Skip to main content
Log in

From the Method of Division to the Theory of Transformations: Thompson After Aristotle, and Aristotle After Thompson

  • Thematic Issue Article: D’Arcy Thompson’s Conceptual Legacy
  • Published:
Biological Theory Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Aristotle’s influence on D’Arcy Thompson was praised by Thompson himself and has been recognized by others in various respects, including the aesthetic and normative dimensions of biology, and the multicausal explanation of living forms. This article focuses on the relatedness of organic forms, one of the core problems addressed by both Aristotle’s History of Animals (HA), and the renowned chapter of Thompson’s On Growth and Form (G&F), “On the Theory of Transformations, or the Comparison of Related Forms.” We contend that, far from being an incidental inspiration stemming from Thompson’s classicist background, his translation of HA played a pivotal role in developing his theory of transformations. Furthermore, we argue that Thompson’s interpretation of the Aristotelian method of comparison challenges the prevailing view of Aristotle as the founder of “typological essentialism,” and is a key episode in the revision of this narrative. Thompson understood that the method Aristotle used in HA to compare animal forms is better comprehended as a “method of transformations,” leading to a morphological arrangement of animal diversity, as opposed to a taxonomical classification. Finally, we examine how this approach to the relatedness of forms lay the foundation for a causal understanding of parts and their interconnections. Although Aristotle and Thompson emphasized distinct types of causes, we contend that they both differ in a fundamental sense from the one introduced by Darwin’s theory of natural selection, which was formulated as a solution to the species problem rather than the form problem. We conclude that Thompson’s interpretation of Aristotle’s approach to form comparison has not only impacted contemporary scholarship on Aristotle’s biology, but revitalized a perspective that has regained significance due to the resurgence of the problem of form in evo-devo.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. These remarks of Thompson’s are admittedly speculative. Aristotle’s description is vague, and it is not clear which species he is referring to. See Thompson’s notes 5, 6 to HA 565a23-28 and note 1 to 565b6 (Thompson 1910).

  2. A related controversy Thompson didn’t comment on concerns the chronological and conceptual relationship of HA and the other biological treatises. Balme argued that, “HA was written by Aristotle during and following his stay on Lesbos, and after writing the other biological treatises” (Balme 1987a, p. 17). Lennox (1996) has noted that one needs to distinguish when and where research was done from when and where treatises were written. Moreover, even if HA was written after the Parts of Animals and Generation of Animals, the research there recorded corresponds to the preliminary stages of inquiry according to Aristotle HA 491a7-15).

  3. Moreover, in the 1960s the problem of form got dissolved in the framework of the Modern Synthesis, either by conflating it with that of adaptation, or by reducing it to the classification or the systematic description of diversity.

  4. The independence between the definition and the identification of species implies that essentialism and fixism were not intrinsically linked, as shown by the fact that Linnaeus himself speculated on the evolution of new species through hybridization among genera.

  5. As indicated above, Aristotle applies the method of the more and the less not only to parts, but also to activities. In several books of HA dealing with methods and processes associated with successful reproduction (books V, VI, and IX), Aristotle discusses reproductive organs in forms of various kinds, but much of what we find in these books, as well as books VII and VIII, is about animal behavior in relationship to their environments. These books might be interpreted as a proto-ethology and a proto-ecology more than as a proto-morphology.

  6. For example, Thompson translates 490b9-10 as follows: “There is another genus of the hard-shelled kind, which is called oyster; another of the soft-shelled kind.” In this passage, “another genus” translates ἄλλο γένος, whereas “the hard-shelled kind” translates τὸ τῶν ὀστρακοδέρµων [γένος] and “the soft-shelled kind” τὸ τῶν µαλακοστράκων [γἐνος]. In these two cases, γένος must be supplied, but it is the obvious complement for τὸ in both cases.

  7. For details, see the introduction to Peck’s (1965) translation of HA I-III, pp. v-xxxii.

  8. While the application of the method of connections led to the realization of its limits (for instance, certain elements might be fused or even be absent in certain groups as compared to others, such as digits in the horse limb), the topological method allowed transit across widely (apparently) unrelated animal forms.

  9. Aristotle does make “analogical” comparisons across kinds, such as between lung and gills, between feathers and scales, or between different kinds of wings (e.g., insect and bird wings). But these comparisons are based on function and not on shape or structure, what Owen called analogies as opposed to homologies.

  10. Aristotle writes that despite the apparently striking morphological differences in the location of their limbs (cephalopods have their feet towards the “front,” while in testacean mollusks limbs project out from the side), when looking at the disposition of internal parts, “the configuration of the body” is alike. And by this likeness he means, in modern parlance, topological sameness, since a topological deformation (bending a straight line) is used to transform one digestive tract into the other (PA IV.684b20-25) (see Lennox 2002, pp. 311–312).

  11. There is a debate among Aristotle scholars regarding whether the conceptual schema genos/eidos is applicable to animal groups, such as birds or eagles (Balme 1987b), or parts, such as beaks or wings (Pellegrin 1987).

  12. While Aristotle’s understanding of correlations is indissociable from his causal interpretation of these correlations, the identification of correlations between parts has proved to be one of the greatest tools of morphology to unravel functional and developmental correlations (Olson and Miller 1958). As Thompson puts it: “if … diverse and dissimilar fishes can be referred as a whole to identical functions of very different coordinate systems, this fact will of itself constitute a proof that variation has proceeded on definite and orderly lines, that a comprehensive ‘law of growth’ has pervaded the whole structure in its integrity, and that some more or less simple and recognisable system of forces has been at work” (Thompson 1917, p. 728).

  13. This does not mean that the comparative study of form cannot be used for phylogenetic purposes. On the contrary, the reconstruction of phylogenetic relationships makes extensive use of morphological data. But the labor of comparative biology is epistemologically prior to the establishment of genealogical relationships, given that they are inferred from the acknowledgment of similarity among parts, and not the other way around (Patterson 1982; Rieppel and Kearney 2002). In the context of evo-devo, it has also been argued that the developmental explanation of homology depends on the previous identification of structural units, based on morphological criteria (Roth 1991; Wagner 1996). In this sense, evolutionary morphologists today seek to identify homologs by means of “operational definitions,” i.e., definitions that are necessary to reach a causal explanation without being themselves explanatory (Bolker 2000).

  14. This functional approach to living beings by no means entails that Aristotle was a Panglossian, a priori teleologist. On the contrary, he explicitly objects to the idea that every difference among animal forms should be explained in teleological terms. Instead, he argues that some biological traits necessarily derive from the formal and functional properties of other parts (PA IV.677a16-19). See footnote 15 for an example.

  15. For instance, in discussing a species of octopus with only one, instead of two, rows of suckers on its “arms” he explicitly explains it as a consequence of structure—this is a small octopus with very slender arms, so there is only room for one row of suckers. He then says: “It is not, then, because it is best that they have this feature, but because it is necessary owing to the distinctive account of their substantial being” (PA IV.9 685b12ff). That is, not only does he invoke a structural feature as necessitating the attribute in question, he is claiming that that structural feature is a defining feature of the nature of this kind of octopus, and he is explicitly ruling out a teleological explanation.

  16. “[P]aradigm set up in Heaven”: Thompson is quoting Plato’s Republic IX.592b2.

  17. Both Walsh (2015) and Austin (2018) refer to the contemporary reading of genos and eidos among Aristotle’s scholars.

References

  • Amundson R (1998) Typology reconsidered: two doctrines on the history of Evolutionary Biology. Biol Philos 13(2):153–177

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Amundson R (2005) The changing role of the embryo in evolutionary thought: roots of evo-devo. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Arthur W (2023) D’Arcy Thompson’s morphological transformations: issues of causality and dimensionality. Biol Theory. https://doi.org/10.1007/s13752-023-00438-0

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Austin CJ (2018) Essence in the age of evolution: a new theory of natural kinds. Routledge, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Balme DM (1962) Γένος and Ει̑δος in Aristotle’s biology. Classical Q 12(1):81–98

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Balme DM (1962) Γένος and Ει̑δος in Aristotle’s biology. The Classical Quarterly, 12(1):81–98. http://www.jstor.org/stable/638031

  • Balme DM (1987a) The place of biology in Aristotle’s philosophy. Philosophical issues in Aristotle’s Biology. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 9–20

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Balme DM (1987b) Aristotle’s use of division and differentiae. In: Gotthelf A, Lennox JG (eds) Philosophical issues in Aristotle’s Biology. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 69–89

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Benson RH (1982) Deformation, Da Vinci’s concept of form, and the analysis of events in evolutionary history. In: Montanaro Gallitelli E (ed) Palaeontology, essential of historical geology: proceedings of the first international meeting on “Palaeontology, Essential of Historical Geology.” Venice, Fondazione Giorgio Cini, 2–4 June 1981. S.T.E.M. Mucchi, Modena, pp 241–277

  • Bolker JA (2000) Modularity in development and why it matters to evo-devo. Am Zool 40(5):770–776

    Google Scholar 

  • Bookstein FL (1977) The study of shape transformation after D’Arcy Thompson. Math Biosci 34:177–219

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bookstein FL (1982) Foundations of morphometrics. Annu Rev Ecol Syst 13(1):451–470

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bookstein FL (1998) A hundred years of morphometrics. Acta Zool Academiae Scientarium Hung 44(1–2):7–59

    Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt I (2003) Homology in comparative, molecular, and evolutionary developmental biology: the radiation of a concept. J Exp Zool 299(1):9–17

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brigandt I (2007) Typology now: homology and developmental constraints explain evolvability. Biol Philos 22(5):709–725

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cain AJ (1958) Logic and memory in Linnaeus’s system of taxonomy. Proceedings of the Linnean Society of London, 169(1–2):144–163. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1095-8312.1958.tb00819.x

  • Camardi G (2001) Richard Owen, morphology and evolution. J Hist Biol 34(3):481–515

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chung C (2003) On the origin of the typological/population distinction in Ernst Mayr’s changing views of species, 1942-1959. Stud History Philos Sci Part C: Stud History Philos Biol Biomedical Sci 34(2):277–296

    Google Scholar 

  • Coleman W (1998) Morphology in the evolutionary synthesis. In: Mayr E, Provine WB (eds) The evolutionary synthesis. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, pp 174–180

  • Crubellier M, Pellegrin P (2002) Aristotle. Le philosophe et les savoirs. Éditions du Seuil, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin C (1859) On the origin of species by means of natural selection. John Murray, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Dresow M (2020) Re-forming morphology: two attempts to rehabilitate the problem of form in the first half of the twentieth century. J History Biology 2020 53(2):231–248

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eble GJ (2003) Morphological modularity and macroevolution: conceptual and empirical aspects. In: Callebaut W, Rasskin-Gutman D (eds) Modularity: understanding the development and evolution of natural complex systems. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 221–238

    Google Scholar 

  • Ereshefsky M (2001) The poverty of the Linnaean hierarchy: a philosophical study of biological taxonomy. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Furth M (1987) Aristotle’s biological universe: an overview. In: Gotthelf A, Lennox JG (eds) Philosophical issues in Aristotle’s biology. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 9–20

    Google Scholar 

  • Gayon J (1998) La marginalisation de la forme dans la biologie de l’évolution. Bull De La Société D’histoire Et d’épistémologie Des Sci De La Vie 5(2):133–168

    Google Scholar 

  • Geoffroy Saint-Hilaire E (1818) Philosophie anatomique: des organes respiratoires sous le rapport de la détermination et de l’Identité de leurs pièces osseuses. Méquignon–Marvis, Paris

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gotthelf A (1987) Aristotle’s conception of final causality. In: Gotthelf A, Lennox JG (eds) Philosophical issues in Aristotle’s biology. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 204–242

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gould SJ (1971) D’Arcy Thompson and the science of form. New Literary History 2(2):229–258

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Houle D, Pélabon C, Wagner GP, Hansen TF (2011) Measurement and meaning in biology. Q Rev Biology 86(1):3–34

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hull DL (1965) The effect of essentialism on taxonomy–two thousand years of stasis (I). Br J Philos Sci 15(60):314–326

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jaeger W (1948) Aristotle: fundamentals of the history of his development. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Kemp M (2011) Loving insight: D’Arcy Thompson’s Aristotle and the soul in nature. In: Taliaferro C, Evans L (eds) Turning images in philosophy, science, and religion: a new book of nature. Oxford Academic, Oxford, pp 5–24

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lee H (1948) Place-names and the date of Aristotle’s biological works. Classical Q 42(3–4):61–67

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lennox J (1980) Aristotle on genera, species, and the more and the less. J Hist Biol 13(2):321–346

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lennox JG (1987) Kinds, forms of kinds, and the more and the less in Aristotle’s biology. In: Lennox J, Gotthelf A (eds) Philosophical issues in Aristotle’s biology. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 339–359

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lennox JG (1996) Aristotle’s biological development: the Balme hypothesis. In: Wians W (ed) Philosophical development, problems and prospects. Roman and Littlefield, London, pp 228–248

    Google Scholar 

  • Lennox JG (2001) History and philosophy of science: a phylogenetic approach. História, Ciências, Saúde-Manguinhos, 8(3):655–669. https://doi.org/10.1590/s0104-59702001000400008

  • Lennox JG (2002) Aristotle: On the parts of animals I?IV. Clarendon Aristotle Series. Oxford University Press, Oxford

  • Lennox JG (2005) Getting a science going: Aristotle on entry level kinds. In: Wolters G (ed) Homo Sapiens und Homo Faber (Festschrift Mittelstrass). Walter De Gruyter, Berlin, pp 87–100

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lennox JG (2009) Bios, praxis and the unity of life. Aristotele: was ist Leben? Aristoteles’ Anschauungen Zur Entstehungsweise Und Funktion Von Leben, Akten Der Tagung Vom 23–26. August 2006 in Bamberg. Franz Steiner Verlag, Bamberg, Stuttgart, pp 239–259

    Google Scholar 

  • Lennox JG (2017a) An Aristotelian philosophy of biology: form, function and development. Acta Philosophica: Rivista Internazionale Di Filosofia 26(1):33–52

    Google Scholar 

  • Lennox JG (2017b) Aristotle and Darwin: antagonists or kindred spirits? Philosophic Exch 46(1), Art. 3.

  • Lennox JG (2018) Aristotle, dissection, and generation. In: Falcon A, Lefebvre D (eds) Aristotle’s generation of animals: a critical guide. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 249–272

    Google Scholar 

  • Love AC (2006) Reflections on the middle stages of EvoDevo’s ontogeny. Biol Theory 1(1):94–97

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Love AC (2009) Typology reconfigured: from the metaphysics of essentialism to the epistemology of representation. Acta Biotheoretica 57(1):51–75

  • Love AC, Raff RA (2003) Knowing your ancestors: themes in the history of evo-devo. Evol Dev 5(4):327–330

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McGhee GR (1999) Theoretical morphology: the concept and its applications. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Minelli A (2021) On the nature of organs and organ systems – a chapter in the history and philosophy of biology. Front Ecol Evol 9:745564

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mitteroecker P, Gunz P (2009) Advances in geometric morphometrics. Evol Biol 36(2):235–247

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Müller-Wille S (2007) Collection and collation: theory and practice of Linnaean botany. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 38(3):541–562

  • Müller-Wille S (2011) Making sense of essentialism. Critical Quarterly 53(4):61–67. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-8705.2011.02022.x

  • Nuño de la Rosa L (2010) Becoming organisms: the organisation of development and the development of organisation. Hist Philos Life Sci 32(2–3):289–315

  • Nuyens F (1948) L’Évolution De La Psychologie d’Aristote. Éditions de l’Institut Supérieure de Philosophie, Leuven

    Google Scholar 

  • Olson E, Miller R (1958) Morphological integration. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Patterson C (1982) Morphological characters and homology. In: Joysey KA, Friday AE (eds) Problems of phylogenetic reconstruction. Academic Press, New York, p 21–74

    Google Scholar 

  • Peck AL (1965) Introduction to his translation of Aristotle, History of Animals, books I-III., books I-III. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Pellegrin P (1982) La classification des animaux chez Aristote: statut de la biologie et unité de l’aristotélisme. Les Belles Lettres, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Pellegrin P (1987) Logical difference and biological difference: the unity of Aristotle’s thought. In: Lennox JG, Gotthelf A (eds) Philosophical issues in Aristotle’s biology. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 313–338

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Popper K (1945) The open society and its enemies. Routledge, London

  • Raup DM (1966) Geometric analysis of shell coiling: general problems. J Paleontol 40(5):1178–1190

    Google Scholar 

  • Richards RA (2010) The species problem: A philosophical analysis. Cambridge University Press

  • Richter S, Wirkner CS (2014) A research program for evolutionary morphology. J Zoological Syst Evolutionary Res 52(4):338–350

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rieppel O (2006) Type in morphology and phylogeny. J Morphol 267(5):528–535

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rieppel O (2007) Homology: a philosophical and biological perspective. Handbook of Paleoanthropology, pp 217–240

  • Rieppel O, Kearney M (2002) Similarity. Biol J Linn Soc 75(1):59–82

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roth VL (1991) Homology and hierarchies: problems solved and unresolved. J Evol Biol 4(2):167–194

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ruse M (1979) The Darwinian revolution: science red in tooth and claw. University of Chicago, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell ES (1916) Form and function: a contribution to the history of animal morphology. John Murray, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell ES (1930) The interpretation of development and heredity. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Shubin NH, Alberch P (1986) A morphogenetic approach to the origin and basic organization of the tetrapod limb. Evol Biol 20:319–387

    Google Scholar 

  • Sloan PR (2009) Originating species: Darwin on the species problem. In: Ruse M, Richards RJ (eds) The Cambridge companion to the origin of species. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 67–86

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober E (1980) Evolution, population thinking, and essentialism. Philos Sci 47(3):350–383

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stone JR (1997) The spirit of D’Arcy Thompson dwells in empirical morphospace. Math Biosci 142(1):13–30

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson DW (1895) A glossary of Greek birds. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson DW (1910) Aristotle: History of animals (Historia Animalium). In: Smith JA, Ross WD (eds) The Works of Aristotle Translated into English, Vol. IV. Clarendon Press, Oxford

  • Thompson DW (1913) On Aristotle as a biologist. With a prooemion on Herbert Spencer. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson DW (1917) On growth and form. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson DW (1921) Natural science. Aristotle. In: Livingstone RW (ed) The legacy of Greece. Clarendon Press, Oxford, pp 137–162

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson DW (1929) Excess and defect: or the little more and the little less. Mind 38(149):43–55

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson DW (1940) Science and the classics. An address to the Classical Association at Cardiff; 9th April 1921. In: Thompson DW (ed) Science and the classics. Oxford University Press, London, pp 1–36

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson DW (1947) A glossary of Greek fishes. Geoffrey Cumberlege, Oxford University Press, Oxford

  • Thompson RD (1958) The scholar-naturalist, 1860–1948. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Thom R (1990) Homéomères et anhoméomères en théorie biologique d’Aristote à Aujourd’Hui. In: Devereux D, Pellegrin P (eds) Biologie, Logique et Métaphysique chez aristote. Actes Du Séminaire C.N.R.S. -N.S.F. Oléron 28 juin-3 juillet 1987. Éditions du CNRS, Paris, pp 491–512

    Google Scholar 

  • Wagner GP (1989) The biological homology concept. Ann Rev Ecol Syst 20(1):51–69

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wagner GP (1996) Homologues, natural kinds and the evolution of modularity. Am Zool 36(1):36–43. https://doi.org/10.1093/icb/36.1.36

  • Wagner GP (2014) Homology, genes, and evolutionary innovation. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Walsh D (2006) Evolutionary essentialism. Br J Philos Sci 57:425–448

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walsh D (2015) Organisms, agency, and evolution. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wilkins JS (2011) Species : a history of the idea. University of California Press

  • Winsor MP (2006a) Linnaeus’s biology was not essentialist. Ann Mo Bot Gard 93(1):2–7

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Winsor MP (2006b) The creation of the essentialism story: an exercise in metahistory. Hist Philos Life Sci 28(2):149–174

    Google Scholar 

  • Witteveen J (2015) A temporary oversimplification: Mayr, Simpson, Dobzhansky, and the origins of the typology/population dichotomy (part 1 of 2). Studies in history and philosophy of Science Part C: studies in history and philosophy of Biological and Biomedical sciences. 54:20–33

  • Witteveen J (2016) A temporary oversimplification: Mayr, Simpson, Dobzhansky, and the origins of the typology/population dichotomy (part 2 of 2). Studies in history and philosophy of Science Part C: studies in history and philosophy of Biological and Biomedical sciences. 57:96–105

  • Young BA (1993) On the necessity of an archetypal concept in morphology: with special reference to the concepts of structure and homology. Biol Philos 8(2):225–248

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

LNR expresses her gratitude to Alan Love and Sahotra Sarkar for extending an invitation to the workshop “Conceptual Legacy of ‘On Growth and Form’” in St Andrews, Scotland, where she delivered an oral presentation connected to this article. The authors would also like to acknowledge Alan Love and two anonymous reviewers, for their insightful comments that contributed significantly to enhancing the content.

Funding

LNR received financial support from the Spanish Ministry of Science and Innovation (project # PID2021-127184NB-I00).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Laura Nuño de la Rosa.

Ethics declarations

Conflicting Interests

The authors have no conflicts of interest to declare.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Nuño de la Rosa, L., Lennox, J.G. From the Method of Division to the Theory of Transformations: Thompson After Aristotle, and Aristotle After Thompson. Biol Theory (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13752-023-00450-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13752-023-00450-4

Keywords

Navigation