Skip to main content
Log in

Bodily Ownership, Psychological Ownership, and Psychopathology

  • Published:
Review of Philosophy and Psychology Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Debates about bodily ownership and psychological ownership have typically proceeded independently of each other. This paper explores the relation between them, with particular reference to how each is illuminated by psychopathology. I propose a general framework for studying ownership that is applicable both to bodily ownership (φ-ownership) and psychological ownership (ψ-ownership). The framework proposes studying ownership by starting with explicit judgments of ownership and then exploring the bases for those judgments. Section 3 discusses John Campbell’s account of ψ-ownership in the light of that general framework, emphasizing in particular his fractionation (inspired by schizophrenic delusions) of ψ-ownership into two dissociable components. Section 4 briefly presents an account of φ-ownership that I have developed in more detail elsewhere. Section 5 explores the suggestion, originating with Alexandre Billon, that there needs to be an integrated account of φ-ownership and ψ-ownership because depersonalization disorders typically involve breakdowns of both φ-ownership and ψ-ownership. The argument from depersonalization is not compelling, but Section 6 proposes a different way of reaching the same conclusion. Section 7 shows how reflecting on agency and practical reasoning offers a common thread between the models of φ-ownership and ψ-ownership discussed earlier in the paper.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See the Critique of Pure Reason at B13. I have discussed different ways of looking at Kant’s unity of apperception in Bermúdez 1994.

  2. For a broadly similar distinction see Graham and Stephens 1994.

  3. Frith himself now makes more modest claims for the comparator theory. See Frith 2012.

  4. Compare Martin 1995, who writes “in having bodily sensations, it appears to one as if whatever one is aware of through having such sensations is a part of one’s body” (1995, p. 269). He describes this as a “sense of ownership”, but for reasons indicated above I find this terminology unhappy.

  5. It is true that visual perception is inherently relational, in that the field of view is centered on the viewer’s eyes. But this is not really an analog of Connectedness, because the body is not experienced from a single origin. When we say, for example, that one thing looks nearer than another, this incorporates an implicit self-reference reflecting the origin of the visual point of view. Bodily experience, in contrast, does not allow such spatial comparisons. There is no privileged body-part that counts as “me” for the purposes of describing, say, a pain as further away than an itch.

  6. I am assuming that the general map corresponds to the experienced body, rather than the real body. In this sense it corresponds to what O’Shaughnessy termed the long-term body-image (O'Shaugnessy 1995).

  7. See Tsakiris 2011 §6 for a review and further references.

  8. Dugas and Moutier 1911,28, translated in Billon 2017.

  9. Leroy 1901, 520–1, translated in Billon 2017.

  10. Mayer-Gross 2011, 114

  11. For a different perspective see Rusconi et al. 2010, who offer a positive account of Gerstmann’s syndrome. It is not clear to me, however, that they are clearly distinguishing between a syndrome in the sense of a cluster of symptoms that typically accompany each other, and the richer sense of syndrome in which the cluster of symptoms implicates the breakdown of a single, personal-level cognitive capacity. In fact, the Rusconi et al. hypothesis is that the cortical substrate for Gerstmann’s syndrome is a white matter lesion, that disrupts connections between intra-parietal and angular cortex.

  12. This dependence of φ-ownership upon ψ-ownership certainly emerges clearly in the model of φ-ownership sketched out in §4, but it seems likely to be implicated in any alternative account. To take just one example, the hypothetical (and to my mind illusory) “feeling of mineness” that some authors have postulated is an occurrent mental state that the subject would need to φ-own. The same point applies, of course, if one thinks (with Zahavi and Kriegel 2015 that the “feeling of mineness” (which they term “for-me-ness”) is not an experience itself, but rather an aspect of a core type of experience.

  13. To be clear, the claim is that ψ-ownership presupposes φ-ownership for embodied subjects. Peacocke has argued, in effect, that there is no logical reason why disembodied subjects should not be capable of ψ-ownership (Peacocke 2014). This issue is orthogonal to that considered here, however. There is no reason to think that an account of φ-ownership for embodied subjects would carry over to disembodied subjects, or vice versa.

  14. See, for example, Evans 1982 and Bermudez 2017a.

  15. Ayers 1991, 186–7

  16. For further discussion see Bermudez 1998 and Essays 1–4 in Bermúdez 2018.

  17. Tye 2003, 76.

  18. The claim here is about the normal case. It is an interesting question (raised by Alexandre Billon) how ψ-ownership would work for someone in a sensory deprivation tank, as envisaged by Anscombe. My hunch (and prediction) is that a lack of ongoing sensory feedback would not change the dependence of ψ-ownership upon φ-ownership. No doubt, things would be very different for someone who had existed for their entire life in a sensory deprivation tank (which, in effect, is the thought experiment proposed by Avicenna – the so-called flying or floating man argument). But since this scenario is so far from the normal case, and since it is unlikely that any prediction made about that case will ever be tested, I am not sure that it helps to speculate about it.

  19. For a different approach to the role of agency in self-awareness see O'Brien 2007.

  20. This is also, broadly speaking, compatible with the account of thought insertion proposed by Graham and Stephens (1994), who suggest that schizophrenic patients deny the authorship of thoughts when those thoughts are inexplicable in terms of rest of their beliefs and desires. Their idea is that delusions of thought insertion can sometimes be the best way for the patient to make sense of profoundly anomalous experiences.

  21. See further the essays in O'Brien and Soteriou 2009.

  22. Descartes, Meditations on First Philosophy (AT VII, p. 81), translated by John Cottingham.

References

  • Ayers, M. 1991. Locke: Epistemology and Ontology. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bermúdez, J.L. 1994. The unity of apperception in the critique of pure reason. European Journal of Philosophy 2: 213–240.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bermudez, J.L. 1998. The Paradox of Self-Consciousness. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bermudez, J.L. 2001. Normativity and rationality in delusional psychiatric disorders. Mind and Language 16: 457–493.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bermudez, J.L. 2005. The phenomenology of bodily awareness. In Phenomenology and Philosophy of Mind, ed. D.W. Smith and A.L. Thomasson. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bermudez, J.L. 2011. Bodily awareness and self-consciousness. In Oxford Handbook of the Self, ed. S. Gallagher, 157–179. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bermúdez, J.L. 2015. Bodily ownership, bodily awareness and knowledge without observation. Analysis 75: 37–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bermudez, J.L. 2017a. Understanding “I”: Language and Thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bermudez, J.L. 2017b. Ownership and the space of the body. In The Subject’s Matter: Self-Consciousness and the Body, ed. A. Alsmith and F. de Vignemont. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bermúdez, J.L. 2018. The Bodily Self: Selected Essays. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bermudez, J.L., A.J. Marcel, and N. Eilan, eds. 1995. The Body and the Self. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Billon, A. 2015. Why are we certain that we exist? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 91: 723–759.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Billon, A. 2016. Making sense of the Cotard syndrome: Insights from the study of depersonalisation. Mind and Language 31: 356–391.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Billon, A. 2017. Three challenges to recent theories of bodily self-awareness. In The Subject’s Matter: Self-Consciousness and the Body, ed. A. Alsmith and F. de Vignemont. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Botvinivk, M., and J. Cohen. 1998. Rubber hand 'feel' touch that eyes see. Nature 391: 756.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, J. 1999a. Schizophrenia, the space of reasons, and thinking as a motor process. The Monist 82: 609–625.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, J. 1999b. Immunity to error through misidentification and the meaning of a referring term. Philosophical Topics 29: 89–104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, J. 2002. The ownership of thoughts. Philosophy, Psychiatry, and Psychology 9: 35–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davies, M., M. Coltheart, R. Langdon, and N. Breen. 2001. Monothematic delusions: Towards a two-factor account. Philosophy, Psychiatry and Psychology 8: 133–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dugas, L., and F. Moutier. 1911. La Dépersonnalization. Paris: Alcan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, G. 1982. The Varieties of Reference. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frith, C. 1992. The Cognitive Neuroscience of Schizophrenia. New York: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frith, C. 2012. Explaining delusions of control: The comparator model 20 years on. Consciousness and Cognition 21: 52–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. 2005. How the Body Shapes the Mind. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. 2017. Senses of the sense of ownership. In The Subject’s Matter: Self-Consciousness and the Body, ed. A. Alsmith and F. de Vignemont. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gerrans, P. 2000. Refining the explanation of cotard's delusion. Mind and Language 15: 111–122.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Graham, G., and G.L. Stephens. 1994. Mind and mine. In Philosophical psychopathology, ed. G. Graham and G.L. Stephens. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaspers, K. 1963. General Psychopathology. Manchester: Manchester University Press.

  • Lenggenhager, B., T. Tadi, T. Metzinger, and O. Blanke. 2007. Video ergo sum: Manipulating bodily self-consciousness. Science 317: 1096–1099.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leroy, E.-B. 1901. Sur l’illusion dite dépersonnalisation. L’Année Psychologique, pages 519–522.

  • Martin, M. 1995. Bodily awareness: A sense of ownership. In The Body and the Self, ed. J.L. Bermúdez, A.J. Marcel, and N. Eilan. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayer-Gross, W. 2011. On depersonalization. British Journal of Medical Psychology 15: 103–126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mellor, C. S. 1970. First rank symptoms of schizophrenia. British Journal of Psychiatry 117: 15–23.

  • O'Brien, L. 2007. Self-Knowing Agents. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • O'Brien, L., and M. Soteriou. 2009. Mental Actions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • O'Shaugnessy, B. 1995. Proprioception and the body image. In The body and the self, ed. J.L. Bermudez, A.J. Marcel, and N. Eilan. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pacherie, E., M. Green, and T.J. Bayne. 2006. Phenomenology and delusions: Who put the 'alien' in alien control? Consciousness and Cognition 15: 566–577.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke, C. 2014. The Mirror of the World: Subjects, Consciousness, and Self-Consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rusconi, E., P. Pinel, S. Dehaene, and A. Kleinschmidt. 2010. The enigma of Gerstmann's syndrome revisited: A telling tale of the vicissitudes of neuropsychology. Brain 133: 320–332.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shallice, T. 1988. From Neuropsychology to Mental Structure. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tsakiris, M. 2011. The sense of body ownership. In The Oxford Handbook of the Self, ed. S. Gallagher. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. 2003. Consciousness and Persons. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Young, A. W. and K. M. Leafhead. 1996. Betwixt life and death: Case studies of the Cotard delusion. In Halligan, P.W.; Marshall, J.C. Method in Madness: Case studies in Cognitive Neuropsychiatry. Hove: Psychology Press.

  • Zahavi, D., and U. Kriegel. 2015. For-me-ness: What it is and what it is not. In Philosophy of Mind and Phenomenology, ed. D. Dahlstrom, A. Elpidorou, and W. Hopp, 36–53. Abingdon: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am grateful for comments from Alexandre Billon and an anonymous referee.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to José Luis Bermúdez.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Bermúdez, J.L. Bodily Ownership, Psychological Ownership, and Psychopathology. Rev.Phil.Psych. 10, 263–280 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-018-0406-3

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-018-0406-3

Navigation