Skip to main content
Log in

On de Finetti’s instrumentalist philosophy of probability

  • Original paper in Philosophy of Probability
  • Published:
European Journal for Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

De Finetti is one of the founding fathers of the subjective school of probability. He held that probabilities are subjective, coherent degrees of expectation, and he argued that none of the objective interpretations of probability make sense. While his theory has been influential in science and philosophy, it has encountered various objections. I argue that these objections overlook central aspects of de Finetti’s philosophy of probability and are largely unfounded. I propose a new interpretation of de Finetti’s theory that highlights these aspects and explains how they are an integral part of de Finetti’s instrumentalist philosophy of probability. I conclude by drawing an analogy between misconceptions about de Finetti’s philosophy of probability and common misconceptions about instrumentalism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. A few preliminary comments are in place: 1. As we shall see in Section 4.6, in de Finetti’s theory the notion of expectation is taken to be a ‘primitive’. A degree of expectation about an event (proposition) is the expectation of the binary random-variable that represents the occurrence of that event (truth-value of that proposition), which is not defined as a probability-weighted sum. 2. The distinction between the terms ‘degree of belief’ and ‘degree of expectation’ is interesting and important, but its consideration goes beyond the scope of this paper. In any case, this distinction will not play an essential role in most of the discussion below. 3. In what follows, I shall talk about degrees of expectation about both events and propositions. The analysis of degrees of expectation about events can easily be translated to the analysis of degrees of expectation about propositions and vice versa. In fact, de Finetti frequently used the term ‘event’ to refer to propositions. 4. For ease of presentation, in discussing the literature on de Finetti’s theory, I shall sometimes follow the common terminology and refer to subjective probabilities as coherent degrees of belief or coherent credences.

  2. For a similar criticism, see for example Kyburg (1970, Chap. 6), Psillos (2007, p. 45), Bunge (2012, Chap. 11), Talbot (2016, Section 4.2F), and Williamson (2017, p. 78). Some authors agree with Hájek that Bayesianism of the style of de Finetti only imposes the constraints (i) and (ii), but do not conceive de Finetti’s epistemology as permissive. Rather, in analogy with deductive logic, they take subjective probability a la de Finetti to provide a logic of partial belief (Gillies 1973, Chap. 1; Howson 2000) or a logic of inductive inference (Howson and Urbach 2006, Chap. 9). Although some of de Finetti’s writings may suggest such an interpretation, I believe that it is inadequate. I will propose below that de Finetti conceived his theory of probability as much broader.

  3. A bet is an option to receive (or give) a specified positive amount S (‘the stake’) if an event E occurs, sold (bought) by a bookie for a price Q. The ratio Q/(S − Q) is ‘the odds’, and an agent will accept to buy a bet at these odds only if her degree of belief in E is equal or larger than the betting quotient Q/S. Betting quotients are odds normalized, so that their values lie within the half-open unit interval [0, 1). This interval could be extended to the closed-unit interval [0, 1] by allowing the odds to take the ‘value’ ∞ (Howson 2000, pp. 125–126).

  4. Mura (2009) is a notable exception.

  5. The main focus in de Finetti’s later writings is on the Theory of Probability (Vols. 1 and 2), Probability, Induction and Statistics, and Philosophical Lectures on Probabilities, which constitute his comprehensive attempts to present the main ideas of his theory and philosophy of probability.

  6. For Vailati’s philosophy, see for example Arrighi et al. (2010).

  7. De Finetti (1937/1980, p. 61) takes the idea that betting reveals an agent’s subjective probability to be “trivial and obvious.” Yet, as we shall see below, in his later philosophy he considered this idea less obvious and opted for a different method of measuring probability.

  8. De Finetti was not always careful in articulating his concept of probability and some of his writings could naturally be interpreted as advocating an operational definition of probability in the philosophical sense. For example, in his discussion in the Theory of Probability of two decision-theoretic frameworks for measuring probabilities and explicating coherence, he said that each of these frameworks will consist of “a scheme of decisions to which an individual (it could be You) can subject himself in order to reveal – in an operational manner – that value which, by definition, will be called his prevision of [a random quantity] X, or in particular his probability of [an event] E” (de Finetti 1974a, p. 85).

  9. Quantum mechanics seems to provide a counterexample. For instance, in a measurement of position, a system that is in a superposition of various positions does not have any definite position before the measurement. But calling the operation that transforms a superposition of positions to a definite position a measurement of position is a misnomer. More generally, the so-called ‘measurement’ in quantum mechanics is a misnomer. The term ‘measurement’ in this theory is more akin to a preparation or transformation of a state of a system, or perhaps an operational definition of a quantity.

  10. Gillies (2000, pp. 200–203) seems to advocate such a view in the context of the social sciences.

  11. For a discussion of qualitative probabilities and their relations to numerical probabilities, see for example de Finetti (1937/1980), Koopman (1940a, b), Savage (1954/1972), Suppes and Zanotti (1976, 1982), Suppes (1994, 2009), and references therein.

  12. The argument here is that de Finetti was instrumentalist about probability and probabilistic theories. The question whether he was an instrumentalist about science in general, as the above quotation may suggest, is interesting but goes beyond the scope of this study.

  13. Obviously, such inductive reasoning may be dependent on probabilities. On the proposed interpretation, this is not a problem for de Finetti as he did not attempt to define probability, let alone provide a reductive definition.

  14. The question arises as to how such background knowledge could be integrated into the framework of the mathematical probability theory.

  15. De Finetti also appealed to a weaker symmetry condition, ‘partial exchangeability’, where a series of events is divided into k classes and the probability distribution remains invariant only under permutations within each of these classes. For an analysis of various conceptions of exchangeability and de Finetti’s ‘representation theorem’ for exchangeable random-variables, see for example Diaconis (1977, 1988).

  16. Arguably, in all the main interpretations of probability the fundamental object is conditional probability (see Hájek 2003; Berkovitz 2015, Section 4.2, and references therein).

  17. De Finetti’s (1974a, p. 134) presentation of conditional probability is both ambiguous and potentially misleading. “In precise terms, we shall write P(E/H) for the probabilityof the event E conditional on the event H’ (or even the probabilityof the conditional event E ∣ H’), which is the probability that You attribute to E if you think that in addition to your present information, i.e. the H0 which we understand implicitly, it will become known to You that H is true (and nothing else)”; where the ‘conditional event’ E ∣ H is a conditional proposition that is true when H and E are true, false when H is true and E is false, and has no truth-value when H is false. (For the sake of simplicity, I assume that H includes the background knowledge H0; nothing essential in what follows will depend on this assumption.) The statement in the first brackets of the above quotation suggests that the conditional probability of E given H is to be understood as the unconditional probability of the conditional event E ∣ H, whereas the last part of the sentence suggests my interpretation above. There are at least two reasons why the interpretation of de Finetti’s concept of conditional probability as unconditional probability of a conditional event cannot be correct. First, as noted above, in de Finetti’s theory all probabilities are conditional on background knowledge and unconditional probabilities do not make sense. But if conditional probability were defined as an unconditional probability of a conditional event, it would fundamentally be an unconditional probability of such event, and accordingly will not be related to background knowledge. Second, the interpretation of conditional probability as unconditional probability of a conditional event is incompatible with de Finetti’s characterization of the measurement of conditional probability in terms of conditional penalty in the Brier scoring-rule decision-theoretic framework. Consider the Brier scoring-rule decision-theoretic framework (see Section 4.1), and suppose an agent with coherent degrees of expectation. In this framework, the decision of such an agent is comprised of the probabilities that she post for various propositions (events) E1, ..., En, and the penalty she is subject to is proportional to the distance (i.e. the square root difference) between the posted probabilities and the values of the binary random-variables that represent whether these propositions (events) are true (occur). It is assumed that penalties for the various probabilities are additive and that the agent is trying to minimize her expected loss. Given these assumptions, the agent’s decision reflects her probabilities. The penalty for the conditional probability of E given H is conditional on H being true (occurring): H(E − P(E))2; where H and E are binary random-variables that represent respectively the truth-values (occurrences) of the propositions (events) E and H. This conditional penalty is compatible with interpreting conditional probability as a conditional with a probabilistic consequent but not with interpreting it as an unconditional probability of a conditional event. If the conditional probability of E given H were defined as the unconditional probability of the conditional event E ∣ H, the penalty would have to be (E| H − P(E|H))2; where EH is the random variable that is supposed to represent the truth-value of EH. But this penalty is ill defined, as E ∣ H has no truth-value when H is false.

  18. De Finetti (1972, pp. 15–16, 1974a, Section 4.3) demonstrates that a coherence condition on the degrees of expectation about H conditional on H0, E&H conditional on H0 and E conditional on H&H0 implies that, when the degree of expectation about H conditional on H0 is non-zero, the probability of E conditional on H & H0 is equal to the ratio of the probability of E & H conditional on H0 and the probability of H conditional on H0. Thus, if we label the probability of E conditional on H & H0 as the ‘conditional probability of E given H’, the probability of E & H conditional on H0 as the ‘unconditional probability of E & H’ and the probability of H conditional on H0 as the ‘unconditional probability of H’, we obtain the equality (KCP).

  19. Two comments: 1. Although de Finetti didn’t use this notation, it follows naturally from his representation of conditional probability (de Finetti 1974a, pp. 134–139) and his verificationism (de Finetti 1974a, p. 34, 1974b, pp. 266–267 and 302–313). For a detailed discussion of de Finetti’s verificationism and its implications for the logical structure of subjective probability, see Berkovitz (2012). 2. It is important to distinguish between zero loss in the case of degrees of expectation about unverifiable events and zero loss in the case of degrees of expectation about verifiable events. In the first case, the zero loss is independent of the values of degrees of expectation and it reflects the fact that degrees of expectation about unverifiable events are excluded from the accumulated loss because they have no instrumental value. In the second case, zero loss is only possible for extreme degrees of expectation about verifiable events and it represents maximum instrumental value.

  20. Consider, for example, an agent who assigns degrees of expectation α and β to a verifiable event E and its absence ¬E, respectively. Suppose that α and β constitute an incoherent system of degrees of expectation: α + β ≠ 1. Then, the posted degree of expectation about E that minimizes the agent’s expected loss is α/α + β. For her subjective expected loss is Exp(LD) = (α(1 − d)2 + βd2)/k2, where d is the degree of expectation that she posts for E, and Exp(LD) is minimized when d = α/α + β. A similar reasoning demonstrates that the degree of expectation that the agent should post for ¬E is β/α + β. As is not difficult to see, these degrees of expectation are coherent.

  21. The differences between the Brier scoring-rule and de Finetti’s variant of it are immaterial for the discussion in this section.

  22. The distinction between pragmatic and epistemic justifications of the calculus of probability has been made by a number of authors. For some examples, see Skyrms (1984), Armendt (1992, 1993), Christensen (1996, 2004), Joyce (1998, 2009), Huber (2007), Gibbard (2008a, b), Leitgeb and Pettigrew (2010a, b), Weisberg (2015), and Pettigrew (2016).

  23. In de Finetti’s theory, zero probability does not imply impossibility. Accordingly, a degree of expectation zero (one) about a contingent proposition E is compatible with E being true (false).

  24. Joyce (2009, Section 5) proposes that different weights in the average sum that constitutes the accumulated loss could reflect the extent to which the epistemic utilities of degrees of belief contribute to the overall epistemic utility of a system of degrees of belief. While this proposal has some similarities to our interpretation of de Finetti’s variant of the Brier scoring-rule decision-theoretic framework, it is also quite different because it is situated in a different epistemic framework. In both cases, the scoring-rule can be thought of as measuring epistemic utility. Yet, Joyce (2009) bases his notion of epistemic utility on the idea that degrees of belief are estimates of truth-values of propositions the accuracy of which could be measured by the Brier scoring-rule, whereas in our interpretation of de Finetti the epistemic utility of degrees of expectation should be evaluated according to their instrumental value.

  25. To assume that such a scale exists is of course an idealization.

  26. For objections to identifying degrees of belief with fair betting quotients, see for example Christensen (1996, 2004), Maher (1997), and Vineberg (2016, Section 2.2).

  27. Christensen holds that the classic formulations of the Dutch Book argument, due to Ramsey and de Finetti, demonstrate that agents who are Dutch Book vulnerable are ‘pragmatically’ inconsistent, and accordingly these arguments provide only pragmatic justifications for the probability calculus. His aim is to offer a non-pragmatic reading of the Dutch Book argument that will furnish epistemic reasons to conform to this calculus. Christensen (2004) presents his “depragmatized Dutch Book argument” in two stages. First, he formulates it for a ‘simple agent’, i.e. an agent “who values money positively, in a linear way” and “does not value anything else at all, positively or negatively” and whose “degrees of belief sanction as fair monetary bets at odds matching his degrees of belief” (ibid., p. 117). The argument is based on two principles for simple agents (ibid. pp. 118 and 119):

    Bet Defectiveness. For a simple agent, a set of bets that is logically guaranteed to leave him

    monetarily worse off is rationally defective.

    Belief Defectiveness. If a simple agent’s beliefs sanction as fair each of a set of bets, and that

    set of bets is rationally defective, then the agent’s beliefs are rationally defective.

    The argument proceeds as follows. If a simple agent has incoherent degrees of belief, then there is a set of monetary bets at odds matching her degrees of belief that logically guarantees her monetary loss. By Bet Defectiveness, this set of bets is rationally defective. Thus, since each member of this set of bets is sanctioned by the agent’s degrees of belief, it follows from Belief Defectiveness that her degrees of beliefs are rationally defective (ibid., p. 121). Having established that in Dutch bookable scenarios the degrees of belief of a simple agent are rationally defective, Christensen then argues that the point of the Dutch Book argument is not dependent on the fact that it is formulated for such an agent. That is, he argues that since “the basic defect diagnosed in the simple agent is not a preference-defect”, the problem has to lie with the incoherent degrees of belief, and “the simple agent’s problematic preferences function in the [Dutch Book argument] merely as a diagnostic device” that “discloses a purely epistemic defect” (ibid., p. 123).

    As Vineberg (2016, Section 2.2) notes, in Christensen’s reasoning the so-called pragmatic dimension of the Dutch Book argument seems to have been merely submerged. While Christensen’s claim that the model of simple agent functions only as a diagnostic device for disclosing the defect in incoherent degrees of belief, it is not clear from his argument why incoherence is irrational unless it has bearings for the instrumental value of beliefs. Indeed, Christensen claims that “[i]n severing the definitional or metaphysical ties between belief and preferences,” his depragmatized Dutch Book argument “frees us from seeing the basic problem with incoherent beliefs as a pragmatic one” (ibid., p. 123). But his argument for the belief defectiveness of incoherent degrees of belief relies heavily on what he takes to be a pragmatic consideration, i.e. the fact that incoherent degrees of belief could, in certain circumstances, leave agents worse off come what may.

  28. For a similar proposal see Leitgeb and Pettigrew (2010a, b). Leitgeb and Pettigrew define inaccuracy relative to a world, and they propose to minimize the expectation of the inaccuracy of an agent’s degrees of belief (or more exactly, credence function) over all and only the worlds that are epistemically possible for the agent (2010a, pp. 205–206).

  29. Two comments: 1. Joyce uses here the term ‘credence’. But since he seems to employ the terms ‘credence’ and ‘degree of belief’ interchangeably and for continuity with the terminology of previous sections, I use the term ‘degree of belief’. Nothing essential in what follows will hinge on this terminological choice. 2. (i) and (ii) correspond to claims (3) and (4) in Joyce (2009).

  30. Following Jeffrey (1992, p. 44), Joyce (1998, pp. 575–576) characterizes probabilism as the doctrine that “any adequate epistemology must recognize that opinions come in varying gradations of strength and must make conformity to the axioms of probability a fundamental requirement of rationality for these graded or partial beliefs.”

  31. Two comments: 1. For principles that relate subjective probabilities to objective probabilities, see, for example, Hacking’s (1965, Chap. 9) ‘frequency principle’, Lewis’ (1986, Chapter 19) ‘principal principle’, and Mellor’s (1995, Chap. 4) ‘evidence condition’. 2. In the example above I assumed for the sake of simplicity that the agent’s degree of belief is constrained by objective probability. Yet, this reasoning could be reformulated so as to apply to agents who follow de Finetti and reject the idea of objective probability or those who reject the idea that objective probabilities should constrain degrees of belief.

  32. Milne (1997) and Mura (2009) are notable exceptions.

  33. This is a quotation from the English summary of de Finetti and Savage’s (1962) “Sul modo di scegliere le probabilità iniziali” (“How to choose the initial probabilities”). For a different interpretation of de Finetti’s view of imprecise probabilities, see Feduzi et al. (2017).

References

  • Armendt, B. (1992). Dutch strategies for diachronic rules: When believers see the sure loss coming. In D. Hull, M. Forbes, & K. Okruhlik (Eds.), PSA 1992 (Vol. 1, pp. 217–229). East Lansing: Philosophy of Science Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • Armendt, B. (1993). Dutch books, additivity, and utility theory. Philosophical Topics, 21(1), 1–20.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arrighi, C., Cantu, P., De Zan, M., & Suppes, P. (Eds.). (2010). Logic and pragmatism: Selected essays by Giovanni Vailati. Stanford: CSLI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berkovitz, J. (2012). The world according to de Finetti: On de Finetti’s theory of probability and its application to quantum mechanics. In Y. ben Menachem & M. Hemmo (Eds.), Probability in physics (pp. 249–280). New York: Springer.

  • Berkovitz, J. (2015). The propensity interpretation of probability: A re-evaluation. Erkenntnis, 80(suppl. 3), 629–711.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bradley, S. (2016). Imprecise probabilities. The Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy (winter 2016 edition), E. N. Zalta (Ed.). URL https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/imprecise-probabilities/.

  • Brier, G. W. (1950). Verification of forecasts expressed in terms of probability. Monthly Weather Review, 78(1), 1–3.

    Google Scholar 

  • Briggs, R. (2009). Distorted reflection. Philosophical Review, 118(1), 59–85.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bunge, M. (2012). Evaluating philosophies. Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science, Vol. 295. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Christensen, D. (1991). Clever bookies and coherent beliefs. Philosophical Review, 100(2), 229–247.

    Google Scholar 

  • Christensen, D. (1996). Dutch-Book arguments depragmatized: Epistemic consistency for partial believers. Journal of Philosophy, 93(9), 450–479.

    Google Scholar 

  • Christensen, D. (2004). Putting logic in its place. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawid, P. A., & Galavotti, M. C. (2009). De Finetti’s subjectivism, objective probability, and the empirical validation of probability assessments. In M. C. Galavotti (Ed.), Bruno de Finetti: Radical probabilist (pp. 97–114). London: College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Finetti, B. (1937/1980). Foresight: Its logical laws, its subjective sources (translated by H. E. Kyburg). In H. E. Kyburg & H. E. Smokler (Eds.), Studies in subjective probability (2nd ed., pp. 53–118). Huntington: Robert E. Kreiger Publishing Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Finetti, B. (1957). L’informazione, il ragionamento, l’inconscio nei rapporti con la previsione. L’industria, 2, 186–210.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Finetti, B. (1970). Logical foundations and measurement of subjective probability. Acta Psychologica, 34(2/3), 129–145.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Finetti, B. (1972). Probability, induction and statistics: The art of guessing. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Finetti, B. (1974a). Theory of probability: A critical treatment (Vol. 1). New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Finetti, B. (1974b). Theory of probability: A critical treatment (Vol. 2). New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Finetti, B. (2008). Philosophical lectures on probability. Collected, edited and annotated by A. Mura with an introductory essay by M. C. Galavotti, translated by H. Hosni. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Finetti, B., & Savage, L. J. (1962). Sul modo di scegliere le probabilità iniziali. Biblioteca del Metron, Serie C, 1, 81–154.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diaconis, P. (1977). Finite forms of de Finetti’s theorem on exchangeability. Synthese, 36(2), 271–281.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diaconis, P. (1988). Recent progress on de Finetti’s notions of exchangeability. In J. M. Bernardo, M. H. DeGroot, D. V. Lindley, & A. F. M. Smith (Eds.), Bayesian Statistics (Vol. 3, pp. 111–125). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Doob, J. L. (1971). What is a martingale? American Mathematical Monthly, 78(5), 451–463.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duhem, P. (1893/1996). Physics and metaphysics. In R. Ariew & P. Barker (eds. and trans.), Pierre Duhem: Essays in the history and philosophy of science. Indianapolis: Hackett (1996).

  • Eriksson, L., & Hájek, A. (2007). What are degrees of belief? Studia Logica, 86(2), 183–213.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feduzi, A., Runde, J., & Zappia, C. (2017). De Finetti and Savage on the normative relevance of imprecise reasoning: A reply to Arthmar and Brady. History of Economic Ideas, 25(1), 211–223.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher, R. A. (1971). The design of experiments (9th ed.). London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Galavotti, M. C. (2001). Subjectivism, objectivism and objectivity in Bruno de Finetti’s Bayesianism. In D. Corfield & J. Williamson (Eds.), Foundations of Bayesianism (pp. 161–174). New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Galavotti, M. C. (2008). De Finetti’s philosophy of probability, an introductory essay to de Finetti’s Philosophical lectures on probability. In de Finetti (2008), xv–xxii.

  • Gibbard, A. (2008a). Rational credence and the value of truth. In T. Szabo Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Oxford studies in epistemology (Vol. 2, pp. 143–164). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Gibbard, A. (2008b). Aiming at the truth over time: Reply to Arntzenius and Swanson. In T. Szabo Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Oxford studies in epistemology (Vol. 2, pp. 190–203). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Gillies, D. (1972). Operationalism. Synthese, 25(1/2), 1–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gillies, D. (2000). Philosophical theories of probability. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldstein, S. (2017). Bohmian mechanics. The Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy (summer 2017 edition), E. N. Zalta (Ed.). URL https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2017/entries/qm-bohm/.

  • Hacking, I. (1965). Logic of statistical inference. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hájek, A. (2003). What conditional probability could not be. Synthese, 137(3), 273–323.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hájek, A. (2005). Scotching Dutch books? Philosophical Perspectives, 19(1), 139–151.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hájek, A. (2008a). Arguments for – or against – probabilism? British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 59(4), 793–819.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hájek, A. (2008b). Dutch Book arguments. In P. Anand, P. Pattanaik, & C. Puppe (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of rational and social choice (pp. 173–195). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hájek, A. (2012). Interpretations of probability. The Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy (winter 2012 edition), E. N. Zalta (Ed.). URL https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2012/entries/probability-interpret/.

  • Hawthorne, J. (1993). Bayesian induction is eliminative induction. Philosophical Topics, 21(1), 99–138.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawthorne, J. (1994). On the nature of Bayesian convergence. In D. Hull, M. Forbes, & R. M. Burian (Eds.), PSA 1994 (Vol. 1, pp. 241–249). East Lansing: Philosophy of Science Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hellman, G. (1997). Bayes and beyond. Philosophy of Science, 64(2), 191–221.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howson, C. (2000). Hume's problem: Induction and the justification of belief. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howson, C. (2008). De Finetti, countable additivity, consistency and coherence. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 59(1), 1–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howson, C., & Urbach, P. (1993). Scientific reasoning: The Bayesian approach (2nd ed.). Chicago: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howson, C., & Franklin, A. (1994). Bayesian conditionalization and probability kinematics. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 45(2), 451–466.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howson, C., & Urbach, P. (2006). Scientific reasoning: The Bayesian approach (3rd ed.). Chicago: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huber, F. (2007). The consistency argument for ranking functions. Studia Logica, 86(2), 299–329.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jeffrey, R. (1986). Probabilism and induction. Topoi, 5(1), 51–58.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jeffrey, R. (1992). Probability and the art of judgment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Joyce, J. M. (1998). A nonpragmatic vindication of probabilism. Philosophy of Science, 65(4), 575–603.

    Google Scholar 

  • Joyce, J. M. (2005). How probabilities reflect evidence. Philosophical Perspectives, 19(1), 153–178.

    Google Scholar 

  • Joyce, J. M. (2009). Accuracy and coherence: Prospects for an alethic epistemology of partial belief. In F. Huber & C. Schmidt-Petri (Eds.), Degrees of belief (Vol. 342, pp. 263–297). New York: Springer.

  • Joyce, J. M. (2010). A defense of imprecise credences in inference and decision making. Philosophical Perspectives, 24(1), 281–323.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, M. (1996). Decision theory as philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy, R., & Chihara, C. (1979). The Dutch Book argument: Its logical flaws, its subjective sources. Philosophical Studies, 36(1), 19–33.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kolmogorov, A. N. (1933/1950). Foundations of probability. New York: Chelsea Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koopman, B. O. (1940a). The axioms and algebra of intuitive probability. Annals of Mathematics, Second Series, 41(2), 269–292.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koopman, B. O. (1940b). The bases of probability. Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society, 46(10), 763–774.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kyburg, H. (1970). Probability and inductive logic. London: Macmillam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kyburg, H. (1978). Subjective probability: Criticisms, reflections and problems. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 7(1), 157–180.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leitgeb, H., & Pettigrew, R. (2010a). An objective justification of Bayesianism I: Measuring inaccuracy. Philosophy of Science, 77(2), 201–235.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leitgeb, H., & Pettigrew, R. (2010b). An objective justification of Bayesianism II: The consequences of minimizing inaccuracy. Philosophy of Science, 77(2), 236–272.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levi, I. (1974). On indeterminate probabilities. Journal of Philosophy, 71(13), 391–418.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levi, I. (1980). The enterprise of knowledge: An essay on knowledge, credal probability, and chance. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levi, I. (1985). Imprecision and indeterminacy in probability judgment. Philosophy of Science, 52(3), 390–409.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levi, I. (1986). Hard choices: Decision making under unresolved conflict. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1973). Counterfactuals. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1986). Philosophical papers (Vol. 2). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maher, P. (1993). Betting on theories. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maher, P. (1997). Depragmatized Dutch Book arguments. Philosophy of Science, 64(2), 291–305.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mahtani, A. (2012). Diachronic Dutch Book arguments. Philosophical Review, 121(3), 443–450.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mellor, D. H. (1995). The facts of causation. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Milne, P. (1997). Bruno de Finetti and the logic of conditional events. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 48(2), 195–232.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mura, A. (2009). Probability and the logic of de Finetti’s trievents. In M. C. Galavotti (Ed.), Bruno de Finetti: Radical probabilist (pp. 201–242). London: College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettigrew, R. (2016). Accuracy and the laws of credence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Psillos, S. (1999). Scientific realism: How science tracks truth. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S. (2007). Putting a bridle on irrationality: An appraisal of van Fraassen’s new epistemology. In B. Monton (Ed.), Images of empiricism: Essays on science and stances, with a reply from Bas C. van Fraassen (pp. 134–164). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Ramsey, P. F. (1926/1980). Truth and probability. In H. E. Kyburg & H. E. Smokler (Eds.), Studies in subjective probability (2nd ed., pp. 23–52). Huntington: Robert E. Kreiger Publishing Co.

  • Savage, L. (1954/1972). The foundations of statistics (2nd ed.). New York: Dover Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schick, F. (1986). Dutch bookies and money pumps. Journal of Philosophy, 83(2), 112–119.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shimony, A. (1988). An adamite derivation of the calculus of probability. In J. H. Fetzer (Ed.), Probability and causality (pp. 151–161). Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skyrms, B. (1984). Pragmatics and empiricism. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skyrms, B. (1987). Coherence. In N. Rescher (Ed.), Scientific inquiry in philosophical perspective (pp. 225–242). Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. (1968). A theory of conditionals. In N. Rescher (Ed.), Studies in logical theory (pp. 98–112). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppes, P. (1994). Qualitative theory of subjective probability. In G. Wright & P. Ayton (Eds.), Subjective probability (pp. 18–37). Chichester: John Wiley.

  • Suppes, P. (2009). Some philosophical reflections on de Finetti’s thought. In M. C. Galavotti (Ed.), Bruno de Finetti: Radical probabilist (pp. 19–39). London: College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppes, P., & Zanotti, M. (1976). Necessary and sufficient conditions for existence of a unique measure strictly agreeing with a qualitative probability ordering. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 5(3), 431–438.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppes, P., & Zanotti, M. (1982). Necessary and sufficient qualitative axioms for conditional probability. Zeitschrift für Wahrscheinlichkeitstheorie und verwandte Gebiete, 60, 163–169.

    Google Scholar 

  • Talbott, W. (2016). Bayesian epistemology. The Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy (winter 2016 edition), E. N. Zalta (Ed.). URL https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/epistemology-bayesian/.

  • van Fraassen, B. (1983). Calibration: A frequency justification for personal probability. In R. S. Cohen & L. Laudan (Eds.), Physics, philosophy and psychoanalysis (pp. 295–319). Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

  • Vicig, P., & Seidenfeld, T. (2012). Bruno de Finetti and imprecision: Imprecise probability does not exist! International Journal of Approximate Reasoning, 53(8), 1115–1123.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vineberg, S. (2001). The notion of consistency for partial belief. Philosophical Studies, 102(3), 281–296.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vineberg, S. (2016). Dutch Book arguments. The Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy (spring 2011 edition), Edward N. Zalta (Ed.). URL https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2016/entries/dutch-book/.

  • Walley, P. (1991). Statistical reasoning with imprecise probabilities. London: Chapman and Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, J. (2015). You’ve come a long way, Bayesians. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 44(6), 817–834.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, J. (2017). Lectures on inductive reasoning. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

For helpful comments on previous drafts of this paper and discussions of de Finetti’s philosophy, I am very grateful to the journal’s editors-in-chief, Phyllis Illari and Federica Russo, and Holger Andreas, Colin Elliott, Franz Huber, Joel Katzav, Noah Stemeroff, and in particular Donald Gillies, Aaron Kenna and Alberto Mura. Parts of this paper were presented at the CSHPS 2010, Montreal; GRECC Colloquium, Philosophy, Universitat Autònoma de Barcelona; IHPST Workshop, University of Toronto; Israel Foundations of Physics Discussion Group, Edelstein Center, Hebrew University of Jerusalem; Serious Metaphysics Group, Philosophy, University of Cambridge; Munich Center for Mathematical Philosophy, Ludwig Maximilian University of Munich; 42nd Dubrovnik Philosophy of Science conference; IHPST Colloquium, Paris; LSE Choice Group, CPNSS, London School of Economics; Theory Workshop, Sociology, University of Toronto; Probability and Models: Instrumentalism and Pragmatism in De Finetti’s Subjectivism workshop, HPS, University of Sassari; Philosophy, University of Rome III; CSHPS 2017, Toronto; Philosophy of Science Group, CONICET, University of Buenos Aires; Colloquialism, IHPST, University of Toronto; and the Philosophy Colloquium, Department of Economics, Philosophy and Political Science, University of British Columbia, Okanagan. I would like to thank the audiences in these forums for their helpful comments and suggestions. The research for this paper was supported by SSHRC Insight and SSHRC SIG grants.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Joseph Berkovitz.

Additional information

Publisher’s note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Berkovitz, J. On de Finetti’s instrumentalist philosophy of probability. Euro Jnl Phil Sci 9, 25 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-018-0226-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13194-018-0226-4

Keywords

Navigation