Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Human Rights Without Political Participation?

  • Published:
Human Rights Review Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

John Rawls claims that “benevolent absolutisms” honor human rights without honoring political participation rights. Critics argue that he is mistaken. One objection appeals to the instrumental value of political participation rights. This objection holds that without political participation rights, individuals cannot secure the content of their rights against encroachment. Given this, individuals without political participation rights cannot be said to have rights at all. Here, I evaluate this instrumental objection. I identify three ways of relating political participation rights to human rights and show that one makes sense of Rawls’s claim. I then defend this view from instrumental objections. This has implications beyond the realm of Rawls scholarship. Many societies are not democratic and are not democratizing. We must determine whether any of these societies can secure at least the content of human rights and, if so, what shape their social and political institutions must take to do so.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Rawls mentions these societies three times. On two occasions, he says they “honor human rights,” but on another occasion, he says they honor “most” human rights. He does not explain the difference.

  2. I want to thank two anonymous reviewers for getting me to consider this objection.

  3. A liberal society has a “common good” too, says Rawls: “achieving political justice for all its citizens over time and preserving the free culture that justice allows” (1999, p. 71).

  4. Rawls leaves open the question of whether there are other, non-associationist decent societies.

  5. Reidy does not comment on the distinction Rawls seems to draw between human rights proper and political participation rights.

  6. In fact, it may be the case that even thin democratic participation cannot secure the content of rights generally in this way. As I pointed out earlier, the logic of elections and thin democratic participation is inadequate as an account of the success modern liberal societies have in securing the content of human rights for all.

  7. Again, it is fair to ask if this should count as an absolutism. I will address this concern in the final section of the paper.

  8. An anonymous reviewer suggests that what Rawls says in A Theory of Justice (1999, rev. ed., Section 70) about the morality of authority is not consistent with the idea that absolutisms can honor human rights as rights. This is a very interesting piece of the puzzle, and I am not sure how it might fit. My initial reaction is to wonder if the moral psychology Rawls develops in A Theory of Justice can be easily transferred to the case of benevolent absolutisms. I am not sure that it can. We should distinguish the children Rawls discusses, who lack the knowledge and understanding they would need to assess parental injunctions, from the subjects of a benevolent leader who might have the knowledge and understanding they would need to assess government injunctions, but who are never offered an opportunity to do so. In any case, this is an issue that requires a better response than I can give at this point.

References

  • Besley T, Kudamatsu M (2007) Making Autocracy Work. DEDPS 48. Suntory and Toyota International Centres for Economics and Related Disciplines, London School of Economics and Political Science, London, UK.

  • Buchanan A (2004) Justice, Legitimacy, and Self-Determination. Oxford University Press, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bueno De Mesquita B, Downs G, Smith A, Cherif FM (2005) Thinking Inside the Box: A Closer Look at Democracy and Human Rights. Int Stud Q 49, pp. 439–457.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carothers T (2002) The End of the Transition Paradigm. J Democracy 13, pp. 5–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christiano T (2011) An Instrumental Argument for a Right to Democracy. Philos & Public Aff 39(2), pp. 142–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eule J (1990) Judicial Review of Direct Democracy. Yale Law J 99, pp. 1503–1589.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freedom House (2013) Freedom in the World 2013: Democratic Breakthroughs in the Balance. http://www.freedomhouse.org/report/freedom-world/freedom-world-2013.

  • Freeman S (1992) Original Meaning, Democratic Interpretation, and the Constitution. Philos & Public Aff 21(1), pp. 3–42.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frey B, Goette L (1998) Does the Popular Vote Destroy Civil Rights? Am J Polit Sci 42(4), pp. 1343–1348.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gamble B (1997) Putting Civil Rights to a Popular Vote. Am J Polit Sci 41(1), pp. 245–269.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hajnal Z, Gerber E, Louch H (2002) Minorities and Direct Legislation: Evidence from California Ballot Proposition Elections. J Polit 64(1), pp. 154–177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kurlantzick J (2013) Democracy in Retreat: The Revolt of the Middle Class and the Worldwide Decline of Representative Government. Yale University Press, New Haven, CT.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis D (2011) Direct Democracy and Minority Rights: Same-Sex Marriage Bans in the U.S. States. Soc Sci Q 92(2), pp. 364–382.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lupia A, Matsusaka J (2004) Direct Democracy: New Approaches to Old Questions. Annu Rev Polit Sci 7, pp. 463–482.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nickel JW (2007) Making Sense of Human Rights, 2nd ed. Blackwell, Malden, Ma.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls J (1993) Political Liberalism. Columbia University Press, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls J (1999) The Law of Peoples. Harvard University Press, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reidy D (2006) Political Authority and Human Rights. In: Martin R, Reidy D (eds.). Rawls’s Law of Peoples: A Realistic Utopia?, pp. 169–88. Blackwell, Malden, Ma.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Reidy D (2012) On the Human Right to Democracy: Searching for Sense Without Stilts. J Soc Philos 43(2), pp. 177–203.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shue H (1996) Basic Rights: Subsistence, Affluence, and U.S. Foreign Policy, 2nd ed. Princeton University Press, Princeton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith PH, Ziegler MR (2008) Liberal and Illiberal Democracy in Latin America. Lat Am Polit Soc 50, pp. 31–57.

  • Steiner H (1998) Political Participation as a Human Right. Hum Rights Yearbook 1, pp. 77–134.

  • Voice P (2011) Rawls Explained: From Fairness to Utopia. Open Court Press, Chicago.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zakaria F (2003) The Future of Freedom: Illiberal Democracy at Home and Abroad. W. W. Norton, New York.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Walter J. Riker.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Riker, W.J. Human Rights Without Political Participation?. Hum Rights Rev 15, 369–390 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12142-014-0341-3

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12142-014-0341-3

Keywords

Navigation