Introduction

In contemporary bioethics, the human enhancement debate focuses on the ethical ramifications of improving ourselves through the use of increasingly sophisticated forms of medicine and technology.Footnote 1 Some of this literature focuses on the possibility of enhancing our moral motivations and behaviour,Footnote 2 while other work in this area focuses instead on the ways in which drugs might improve our emotional lives and our closest relationships.Footnote 3 In this paper, our primary interest will be in cognitive enhancement, which involves improving or augmenting “internal or external information processing systems” [8]—in particular, we will consider one way in which cognitive enhancement might, counterintuitively, make us worse off. While there is lively debate about the conditions under which a given intervention constitutes an enhancement, we can think of cognitive enhancements generally as standing in contrast with therapeutic improvements—i.e., interventions that merely repair or treat some form of dysfunction.Footnote 4 In other words, cognitive enhancements improve cognitive dispositions, performances, capacities and well-being in a way that goes beyond correcting pathology [2].Footnote 5

Of course, there are many widely accepted ways of improving cognitive capacities beyond the baseline—for example, taking part in study sessions, ingesting caffeine, and eating a healthy diet. However, the most interesting philosophical and ethical questions arise when we turn to interventions that might have more potent effects. Relevant current and possible future examples include brain computer interfaces (BCIs),Footnote 6 neural implants, genetic engineering,Footnote 7 and pharmacological cognitive enhancements (hereafter, PCEs)Footnote 8—drugs that improve our memory, focus, intelligence, and so on. Our central concern in this paper relates to the use of current and future PCEs (for example, modafinil, amphetamines, methylphenidate, and future drugs that likely use similar neurological mechanisms). However, as we’ll later explore, our conclusion also has important and surprising ramifications for how we might think of some of these other forms of enhancement.

It’s obvious why PCEs are alluring. On a personal level, an effective cognitive enhancement drug might provide an edge in one’s career, make one a shaper conversationalist, and help one learn new skills at a faster rate (as well as perform old skills more effectively).Footnote 9 Further, when we think about the well-being of society more broadly, there is good reason to suppose that PCEs could help to increase the speed at which important new developments emerge to improve quality of life—treatments for currently fatal diseases, for example.

However, bioconservative ethicists warn that we should be careful about blithely endorsing the use of such enhancements. There are many different reasons why one might adopt such a cautious line, ranging from concerns about exacerbating extant inequalities in society to suggestions that boosting intelligence may not promote well-being as much as one might think.Footnote 10 Our focus in the following sections will be on one specific worry: that PCEs (and cognitive enhancement more broadly) make our achievements less valuable.

In Section 2, we’ll explore exactly why one might plausibly worry that cognitive enhancement “cheapens” achievement, and look at how one particular response—the integrationist response—is especially well-positioned to respond to this worry. In Sections 3 and 4, however, we will argue that despite the integrationist defence’s initial promise, there is a serious and unexplored dilemma waiting in the wings for current and likely future pharmacological cognitive enhancement. This reveals the Problem of Cheapened Achievements to be more difficult to address than has been appreciated. More specifically, we will show why the integrationist defence leads to a situation in which having valuable enhanced achievements come at the price of significant drug dependency and an ongoing requirement to increase dosage (thereby also increasing the risk of serious health problems). As we’ll see, whether the Problem of Cheapened Achievements can be resolved via an integrationist strategy depends very much on the future state of science and medicine.

Cognitive Enhancement, Achievement and Integration

The Cheapened Achievements Problem

Various bioconservative philosophers have advanced what we will called the cheapened achievements problem for cognitive enhancement. In some places, this is articulated as a worry about cheating (e.g., [17] or unfairness (e.g., [18]—that, for example, students who take drugs like modafinil gain an unfair advantage over their peers, and are perhaps consequently less deserving of their resulting grades. However, there is a deeper worry at play—namely, that because cognitive enhancements can help us attain our cognitive goals faster and with less effort, the resulting achievements themselves are importantly less valuable than if the same goals were attained without enhancement.Footnote 11 This means that even if considerations to do with competition and fairness are controlled for, we still have a reason to view cognitive enhancement in a negative light, if we care about having valuable achievements. The question at the heart of this sort of worry is neatly summarised by Bostrom and Sandberg [8], who ask: “If cognitive abilities are for sale, in the form of a pill or some external aid, would that reduce their value and make them less admirable?”

To illustrate the Cheapened Achievements Problem with a thought experiment,Footnote 12 let’s suppose that within the same 6-month period, two authors write excellent autobiographies based on their life experiences—and let’s build into the case the fact that they will earn the same amount of money and reach the same level of critical acclaim. However, imagine that the first author completes her book using nothing more than coffee and willpower, while the second takes a daily dose of a powerful cognitive enhancement drug that improves her focus, reduces her need for sleep, boosts her memory and speeds up her problem-solving ability. One might be very tempted indeed to credit the second author—the cognitively enhanced author—with a less significant achievement. And if we were to be told that this mirrored her own evaluation of her achievement, we would likely not be surprised.Footnote 13

We can find many articulations of the cheapened achievements objection within the bioconservative literature. For example, Kass [21] holds that we lose something of significance when our cognitive functioning is enhanced via drugs or technologies. In particular, he argues, enhancement divorces performance from effort, giving us an “easy life” filled with “trivial” achievements that could otherwise have been valuable. Similarly, Carter and Pritchard [22] draw a useful analogy to computer games here: if we’re trying to complete a difficult quest in a game and use a cheat code to super-charge our avatar and get rid of obstacles, it seems like the resulting success is less of an achievement that it would otherwise have been.Footnote 14 Meanwhile, Harris [23] talks about the importance of our “freedom to fall”, suggesting that great achievements that rely heavily on enhancement technologies mean less due to a dramatically diminished likelihood of making errors. In a similar vein, Agar [24] suggests that our human fallibility with respect to achievements plays a significant role in the strong emotional response we have to success. Further, in Sandel [, pp. 25–26] we find the cheapened achievements objection framed in terms of credit and diminished agency—Sandel argues that the more one relies on enhancement for an achievement, the more “our admiration for the achievement shifts from the [agent] to their pharmacist.”25

The above kind of thinking is quite right, we might think, to suggest that we care when external factors influence our achievements.Footnote 15 Indeed, even outside of the debate, we can see complementary claims being made. For example, in the literature on the nature and normativity of achievement, Gwen Bradford [27] argues that overcoming difficulty is a necessary component of achievements, and that exerting the kind of effort demanded by difficulty is responsible for their value.Footnote 16 Indeed, perhaps it is considerations of difficulty and effort that explain the difference in our reactions to the two authors in our example case above.Footnote 17 In short: there is a compelling worry that when we make success easier, the resulting achievements are less valuable. Now, is there room for the cognitive enhancement advocate to give a convincing reply?

The Bioconservative and Transhumanist Replies

One reply to the Cheapened Achievements Problem is to simply bite the bullet when it comes to the alleged tension between cognitive enhancements and valuable achievements. Such a line would involve simply accepting that in order to maximise the value of our cognitive achievements, we should, ceteris paribus, maximally forego enhancements. Of course, in some cases, other overriding considerations will matter more than the value of an achievement. For example, if one is trying to cure some form of cancer and can do so faster with the help of a PCE and a brain computer interface, the diminished value of that achievement plausibly means very little compared to the resulting reduction in suffering and leap in scientific knowledge. However, as the bioconservative response maintains, from the perspective where what we care about is maximising the value of our achievements, we ought to give cognitive enhancements a wide berth. This, it would seem, is the view that thinkers along the lines of Kass and Sandel would adopt.

However, perhaps the bioconservative reply is too quick. Perhaps there’s a better potential response to the cheapened achievements objection—one that allows us to take greater ownership of enhanced achievements, provided certain conditions are met.

A first pass at a more optimistic line here is found at the opposite end of the spectrum, at which the transhumanist might argue that there’s nothing problematic whatsoever about enhanced achievements—we are, as Andy Clark suggests in Natural Born Cyborgs [30], a species that has evolved to develop and use tools for augmenting our capacities, and continual pursuit of enhancement is just a mark of being human. However, this kind of reply to the Cheapened Achievements Problem involves effectively denying the prima facie plausible intuition underlying the problem—one that we saw (e.g., in the ‘two writers’ case) is widespread and compelling, and for which the transhumanist would arguably have to provide some kind of error theory. Put another way, the transhumanist recommends we avoid the problem, but in a way that would leave it mysterious why we were even drug into it in the first place.

A more moderate response would not quite bite the bullet, but would still account for the weight of the cheapened achievements objection. A promising way to develop such a moderate line maintains that the extent to which enhanced achievements are valuable is itself sensitive to facts about the relevant biotechnology and the agent’s interaction with that biotechnology. The most promising version of that line of reply appears to be the integrationist reply to the Cheapened Achievements Problem, to which we’ll now turn.

The Integrationist Reply

At this point in the dialectic, the defender of cognitive enhancement is in a position to make good use of recent work on cognitive achievements in social and virtue epistemology. The simple template structure of this reply first gives us a more detailed definition of achievement—that it is, borrowing from virtue epistemology (e.g., [31]), a success that is because of (i.e., primarily creditable to) ability.Footnote 18 Such a proposal explains why, for example, an arrow shot by a skilled archer is not an achievement even if it hits the target, if it does so simply because of a fluke gust of wind, or because (say) the arrow had a ‘target detecting’ robot attached to it, which ensured it would hit the target. In such cases, the shot is successful in the sense that it attained the aim of hitting the target, but in such cases the shot is not successful because of the archer’s skill, but because of something (e.g., wind, or the robot) external to their agency.Footnote 19

With this simple “success because ability” structural view of achievement in play, then (for any given cognitive enhancement and achievement) we ought to be asking: is the relevant success sufficiently creditable to the person’s ability? While the bioconservative would say ‘no’ and the transhumanist would ‘say’ yes—but in each case at the cost of incurring some theoretical baggage—the more nuanced integrationist line maintains that the matter of whether—or to what extent—using a given cognitive enhancement will cheapen an achievement will depend crucially on how we use the enhancement. As this line of thought goes, there are factors that can contribute to making cognitive enhancements (such as PCEs) suitably integrated into our cognitive architecture—into us, in a sense—such that the resulting success is appropriately creditable to our abilities. And this is so even if there are some enhancements we depend on but which are not integrated in such a way.

The core idea submitted by the integrationist is that the less an enhancement is cognitively integrated into our cognitive architecture, the less the ensuing success we get by relying on the enhancement is actually creditable to our own cognitive abilities. On the other side of the coin, if the enhancement is integrated (enough), then there is no barrier to attributing the success to our abilities.Footnote 20

The natural question at this juncture is this: what, then, is required for the kind of integration that matters for achievement? Here we find a range of answers in social epistemology. In a bit more detail, different philosophers have different explanations for what we needs to happen for some ‘extra organismic’ scaffolding (including pharmacological cognitive enhancementsFootnote 21) to become integrated in our cognitive architecture in such a way that the success we get by relying on it would be creditable to our abilities. Some suggested necessary conditions include the following (wherein, for ease of reference, ‘D’ represents the relevant drug):

The process awareness condition (e.g., [26]): D is integrated only if the subject forms an accurate view of how the wider processes that D uses is reliable.

The sensitivity condition (e.g., [36, 37]): D is integrated only if the subject is sensitive to different ways that D might malfunction.

The transparency condition (e.g., [38, 39]): D is integrated only if D plays the role it does in a way that is transparent, i.e., such that you don’t critically scrutinise it.

While these are all different possible necessary conditions on a PCE’s being suitably cognitively integrated, all of these authors share a point of commonality: that it takes time for these conditions to be met. As Pritchard [, p. 148] puts it, our intuition about whether certain cognitive achievements (e.g., knowledge) are creditable to the agent may be negative at first, but “as time goes on this intuition lessens.” Meanwhile, as Heersmink [, p. 589] notes with respect to the transparency condition, novice users of a cognitive enhancement typically lack this transparency, and achieving it transparency “in most cases, needs training and may take a 26, 39considerable amount of time” (italics ours).

The thought that these conditions are better met over a lengthy period of enhancement use makes sense. For example, it stands to reason that the transparency condition is better met the longer a drug is taken—when one begins taking a PCE, it is a novel experience that would likely prompt reflection on differences in thinking, in focus, and so on. However, as one becomes habituated to taking the relevant PCE, the normalisation of its use plausibly reduces the likelihood of one paying much attention to its normal functioning. Sheer duration of use over an extended period of time also clearly better positions one to satisfy both the process awareness condition and the sensitivity condition—the longer one takes a PCE, the better placed one is, with reference to accumulated track record evidence, to understand both how and when the PCE works, and to be alert if something goes wrong (e.g., picking up on the signs that something—such as taking a PCE with a large mealFootnote 22—has slowed down the speed at the drug is absorbed and takes effect).

Accordingly, then, advocates of all three of the above potential necessary conditions on cognitive integration agree that the best way to meet these necessary conditions is to use the enhancement reliably over time. In sum, this consistent, repeated use is a key part of what is supposed to allow us to integrate a cognitive enhancement in a way that suffices for enhancement-facilitated successes to be valuable achievements.

For present purposes, we will set aside substantive critiques of the integrationist line itself, and accept that it does offer at least a prima facie plausible response to the Cheapened Achievements Problem—especially when compared to the other two main responses. Against that background, we want to focus on how research in medicine and pharmacology illuminates an unexplored dilemma for the integrationist strategy just sketched—one that reveals the Problem of Cheapened Achievements to be more difficult to address than has been appreciated (at least in some cases).

However, before proceeding, we want to clarify two additional points about the integrationist reply, in order to make explicit what it does and does not take for granted. For one thing, the integrationist line is assuming two ability-based claims about the structure of achievements and about their value—viz., that (i) achievements are successes primarily creditable to ability; and that (ii) the source of the value of an achievement (over and above the value of a mere success) lies in part in the success’s arising from ability.

While both assumptions (i) and (ii) are common in the literature on achievement in virtue epistemology [33, 41, 35], see also [42], they invite the following kind of rejoinder to assumption (i): no success is due entirely to an individual’s ability, nor could it be rightly credited (entirely) to such an ability. This is because the fact that we have the dispositions, including abilities, we have is itself highly contingent upon other previous causes—including to a kind of egalitarian ‘brute luck’Footnote 23 (e.g., in the cognitive case, that we were born with particular kinds of cognitive faculties rather than others).Footnote 24 Appreciation of this point, the rejoinder maintains, suggests it is mistaken to articulate achievements as successes primarily due to individuals themselves, ignoring the extent to which individuals’ own capacities are always themselves beholden to fortune. In response to this concern, it’s important to clarify the kind of ‘template’ characterisation of achievement that the integrationist is taking for granted, and which is standard in virtue epistemology. Crucially, primary credit can be understood in a strong, unrestricted sense (where ability would be contrasted on equal footing with all other factors that feature in a complete history of the relevant success), or in a more restricted sense that is indexed to causal-explanatory salience (Greco 2007, [41]). On the latter view—which is what we have in mind—what the kind of attribution of success to ability that lines up with achievement requires is just that one’s ability be (following here John Greco [41]) what is most explanatorily salient when giving an explanation of the relevant success—viz., as the most salient part of the causal explanation for the success. This articulation is compatible with there being a wide number of factors that play a role in the causal history of the relevant success.

A second point of clarification concerns assumption (ii), viz., that the source of the value of an achievement (over and above the value of a mere success) lies in part in the success’s arising from ability. This is, we want to emphasise, a minimal assumption about what contributes to the value of achievement, and it is not meant to rule out possible alternative sources of the value of achievement whenever a success is primarily due to ability. For example, when a success is primarily due to ability, it might be that the achievement gains additional value in virtue of the level of exertion, or will-power exercised by the agent, and regardless of how high-level her capacity is to perform. Theoretically, at least, there is no barrier to the possibility (e.g., in the more long-term future) that these other contributory sources of value to an achievement might themselves be susceptible to enhancement.Footnote 25 For example, on the assumption that a success primarily due to ability is such that its value is (in some contexts) magnified by the addition of additional exertion or manifestation of will power, we could envision cases where that very will-power or effort capacity is itself subject to a kind of ‘boost’ via enhancement. We want to register that an integrationist line—given the assumptions it makes about achievement and its value—is not incompatible with countenancing such an idea, and it can diagnose achievement cases featuring a valuable exertion of will-power in a principled way. In short, on the integrationist line, an enhancement that directly impacts will power (in the way described above) is either itself going to be suitably integrated, or not; if yes, then the enhancement is not a barrier to whatever value willpower-exertion adds to the value of a given achievement. If no, then the integrationist line is able to get the right result, given that, on this supposition, the willpower’s contribution would not be suitably creditable attributable to the agent.

Cognitive Enhancement and the Risk of Dependence

As it turns out, a potential worry for the integrationist reply to the Cheapened Achievements Problem lies waiting in the wings. In order to uncover the worry, it will be important to consider some of the costs of integration itself, in the case of pharmacological cognitive enhancements.

Provisional PCEs: a Primer

Adderall, Ritalin and Modafinil are most commonly discussed as viable examples or prototypes in the cognitive enhancement debate—consequently, we will call these “provisional PCEs”. It is when we look at their theorised mechanism of action and effects that we begin to see specific risks they pose—risks that, we will argue, have a specific and important implication for integrationist replies to the Cheapened Achievements Problem.

Adderall is a mixed amphetamine salt, peak plasma concentrations of which peak approximately 3 h post-ingestion.Footnote 26 Amphetamines are sympathomimetic noncatecholamines with CNS stimulant activity—their mechanism is poorly understood, but they are thought to limit reuptake of dopamine and noradrenaline to the presynaptic terminal. Crucially, amphetamines target the same receptors as the body’s endogenous catecholamines, such as dopamine and noradrenaline. The chemical structure of amphetamines is very similar to those of the brain’s monoamine neurotransmitters. Due to their sharing of a similar chemical structure, amphetamines are competitive substrates for transporters of the brain’s own monoamine neurotransmitters, some of the most important being the transporter for noradrenaline (NET), dopamine (DAT) and serotonin or 5-HT (SERT). The ingestion of amphetamine accordingly causes changes in the levels of these neurons, and it is from the changing extracellular levels of these neurons that the behavioural and physical effects of amphetamines result. As powerful psychostimulants, they increase feelings of alertness, euphoria and wakefulness. They take primary effect centrally, however they also exert peripheral, autonomic side-effects, like sweating, nausea and tachycardia. Breathing rate increases, blood pressure increases and locomotor changes are seen. The mood changes are described as affecting feelings of ‘novelty, arousal, anxiety [and] reward’ [45].

Methylphenidate Hydrochloride (i.e., MPH)—commonly known as Ritalin—is a psychostimulant with similar properties, with the immediate-release tablets reaching their maximum concentration in just under 2 h.Footnote 27 In its increase of extracellular dopamine levels, MPH amplifies task-specific signal-amplifying and noise-reducing effects of dopamine, meaning the subject taking MPH becomes less easily distractible and more focused and attentive—for example, Volkow et al. [46] determined that MPH-facilitated dopamine increases would likely increase the ‘interest [the task] elicits’ and therefore improve the subject’s performance in that task. Peripheral side effects include agitation and aggression, autonomic effects such as increased heart rate, raised blood pressure and visual disturbances. Further, MPH should be used with caution in those with a psychiatric history, including previous psychosis or bipolar disorder, and in a small number of cases (0.1%) it can elicit new psychosis or manic symptoms. Due to inter-individual variability in users of CNS stimulant drugs, it is currently ‘difficult to predict’ who will respond well to the drug [47]. Like amphetamine, the mechanism of action of this provisional PCE.

remains vague, but MPH is thought to stimulate dopamine release from the presynaptic vesicles, and inhibit dopamine reuptake back into presynaptic neurons—less selectively than amphetamine [48].

The third notable provisional PCE we will consider herein is modafinil (i.e., Provigil), a non-amphetamine type oral stimulant commonly used to treat narcolepsy (a brain condition that causes a person to fall asleep suddenly at inappropriate times).Footnote 28 The maximum drug concentrations in the circulation are reached after 2–4 h, and steady states of modafinil are achieved after 2–4 days of taking the drug. Modafinil is best known for its promotion of alertness and reducing daytime sleepiness, but it also causes mood changes and alters perception and thinking. Again, as with both Adderall (i.e., mixed amphetamine salt) and Methylphenidate, the mechanism of action of Modafinil is not well understood—it appears to act similarly to the sympathomimetic agents, yet along different mechanisms. Some studies have suggested that Modafinil action is dependent upon the dopamine transporter (DAT) and has weak interactions with dopamine, noradrenaline, orexin, histamine and serotonin receptors [50]—though it doesn’t seem to promote spontaneous release of dopamine in the same way as amphetamine [50, 51].

Why Provisional PCEs Come with a Burden of Tolerance, Dependence and Abuse Potential

Drug tolerance results after continued, ‘chronic’ use (i.e., continued use over time) creating a dependence which in turn results in the ‘progressive requirement to use higher drug doses to produce a given effect’ (increasing the risk of side effects).Footnote 29 Tolerance—where regular increases in dose are required maintain effectiveness—also boosts the risk of dangerous side effects. In the case of provisional PCEs, the brain is not programmed to have consistently high levels of these extracellular neurotransmitters, and its homeostatic mechanisms cause it to try and counter the effects of the stimulant drugs. In order to adapt, the brain produces less neurotransmitters and expresses less neurotransmitter receptors, creating a hypofunctioning reward system that makes the effects of the drugs become less potent—prompting users to take more of the drug.

Dependence, meanwhile, encompasses two facets: physiological dependence and psychological dependence.Footnote 30

Physiological dependence: an adaptive state that manifests itself by intense physical disturbances when the administration of a drug is suspended.

Psychological dependence: a condition in which a drug produces a feeling of satisfaction and psychic drive that requires periodic or continuous administration of the drug to produce pleasure or to avoid discomfort.

Drug dependence is thought to begin with positive reinforcement [54]—the user experiences the euphoria and cognitive assonance of the stimulant, which corresponds with an increased desire to continue their drug use. In the case of provisional PCEs such as those above, noradrenaline plays a role in increasing energy, and dopamine provides a pleasurable feeling of wellbeing. Later, negative reinforcement then joins the previous, positive reinforcement—after stopping drug intake for a period, the user experiences unpleasant withdrawal symptoms (e.g., dysphoria, decreased activity, lack of independent thought and increased drowsiness), and this prompts chronic use of the drug. Consequently, negative reinforcement is referred to as the “driving force of addiction” [55].

There is a particularly high abuse potential—a drug’s ability to keep a person dependent on it with provisional PCEs and any drugs that act similarly. Once it is cleared, the ‘up’ effects of a provisional PCE will wear off, causing the user to feel relatively ‘down’. The capacity of the drug to then correct the negative feeling its absence has left encourages the user to continue their use of the drug. The physical reasons for the abuse potential of provisional PCEs include the fact that they provide increased energy (via noradrenaline production) and a pleasurable feeling of well-being (via dopamine production).Footnote 31 Meanwhile, some psychological reasons for this might include the confidence, self-esteem and day-to-day happiness that will likely wax and wane depending on whether one is experiencing the peak of cognition-sharpening effects of cognitive enhancement.Footnote 32

Abuse potential is unsurprisingly related to addiction potential.Footnote 33Not everyone who uses—or even abuses—a substance becomes an “addict”, and it is not completely clear in the literature as to how to spot someone likely to be predisposed to addictive vulnerability (for example, some studies discuss genetic factors (e.g., [57] whilst others e.g., [58] detail environmental or social problems). Regardless of individual variances in susceptibility, Morton and Stock [59] note that clinicians should judge the potency of methylphenidate—for example—using descriptions of the effects elicited by better-known addictive substances, such as cocaine and methamphetamine (its more well-known, addictive relatives). And although modafinil is generally thought to be less worrying in this respect, some research (e.g., [55] suggests that it increases the rating scale of the Addiction Research Center Inventory (ARCI) “as much as amphetamine.”

Sussman and Sussman [, pp. 4026–4030] provide an account of the five main components central to forming addictions, and it is easy to see how provisional PCEs could lead to meeting these conditions.60

  1. 1.

    Partaking in a certain course of action to fulfil motives (e.g., taking amphetamines to study more effectively).

  2. 2.

    Becoming preoccupied with that course of action (e.g., thinking about taking “smart drugs” more and more frequently),

  3. 3.

    Temporary satiation: a small time period which occurs after starting a habit where the “drug” or other tool does work to provide the user with feelings of fulfilment and satisfaction, without the appearance of cravings.

  4. 4.

    Loss of control: when a user wants to stop their use of the drug or other action but not being aware of how to control urges and prevent future use; ‘the addictive behaviour may become increasingly more automatic’ (e.g., one simply takes a nootropic as soon as they get up, or as soon as they sit down to take part in an academic task).

  5. 5.

    Suffering negative consequences (e.g., ‘physical discomfort’, like feeling agitated or withdrawn without amphetamines, or ‘financial loss’, after spending £50 a week (a rough approximation) on PCEs).

The potential for abuse (and possible addiction) is emphasized throughout the literature and should serve as a warning to clinicians. We also suggest that the changing function of these drugs from therapeutic interventions to enhancements carries the risk of aggravating abuse potential. And—perhaps most importantly—we have good reason to think that we can expect future PCEs to carry similar risks given the relevant underlying neurological mechanisms. Most future PCEs are likely to also exert action upon noradrenaline and dopamine’s extracellular concentrations, translating to increase cognitive capacities (e.g., alertness, focus, and processing speed)—and so come with the same risks as provisional PCEs.

Crucially, these concerns are just as likely to apply to future PCEs. Note that the provisional PCEs discussed herein are classed as such because of their neurological mechanisms. They all exert action upon noradrenaline and dopamine’s extracellular concentrations, and through this specific means, they take effect in ways that translate into increasing our cognitive capacities, whether this is through increased alertness or wakefulness, or increased ability to focus. Now, Adderall, Ritalin and Modafinil are “back-door” PCEsFootnote 34—their current pharmaceutical indication is not to cognitively enhance healthy individuals, but to treat those with identified disorders (e.g., ADHD and narcolepsy). However, with their prominent presence in the human enhancement literature, it is fair to assume that future PCEs will be based on refined examples of these drugs. This means that we shall face the same problems as we do with the current provisional PCEs.

In sum, the important takeaway here, for our purposes, is this: provisional PCEs carry with them a burden of tolerance and dependence, as well as a high potential for abuse—and these are all worries that will apply equally to future drugs using similar mechanisms. We’ll now explore how this create a serious difficulty for the integrationist reply to the Cheapened Achievements Problem.

Cognitive Enhancement and Integration: A Dilemma

The likely possibility of dependence and abuse (also correlated with higher likelihood of risks to health) seems to throw a new spanner in the works, in so far as we might appeal to an integrationist line as a response to the Problem of Cheapened Achievements. In particular, in light of the empirical results just canvassed, it looks like we’re left with the following prima facie problematic options:

Horn 1: Valuable achievements (due to appropriately integrated cognitive enhancements) at the risk of tolerance and dependence (and all the associated safety risks) due to consistent, long-term use.

Horn 2: Avoid tolerance/dependence through more sporadic use, but at the cost of integration and thereby of valuable achievements.

In the face of this dilemma, it looks like the three most salient lines of reply are as follows. Firstly, we could simply give up on any kind of integrationist reply—which, recall, pursues a middle ground to the Achievements Problem—and instead embrace one of the extremes (a strong bioconservative line or a transhumanist line). Problematically, however, neither of those other positions was promising. The second option on the table is to take horn 1 of the dilemma for the integrationist and preserve the value of enhancement-aided achievement at the cost of physical dependency (and its attendant risks). Meanwhile, the third option involves taking horn 2 of the dilemma—avoiding drug dependency (i.e., via only sporadic use) at the cost of the kind of integration that is plausibly needed to make sense of how the enhancement-aided success is an achievement to which we can credit you.

None of these options looks particularly appealing. So, does this mean that the Cheapened Achievements Problem is simply unresolvable? In spite of raising the above dilemma for the integrationist, we want to close by suggesting that it’s too early to simply conclude that there’s no satisfying response to the Cheapened Achievements Problem. More specifically, notice that one of the key contributors to the dilemma for the integrationist response is the fact that current pharmacological cognitive enhancements have some of the side effects they do—but this is only contingently so. It is not an essential feature of cognitive enhancements (pharmacological or otherwise) that they, for example, are detrimentally dependency-forming in the ways that current pharmacological enhancements are.

The foregoing observation offers us a new vantage point to realistically assess the Cheapened Achievements Problem. Rather than to either give up on the integrationist reply in favour of one of the ‘nonstarter’ responses, or to think that either horn 1 or horn 2 of the dilemma for the integrationist reply as (given currently technologies) clearly preferable to the other, we are in a position to view the lay of the land with a clear head. The realistic view here is that preserving the value of pharmacologically enhanced achievements might work in the future. This will depend on the future of medicine and technology—on whether pharmacological bioenhancements will be developed that can be used more than merely sporadically but without the relationship to dependency and other side effects that empirical research shows our current options have.

Meanwhile, if such pharmacological cognitive enhancement cannot be developed, then we still have the potential to have enhanced achievements that are primarily creditable to us (via integration)—so long as we are using technology-based enhancements like BCIs and implants, and we use these pieces of technology in the way required to meet the conditions for cognitive integration.Footnote 35 To the extent that we value cognitive achievement, the foregoing also recommends that we direct cognitive enhancement research toward technological solutions as opposed to pharmacological interventions.

Concluding Remarks

We have explored several potential response to the common worry that cognitive enhancement may “cheapen” cognitive achievement. After dismissing the transhumanist and bioconservative responses as problematic in principle for different reasons, we highlighted the comparatively more promising integrationist defence—a line of argument that draws on social and virtue epistemology to respond to the Problem of Cheapened Achievements. However, in unpacking the temporal component of this defence and considering the risks associated with cognitive enhancement drugs that share a particular set of neural mechanisms, we saw that the integrationist is faced with a dilemma. They can risk dependency and addiction while gaining credit for their cognitive achievements (and thereby retaining their value), or they can avoid such physical and psychological risks but forego integration and the valuable achievements it brings.Footnote 36