter-group vocabulary of legal understanding, which connects different parts of society, and links social agents, at different societal positions, to the political system.Footnote 134 Through these various processes, Colombia has assumed the form of a democracy that contains multiple subjects (citizens) capable of participating in legal/political activities, such that the range of persons able to play a role in the construction of legal norms has been greatly widened. This means that the political system is able to produce and legitimate legislation in many ways, and it is articulated with persons requiring legislation in its environment through many channels, each of which is accessed by a range of different subjects. Legal exchanges form a key line of political communication, in which social demands are translated into law, and legal exchanges themselves create new acts of legislation, new constitutional norms, and new legal subjects (citizens). The autonomous force of law, in other words, is not a limit on democracy: the legal system itself, sustained by strong presumptions in favour of global human rights, is the basic source of democratic formation and integration, and it even constructs the subjects on which democracy relies. The political system has evolved as a multi-articulated democracy, in which new channels of interaction, partly constructed within the law itself, replace classical patterns of participation and will formation.

The political institutions in Colombian society struggled, historically, to generate democratic citizenship on national foundations alone. In fact, purely national political institutions did not create a fully nationalized society. Eventually, more stable patterns of citizenship and stable patterns of national inclusion began to emanate from exchanges within the legal system, acting at a heightened level of autonomy. National citizenship was created, in part, through an alignment of national law to global law, and global law was used to design adaptive models of national citizenship which national institutions themselves had not established.

4 Conclusion

In many respects, Colombia is a paradigmatic example of polity with a transnational judicial constitution, usually seen as comprising a set of global legal norms that limit political-democratic modes of agency. However, the case of Colombia demands that we re-formulate our approach to constitutions shaped by autonomous interactions between national law and global law. What is discernible in Colombia is that the distinctive global-legal form of the constitutional order only contradicts norms of democratic legitimacy if democracy is understood in sociologically unreflected categories. The Colombian Constitution has in fact created a foundation for the emergence of a distinctive pattern of democracy, in which global legal rights stimulate the formation of multiple lines of articulation between the political system and society. In this respect, litigation appears as an important source of norms with de facto constitutional rank, and litigation triggers the emergence of new patterns of citizenship. As a result, the Constitution needs to be seen as a document that greatly facilitates the exercise of participatory political agency, locking the political system into its societal environment by opening up multiple processes of socio-political engagement and norm construction, and even materializing new political subjects.

Analysis of Colombian constitutionalism tells us that common approaches to judicial constitutionalism are sociologically naïve in their understandings of politics and democratic practice. This model may appear as a deficient form of democracy to perspectives that insist that majority-mandated legislation is the sole authorized expression of the popular will.Footnote 135 If democracy is viewed as a political order that maximizes popular participation and allows a maximum number of persons to recognize laws as outcomes of their own engagement, the judicial-constitutional model can easily, in some settings, realize democratic normative expectations more fully than classical democratic systems. This model gives reality to the claim in early sociology that democracy is a system of consensual inclusion, in which rights of citizenship are exercised and construct legitimacy for law in multiple fashion. In this model, access to law making depends, not on the possession of a majoritarian mandate, but on the capacity of actors to challenge for and exercise globally acknowledged rights, so that rights provide thresholds of legitimate participation and pre-figure outcomes of such participation.Footnote 136 In the case of Colombia, the rise of a transnational judicial constitutionalism has tended to enhance the quality of the political system as a distinctive public order, open to citizens at different locations in society and capable of extending an overarching system of norms across society. By contrast, in comparable societies that have recently abandoned judicial constitutionalism in favour of more direct models of mobilization, national political systems have almost invariably begun to show symptoms of privatism and patrimonialism as techniques for generating societal support.Footnote 137 Clearly, many forms of political communication that have evolved in Colombia will simply disappear if the autonomous power of the legal system is reduced.

In a world in which many democracies have suddenly become fragile, it is important to avoid burdening democratic political systems with the expectation that they comply with legitimational expectations that are not matched to actual patterns of integration and subject formation in society. The act of looking for the people as a fully implicated political subject in democracy, lying somewhere beneath the system of equivalence on which democracy often depends, can easily destroy the complex, compensatory forms, in which democratic citizenship becomes real. The future of democracy itself may well depend on the use of a sociologically measured perspective for understanding democracy, able to identify varied and contingent ways in which global law articulates premises for the legitimation of laws in national societies and for national citizenship more widely. The future of Colombian democracy, currently under threat because of its judicial bias, may have implications that extend far beyond Colombia itself.