Skip to main content
Log in

Cooperation in Dynamic Games with Asymmetric Players: The Role of Social Preferences

  • Published:
Dynamic Games and Applications Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

I study a two-player repeated game where payoffs are asymmetric. Attempts to form cooperative agreements in such an environment, for example by pro-rating actions relative to the one-shot Nash equilibrium, have generally struggled in practice. I show that cooperative arrangements when payoff functions are asymmetric tend to disproportionately favor the larger player. Incorporating social concerns, either via envious feelings on the part of the smaller player or altruistic feelings on the part of the larger player, shift quasi-cooperative incentives toward outcomes that are more favorable to the smaller player.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Source: Author’s calculations. The figure plots the ratio of the larger player’s share of actions under cooperation \(s_1^c\) to its share under the Nash equilibrium \(s_1^N\), where \(s_1^z = \frac{x_1^z}{x_1^z + x_2^z}, z = c, N\), against the player’s payoff advantage \({\upalpha }\). Cooperation based on grim strategy. Values larger than 1 indicate that player 1 receives a larger share in the cooperative regime than in the Nash equilibrium

Fig. 2

Source: Author’s calculations. The figure plots the ratio of the larger player’s share of actions under cooperation \(s_1^c\) to its share under the Nash equilibrium \(s_1^N\), where \(s_1^z = \frac{x_1^z}{x_1^z + x_2^z}, z = c, N\), against the player’s payoff advantage \({\upalpha }\). Cooperation based on penal code strategy. Values larger than 1 indicate that player 1 receives a larger share in the cooperative regime than in the Nash equilibrium

Fig. 3

The figure plots the two players’ best-response function with and without social preferences. Solid lines depict best-response functions without social preferences. Long-dashed line depicts player 2’s best-response function with social preferences (i.e., \(\lambda _2 < 0\)). Dashed line depicts player 1’s best-response function with social preferences (i.e., \(\lambda _1 > 0\)). Nash equilibrium without social preferences depicted by circle. Nash equilibrium when player 1 does not have social preferences but player 2 does depicted by square. Nash equilibrium when both players have social preferences depicted by triangle

Fig. 4

Source: Author’s calculations. The figure plots the smaller player’s share of actions under cooperation, \(s_2 = \frac{x_2^c}{x_1^c + x_2^c}\), against player 1’s payoff advantage \({\upalpha }\). Solid line shows relation when neither player has social preferences. Dashed line shows relation when player 2 has moderate social preferences. Long-dashed line shows relation when player 2 has larger social preferences

Fig. 5

Source: Author’s calculations. The figure plots the smaller player’s share of actions under cooperation, \(s_2 = \frac{x_2^c}{x_1^c + x_2^c}\), against player 1’s payoff advantage \({\upalpha }\). Solid line shows relation when neither player has social preferences. Dashed line shows relation when player 1 has moderate social preferences. Long-dashed line shows relation when player 1 has larger social preferences

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1.    United States v. Socony-Vacuum Oil Co., 310 US 150 (1940), reversing 105 F.2d 809 (7th Cir. 1939), reversing 23 F. Supp. 937 (W.D. Wisc. 1938).

  2.    The Saudis again honored their quota, while Iran produced slightly more than their allocated amount (2454 bpd). By contrast, Venezuela’s substantially exceeded their quota, producing 1852 bpd. See [3, Ch. 4] for discussion.

  3.    It is not clear that signatories could be forced to remain in any agreement—witness former President Trump’s recent decision to extract the USA from the Paris Agreement; and in any event the actions in the second stage are what really matter.

  4.    Examples of papers that allow for dynamic interaction include Dockner and van Long [14], Barrett [7], Rubio and Ulph [32], de Zeeuw [12], Mason et al. [29].

  5.    A second topic for consideration is the nature of the repeated game strategy. While the strategy used in Duffy and Muñoz García [15]—the grim strategy—is often used in the literature, Axelrod [5] suggests a potentially important role for strategies that are more forgiving. To that end, I consider both the grim strategy—under which defection yields perennial “punishment”—and a penal code strategy—which punishes for one period, and then relents in the event that all parties play in accordance with the strategy.

  6.    A simple condition that ensures this feature of reaction functions is \(\frac{\partial {\uppi }_1(y,y)}{\partial x_1} > \frac{\partial {\uppi }_2(y,y)}{\partial x_2}\).

  7.    Qualitatively similar results emerge in a repeated game with unknown endpoint, if \({\updelta }\) is interpreted as the probability the game will continue one more period. Alternatively, a collusive regime could emerge if players believe there is a positive probability that their rival is irrational [20, 27].

  8.    Note that, by construction, \(x_i^N = R_i(x_j^N), i = 1,2.\)

  9.    Two caveats apply. First, the Nash equilibrium satisfies the pair of conditions Eqs. (1)–(2); as there will be combinations that raise both players’ payoffs so long as \({\updelta } > 0\), I focus on the more cooperative combination. Second, for sufficiently large discount values the players can achieve what we might call “full cooperation,” namely combinations where one player’s payoffs are maximized subject to a minimum payoff constraint for the rival. I suppose the discount factor is too small to engender such an outcome in the discussion below.

  10.    I note that \(x_i^r< x_i^c < x_i^p\), for both i = 1, 2: the player who is being punished lowers its action while the punishing player raises its action, relative to the carrot action [29, 31].

  11.    It is algebraically tedious to characterize these various constraints. The code for these numerical analyses, which were conducted in MATLAB, is available upon request.

  12.    Recall that \(R_1 > R_2\).

  13.    [35, p. 417] describe a structure where “motivation can be described by a utility function depending on own payoff and deviation from fairness.”

  14.    The framework Fehr and Schmidt [18] propose is \(U_i({\uppi }_i,{\uppi }_j) = {\uppi }_i - {\upalpha }_i \text {max} ({\uppi }_j - {\uppi }_i, 0) - {\upbeta }_i \text {max} ({\uppi }_i - {\uppi }_j, 0)\) in a two-player setting. With \({\uppi }_1 > {\uppi }_2\), this collapses to \(U_2 = (1 + {\upalpha }_2) {\uppi }_2 - {\upalpha }_2 {\uppi }_1,\) which is equivalent to the description in Eq. (10) when \(\lambda _2 = -{\upalpha }_2/(1 - {\upalpha }_2)\), and \(U_1 = (1 - {\upbeta }_1) {\uppi }_1 + {\upbeta }_1 {\uppi }_2,\) which is equivalent to the description in Eq. (10) when \(\lambda _1 = {\upbeta }_1/(1-{\upbeta }_1).\) Assuming \(1> {\upalpha }_2, {\upbeta }_1 > 0,\) we then have \(\lambda _2< 0 < \lambda _1\).

  15.    For this diagram, as well as Fig. 5 below, I impose the constraint that player 2 is the small player, i.e., \(s_2 \le 1/2\). While this constraint is irrelevant when \(\lambda _2 = 0\), player 2’s share can exceed 1/2 at small values of \({\upalpha }\) when \(\lambda _2 < 0\).

  16.    This suggests that envy might potentially offset a considerable part of player 2’s payoff disadvantage.

References

  1. Abreu D (1986) Extremal Equilibria of Oligopolistic Supergames. Journal of Economic Theory 39:191–225

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  2. Adams W, Mueller H (1982) The Steel Industry. In: Adams W (ed) The Structure of American Industry, 6th edn. Macmillan Press, New York, N.Y

    Google Scholar 

  3. Adelman MA (1995) Genie Out of the Bottle: World Oil Since 1970. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  4. Andreoni J (1995) Warm-Glow Versus Cold-Prickle: The Effects of Positive and Negative Framing on Cooperation in Experiments. The Quarterly Journal of Economics 110:1–21

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  5. Axelrod R (1984) The Evolution of Cooperation. Basic Books, New York, NY

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  6. Bae H (1987) A Price-Setting Supergame Between Two Heterogeneous Firms. European Economic Review 31:1159–1171

    Google Scholar 

  7. Barrett S (1994) Self-enforcing International Environmental Agreements. Oxford Economic Papers 46:878–894

    Google Scholar 

  8. Barrett S (2001) International Cooperation for Sale. European Economic Review 45:1835–1850

    Google Scholar 

  9. Barrett S (2008) Climate Treaties and the Imperative of Enforcement. Oxford Review of Economic Policy 24:239–258

    Google Scholar 

  10. Bolton GE, Ockenfels A (2000) ERC: A Theory of Equity, Reciprocity, and Competition. The American Economic Review 90:166–193

    Google Scholar 

  11. Carraro C, Siniscalco D (1993) Strategies for the International Protection of the Environment. Journal of Public Economics 52:309–328

    Google Scholar 

  12. de Zeeuw A (2008) International Dynamic Effects on the Stability of International Environmental Agreements. Journal of Environmental Economics and Management 55:163–174

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  13. Diamantoudi E, Sartzetakis ES (2006) Stable International Environmental Agreements: An Analytical Approach. Journal of Public Economic Theory 8:247–263

    Google Scholar 

  14. Dockner E, van Long N (1993) International Pollution Control: Cooperative versus Non-cooperative Strategies. Journal of Environmental Economics and Management 25:13–29

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  15. Duffy J, Muñoz García F (2012) Patience or Fairness? Analyzing Social Preferences in Repeated Games, Games 3:56–77

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  16. Dutta PK, Radner R (2004) Self-enforcing Climate-change Treaties. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 101:5174–5179

    Google Scholar 

  17. Dutta PK, Radner R (2009) Strategic Analysis of Global Warming: Theory and Some Numbers. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization 71:187–209

    Google Scholar 

  18. Fehr E, Schmidt KM (1999) A Theory of Fairness, Competition, and Cooperation. The Quarterly Journal of Economics 114:817–868

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  19. Finus M (2001) Game Theory and International Environmental Cooperation. Edward Elgar, London

    Google Scholar 

  20. Fudenberg D, Maskin E (1986) The Folk Theorem in Repeated Games with Discounting and with Incomplete Information. Econometrica 54:533–54

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  21. Fudenberg D, Tirole J (1989) Noncooperative game theory. Handbook of Individual Organization, North-Holland Press, Amsterdam. Volume 1

  22. Fuentes-Albero C, Rubio SJ (2010) Can International Environmental Cooperation Be Bought? European Journal of Operational Research 202:255–264

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  23. Harrington JE (1991) The Determination of Price and Output Quotas in a Heterogeneous Cartel. International Economic Review 32:767–92

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  24. Hoel M (1992) International Environment Conventions: The Case of Uniform Reductions of Emissions. Environmental and Resource Economics 2:413–436

    Google Scholar 

  25. İriş D, Santos-Pinto L (2014) Experimental Cournot Oligopoly and Inequity Aversion. Theory and Decision 76:31–45

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  26. Kolstad CD (2010) Equity, Heterogeneity and International Environmental Agreements. The B.E. Journal of Economic Analysis & Policy 10. article 3

  27. Kreps DM, Milgrom P, Roberts J, Wilson R (1982) Rational Cooperation in the Finitely Repeated Prisoners’ Dilemma. Journal of Economic Theory 27:245–52

  28. Libecap GD, Wiggins SN (1985) The Influence of Private Contractual Failure on Regulation: The Case of Oil Field Unitization. Journal of Political Economy 93:690–714

    Google Scholar 

  29. Mason CF, Polasky S, Tarui N (2017) Cooperation on Climate-Change Mitigation. European Economic Review 99:43–55

    Google Scholar 

  30. Phillips OR, Mason CF (1996) Market Regulation and Multimarket Rivalry. The RAND Journal of Economics 27:596–617

    Google Scholar 

  31. Polasky S, Tarui N, Ellis G, Mason CF (2008) Cooperation in the Commons. Economic Theory 29:71–88

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  32. Rubio SJ, Ulph A (2007) An Infinite-Horizon Model of Dynamic Membership of International Environmental Agreements. Journal of Environmental Economics and Management 54:296–310

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  33. Schmalensee R (1987) Competitive Advantage and Collusive Optima. International Journal of Industrial Organization 5:351–367

    Google Scholar 

  34. Segerstrom PS (1988) Demons and Repentance. Journal of Economic Theory 45:32–52

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  35. Selten R (1998) Features of Experimentally Observed Bounded Rationality. European Economic Review 42:413–436

    Google Scholar 

  36. Shapiro L (1980) Decentralized Dynamics in Duopoly With Pareto Outcomes. Bell Journal of Economics 11:730–744

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  37. Shcherbakov O, Wakamori N (2017) Identifying the Degree of Collusion Under Proportional Reduction, Staff Working Papers 17-51, Bank of Canada

  38. Weaver JL (1986) Unitization of Oil and Gas Fields in Texas: A Study of Legislative, Administrative, and Judicial Policies. Resources for the Future, Washington, D.C

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Funding

Not applicable.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Contributions

Mason summarized existing literature, described repeated game model, ran simulations, and wrote the draft.

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Charles F. Mason.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The author declares that he has no conflict of interest.

Code availability

Available on request.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

I thank two referees and the guest editor, each of whom provided insightful feedback that greatly improved the presentation of the manuscript. The usual disclaimer applies.

This article is part of the topical collection “Dynamic Games in Environmental Economics andManagement" edited by Florian Wagener and Ngo Van Long.

Appendix: Introducing Asymmetry Makes Player 1 Less Cooperative Under Pro-rata Reductions in the Linear-Quadratic Framework

Appendix: Introducing Asymmetry Makes Player 1 Less Cooperative Under Pro-rata Reductions in the Linear-Quadratic Framework

Consider the linear-quadratic framework introduced above, where \({\uppi }_i = ({\upalpha }_i - X)x_i, X = x_1 + x_2\) and \({\upalpha }_1 = 1, {\upalpha }_2 = 1 - {\upalpha }\). The incentive constraint supporting a quasi-cooperative regime when players choose the grim strategy is

$$\begin{aligned} {\uppi }_1^c \ge (1-{\updelta }) {\uppi }_1^d + {\updelta } pi_1^N, \end{aligned}$$

where \({\uppi }_i^N = (x_i^N)^2, \ x_1^N = (1+{\upalpha })/3, \ x_2^N = (1-2{\upalpha })/3, \ X^N = x_1^N + x_2^N = (2-{\upalpha })/3\). Pro-rata reductions implies \(x_i^c = \mu x_i^N\), with \(\mu < 1.\) In this setting, \({\uppi }_i^c = \mu ({\upalpha }_i - \mu X^N) x_i^N\). Optimal defection, should it occur, would entail \(x_i^d = R_i(x_j^c) = ({\upalpha }_i - \mu x_j^N)/2\) and \({\uppi }_i^d = (x_i^d)^2\).

The incentive constraint can be recast as a condition on the discount factor:

$$\begin{aligned} {\updelta } \ge {\hat{{\updelta }}}_i \equiv \frac{{\uppi }_i^d - {\uppi }_i^c}{{\uppi }_i^d - {\uppi }_i^N}. \end{aligned}$$

Define \(\Omega = {\hat{{\updelta }}}_1 - {\hat{{\updelta }}}_2\); it is immediate that \(\Omega = 0\) if \({\upalpha } = 0\). I claim that \(\partial \Omega /\partial {\upalpha } > 0\), from which it follows that \(\Omega > 0\), for \({\upalpha } \in (0, .5]\). It is easy to see that \(\Omega \) is proportional to \({\upomega } \equiv ({\uppi }_2^d - {\uppi }_2^N)({\uppi }_1^d - {\uppi }_1^c) - ({\uppi }_1^d - {\uppi }_1^N)({\uppi }_2^d - {\uppi }_2^c)\), so it suffices to show that \({\upomega }\) is increasing in \({\upalpha }\). Expanding the definition of \({\upomega }\) yields:

$$\begin{aligned} {\upomega }&= {\uppi }_1^d ({\uppi }_2^c - {\uppi }_2^N) - {\uppi }_2^d ({\uppi }_1^c - {\uppi }_1^N) + {\uppi }_1^c {\uppi }_2^N - {\uppi }_1^N {\uppi }_2^c \\&= {\uppi }_1^d ({\uppi }_2^c - {\uppi }_2^N) - {\uppi }_2^d ({\uppi }_1^c - {\uppi }_1^N) - {\uppi }_1^c ({\uppi }_2^c - {\uppi }_2^N) + {\uppi }_2^c ({\uppi }_1^c - {\uppi }_1^N) \\&= ({\uppi }_1^d - {\uppi }_1^c)({\uppi }_2^c - {\uppi }_2^N) - ({\uppi }_2^d - {\uppi }_2^c)({\uppi }_1^c - {\uppi }_1^N). \end{aligned}$$

Defining \(G_i^d = {\uppi }_i^d - {\uppi }_i^c\) and \(G_i^c = {\uppi }_i^c - {\uppi }_i^N\) allows \({\upomega }\) to be expressed more compactly as

$$\begin{aligned} {\upomega } = G_1^d G_2^c - G_2^d G_1^c. \end{aligned}$$
(15)

I note that when \({\upalpha } = 0\) one has \(G_i^d = G^d \equiv \frac{(1 - \mu )^2}{4}\) and \(G_i^c = G^c \equiv -\frac{(1-\mu )(1 + 2\mu )}{9}\), for \(i = 1, 2\).

It is straightforward to calculate

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial {G_1^c}}{\partial {{\upalpha }}}&= - \left( \frac{1-2{\upalpha }}{9} \right) (1 - \mu )^2; \\ \frac{\partial {G_2^c}}{\partial {{\upalpha }}}&= (1 - \mu ) \left( 1 + \Bigl (\frac{ 5 - 4{\upalpha }}{9} \Bigr ) (1 - \mu ) \right) ; \\ \frac{\partial {G_1^d}}{\partial {{\upalpha }}}&= \frac{2}{9} (1-2{\upalpha }) \mu ^2; \\ \frac{\partial {G_2^d}}{\partial {{\upalpha }}}&= -\frac{1}{2} \left( 1 - {\upalpha } - (1+{\upalpha }) \frac{\mu }{3} \right) \left( 1 + \frac{\mu }{3} \right) + \frac{\mu }{3} \left( 3 - 4{\upalpha } \right) + \frac{\mu ^2}{9} \left( 5 - 4{\upalpha } \right) . \end{aligned}$$

Using these expressions along with the characterizations of \(G_i^c\) and \(G_i^d\), evaluating at \({\upalpha } = 0\), and inserting into Eq. (15) yields

$$\begin{aligned} {\upomega }&= \Bigl (2\mu ^2 {-} \bigl (5\mu ^2 {+} 9\mu {+} (9{+}3\mu )(\mu /6 {-}1/2)\bigr )\Bigr ) G^c/9 {+} \Bigl ((1-\mu )(14 {-} 5\mu ) {-} (1-\mu )^2\bigr )G^d \Bigr )/9 \\&= \frac{\Bigl (\bigl (5\mu ^2 + 9\mu + (9+3\mu )(\mu /6 -1/2)\bigr ) - 2\mu ^2\Bigr ) (1-\mu )(1 + 2\mu )}{81} \\&\quad + \frac{\Bigl ((1-\mu )(14 - 5\mu ) - (1-\mu )^2\Bigr )(1 - \mu )^2 }{36} \\&> \Bigl (\bigl (5\mu ^2 + 9\mu + (9+3\mu )(\mu /6 -1/2)\bigr ) - 2\mu ^2\Bigr ) \frac{ (1-\mu )(1 + 2\mu )}{81} \end{aligned}$$

where I used the fact that \(\mu < 1\), which implies the second term in the second line is strictly positive. Noting that \(\frac{(1-\mu )(1 + 2\mu )}{81} >0\) for \(\mu < 1\), and simplifying the first term, I conclude that a sufficient condition for \({\upomega } > 0\) is \(7\mu (\mu + 3) - 9 >0,\) which is easily seen to hold for \(\mu \ge 1/2.\)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Mason, C.F. Cooperation in Dynamic Games with Asymmetric Players: The Role of Social Preferences. Dyn Games Appl 12, 977–995 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13235-022-00435-1

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13235-022-00435-1

Keywords

Navigation