Skip to main content
Log in

Weakly continuous security and nash equilibrium

  • Published:
Theory and Decision Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper investigates the existence of pure strategy Nash equilibria in discontinuous and nonquasiconcave games. We introduce a new notion of continuity, called weakly continuous security, which is weaker than the most known weak notions of continuity, including the surrogate point secure of SSYM game of Carbonell-Nicolau and Mclean (Econ Theory, 2018a), the continuous security of Barelli and Meneghel (Econometrica 81:813–824, 2013), C-security of McLennan et al. (Econometrica 79:1643–1664 2011), generalized weakly transfer continuity of Nessah (Economics 47:659–662, 2011), generalized better-reply security of Carmona (Econ Theory 48:1–4, 2011), Barelli and Soza (On the existence of Nash equilibria in discontinuous and qualitative games, 2009), Barelli and Meneghel (Econometrica 81:813–824, 2013), lower single deviation property of Reny (Further results on the existence of Nash equilibria in discontinuous games. University of Chicago, 2009), better-reply security of Reny (Econometrica 67:1029–1056, 1999) and the results of Prokopovych (Econ Theory 48:5–16, 2011, Econ Theory 53:383–402, 2013) and Carmona (J Econ Theory 144:1333–1340, 2009). We show that a compact, convex and weakly continuous secure Hausdorff locally convex topological vector space game has a pure strategy Nash equilibrium. Moreover, it holds in a large class of discontinuous games.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. A game \(G=(X_i,u_i)_{i\in I}\) is said to be continuous secure if whenever \({\overline{x}} \in X\) is not an equilibrium, there exist a neighborhood \({{\mathcal {N}}}\) of \({\overline{x}}\), \(\alpha \in {\mathbb {R}}^n\) and a well-behaved correspondence \(\phi _{{\overline{x}}}:{{\mathcal {N}}}\twoheadrightarrow X\) so that

    1. (a)

      for each \(t\in {{\mathcal {N}}}\), and \(i\in I\), we have \(\phi _{{\overline{x}},i}(t)\subseteq B_i(t,\alpha _i)\), and

    2. (b)

      for each \(z\in {{\mathcal {N}}}\), there exists a player j for whom, \(z_j\notin co B_j(z,\alpha _j)\),

    where \(B_i(x,\alpha _i)=\{y_i\in X_i\text { such that }u_i(y_i,x_{-i})\ge \alpha _i\}\).

  2. A game \(G=(X_i,u_i)_{i\in I}\) has the generalized deviation property if whenever \({\overline{x}} \in X\) is not an equilibrium, there exist a neighborhood \({{\mathcal {N}}}\) of \({\overline{x}}\), and a correspondence \(\phi _{{\overline{x}}}:{{\mathcal {N}}}\twoheadrightarrow X\) (having a closed graph and nonempty and convex values) so that for each \(z\in \mathcal{N}\), there exists a player j for whom, \(u^{\phi }_j(y^{'}_j, t^{'}_{-j})> u_j(z)\), for each \((t^{'},y^{'}_j)\in \text {Graph}(\phi _i)\).

  3. A game \(G=(X_i,u_i)_{i\in I}\) is generalized better-reply secure if whenever \((x,u)\in \text {cl}(\Gamma )\) and x is not an equilibrium, then there exist a player i, an \(\alpha >u_i\), a neighborhood \({{\mathcal {N}}}\) of \(x_{-i}\) and a well-behaved correspondence \(\phi _i:{{\mathcal {N}}}\twoheadrightarrow X_i\) such that \(u_i(z)\ge \alpha \), for each \(z\in \text {Graph}(\phi _i)\).

  4. A game \(G=(X_{i},\text { }u_{i})_{i\in I}\) is weakly reciprocal upper semicontinuous, if for any \((x, u)\in \text {Fr}(\Gamma )\), there is a player i and \({\hat{x}}_i\in X_i\) such that \(u_i({\hat{x}}_i,x_{-i})>u_i\).

  5. A game \(G=(X_i,u_i)_{i\in I}\) is said to be generalized weakly transfer continuous if whenever \(x^{*} \in X\) is not an equilibrium, there exist a player i, a neighborhood \(\mathcal{N}(x^{*})\) of \(x^{*}\) and a well-behaved correspondence \(\varphi _i:{{\mathcal {N}}}(x^{*})\twoheadrightarrow X_i\) such that \(\underset{(z,y_i)\in \text {Graph}(\varphi _i)}{\inf }\;\left\{ u_i(y_i, z_{-i})-u_i(z)\right\} >0\).

  6. The local security level at z means that the value of the least favorable outcome in a neighborhood of z is given by \({\underline{u}}_j(z)={\sup }_{{{\mathcal {N}}}\in \Omega (z_{-j})}\;{\sup }_{\varphi _j\in W_{\mathcal{N}}(z)}\; {\inf }_{(z_{-j}^{'},z_j^{''})\in \text {Graph}(\varphi _j)}\;u_j(z^{''}_j,z^{'}_{-j})\).

  7. If \(z_i\ne z_{-i}\), then there is a player j so that \({\underline{u}}_j(z_j,z)\le u_j(z)=\min (W(z),L(z))\) and if \(z_i=z_{-i}\), then there is a player j so that \({\underline{u}}_j(z_j,z)\le \frac{1}{2}[L(z)+W(z)]\)

  8. For more details on this model, see Rothstein (2007) and Nessah and Tian (2016).

  9. Such as the surrogate correspondence security Carbonell-Nicolau and Mclean (2018a), continuous security of Barelli and Meneghel (2013), C-secure of McLennan et al. (2011), generalized deviation property of Bich and Laraki (2017), generalized better-reply security of Barelli and Meneghel (2013), Carmona (2011a), Barelli and Soza (2009), lower single deviation property of Reny (2009), better-reply security of Reny (1999), generalized weakly transfer continuity of Nessah (2011) and the results of Prokopovych (2011; 2013) and Carmona (2009).

  10. The game \(T=(X_i,\succeq _i)_{i\in N}\) has a skew-symmetric (SSYM) representation if for each \(i\in N\), there exists a bi-function \(\varphi _i:X\times X\rightarrow {\mathbb {R}}\) such that for each \(x,y\in X\), we have i) \(\varphi _i\) is skew-symmetric, i.e., \(\varphi _i(x,y)=-\varphi _i(y,x)\) and ii) \(x\succeq _i y\) iff \(\varphi _i(x,y)\ge 0\). A skew-symmetric (SSYM) game is a collection \(T=(X_i,\varphi _i)_{i\in N}\), where \(\varphi _i:X\times X\rightarrow {\mathbb {R}}\) is skew-symmetric and each \(X_i\) is a topological space.

  11. A game \(G=(X_{i},\text { }u_{i})_{i\in I}\) has the single lower deviation property if whenever \(x^*\) is not an equilibrium, there is a player a neighborhood \({{\mathcal {N}}}\) of \(x^*\) and a strategy \({\overline{y}}\in X\) such that for each \(z\in {{\mathcal {N}}}\), there is a player j so as \({\underline{u}}_j({\overline{y}}_j,t_{-j})>{\underline{u}}_j(z)\) for all \(t\in {{\mathcal {N}}}\).

  12. Nessah (2011): A game \(G=(X_i,u_i)_{i\in I}\) is said to be generalized weakly transfer continuous if whenever \(x^{*} \in X\) is not an equilibrium, there exist a player i, a neighborhood \({{\mathcal {N}}}\) of \(x^{*}\) and a well-behaved correspondence \(\varphi _i:{{\mathcal {N}}}\twoheadrightarrow X_i\) such that \(\inf _{(z,y_i)\in \text {Graph}(\varphi _i)}\left[ u_i(y_i, z_{-i})-u_i(z)\right] >0\).

  13. Nessah and Tian (2016): A game \(G=(X_i,u_i)_{i\in I}\) is said to be quasi-weakly transfer continuous if whenever \(x^{*} \in X\) is not an equilibrium, there exists a player i, \({\overline{y}}_i\in X_i\), \(\epsilon >0\), and some neighborhoods \(\mathcal{N}\) of \(x^{*}\) such that for every \(z\in {{\mathcal {N}}}\) and every neighborhood \({{\mathcal {N}}}_z\) of z, \(u_i({\overline{y}}_i,z_{-i})> u_i(z_i,z^{'}_{-i})+\epsilon \) for some \(z^{'}\in {{\mathcal {N}}}_z\).

  14. The definition of continuously security in Barelli and Meneghel (2013) is not exactly equal to the one presented here. Barelli and Meneghel (2013) do not require well-behaved correspondence. Unfortunately, the proof of Theorem 2.2 in Barelli and Meneghel (2013) does not work without well-behaved correspondence.

References

  • Aliprantis, C. B., & Border, K. C. (2006). Infinite dimensional analysis: A Hitchhiker’s guide (3rd ed.). Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Athey, S. (2001). Single crossing properties and the existence of pure strategy equilibria in games of incomplete information. Econometrica, 69, 861–889.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bagh, A., & Jofre, A. (2006). Reciprocal upper semicontinuity and better reply secure games: A comment. Econometrica, 74, 1715–1721.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Balder, E. J. (2011). An equilibrium closure result for discontinuous games. Economic Theory, 48, 47–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barelli, P., & Meneghel, I. (2013). A note on the equilibrium existence problem in discontinuous games. Econometrica, 81, 813–824.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barelli, P., & Soza, I. (2009). On the existence of Nash equilibria in discontinuous and qualitative games. Working Paper.

  • Baye, M. R., Kovenock, D., & de Vries, C. G. (2012). Contests with rank-order spillovers. Economic Theory, 51, 315–350.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baye, M. R., Tian, G., & Zhou, J. (1993). Characterizations of the existence of equilibria in games with discontinuous and non-quasiconcave payoffs. Review of Economic Studies, 60, 935–948.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bich, P. (2009). Existence of pure Nash equilibria in discontinuous and non-quasiconcave games. International Journal of Game Theory, 38, 395–410.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bich, P., & Laraki, R. (2017). On the existence of approximate equilibria and sharing rule solution in discontinuous games. Theoretical Economics, 12, 79–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carbonell-Nicolau, O. (2011). On the existence of pure-strategy perfect equilibrium in discontinuous games. Games and Economic Behavior, 71, 23–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carbonell-Nicolau, O., & Mclean, R. P. (2018a). Nash and Bayes–Nash equilibria in strategic-form games with intransitivities. Economic Theory. https://doi.org/10.1007/s00199-018-1151-7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carbonell-Nicolau, O., & Mclean, R. P. (2018b). On the existence of Nash equilibrium in Bayesian games. Mathematics of Operations Research, 43, 100–129.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carmona, G. (2009). An existence result for discontinuous games. Journal of Economic Theory, 144, 1333–1340.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carmona, G. (2011a). Understanding some recent existence results for discontinuous games. Economic Theory, 48, 31–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carmona, G. (2011b). Symposium on: Existence of Nash equilibria in discontinuous games. Economic Theory, 48, 1–4.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carmona, G. (2016). Reducible equilibrium properties: Comments on recent existence results. Economic Theory, 61, 431–455.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carmona, G., & Podczeck, K. (2009). On the existence of pure strategy Nash equilibria in large games. Journal of Economic Theory, 144, 1300–1319.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carmona, G., & Podczeck, K. (2012). Existence of Nash equilibrium in games with a measure space of players and discontinuous payoff functions. Journal of Economic Theory, 152, 130–178.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carmona, G., & Podczeck, K. (2016). Existence of Nash equilibrium in ordinal games with discontinuous preferences. Economic Theory, 61, 457–478.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dasgupta, P., & Maskin, E. (1986). The existence of equilibrium in discontinuous economic games, I: Theory. Review of Economic Studies, 53, 1–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Castro, L. (2011). Equilibria existence and approximation of regular discontinuous games. Economic Theory, 48, 67–85.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Debreu, G. (1952). A social equilibrium existence theorem. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the USA, 38(10), 886–893.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Duggan, J. (2007). Existence of equilibrium in single and double private value auctions. Econometrica, 73, 93–139.

    Google Scholar 

  • He, W., & Yannelis, N. C. (2016). Existence of Walrasian equilibria with discontinuous, non-ordered, interdependent and price-dependent preferences. Economic Theory, 61, 497–513.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • He, W., & Yannelis, N. C. (2017). Equilibria with discontinuous preferences: New fixed point theorems. Journal of Mathematical Analysis and Applications, 450, 1421–1433.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, M., & Swinkels, J. M. (2005). Equilibrium existence for zero-sum games and spatial models of elections. Games and Economic Behavior, 60, 52–74.

    Google Scholar 

  • Karlin, S. (1959). Mathematical methods and theory in games, programming and economics (Vol. II). Pregamon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McLennan, A., Monteiro, P. K., & Tourky, R. (2011). Games with discontinuous payoffs: A strengthening of Reny’s existence theorem. Econometrica, 79, 1643–1664.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Monteiro, P. K., & Page, F. H., Jr. (2007). Uniform payoff security and Nash equilibrium in compact games. Journal of Economic Theory, 134, 566–575.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Monteiro, P. K., & Page, F. H., Jr. (2008). Catalog competition and Nash equilibrium in nonlinear pricing games. Economic Theory, 34, 503–524.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, J., & Scalzo, V. (2007). Pseudocontinuous functions and existence of Nash equilibria. Journal of Mathematical Economics, 43, 174–183.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nash, J. F. (1950). Equilibrium points in $n$-person games. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 36, 48–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nash, J. F. (1951). Noncooperative games. Annals of Maths, 54, 286–295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nessah, R. (2011). Generalized weak transfer continuity and Nash equilibrium. Journal of Mathematical Economics, 47, 659–662.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nessah, R. (2019). A note on discontinuous games: Single lower-deviation property. Revue d’Economie Politique, 129, 419–429.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nessah, R., & Tian, G. (2016). On the existence of Nash equilibrium in discontinuous games. Economic Theory, 61, 515–540.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nishimura, K., & Friedman, J. (1981). Existence of Nash equilibrium in $n$-person games without quasiconcavity. International Economic Review, 22, 637–648.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prokopovych, P. (2011). On equilibrium existence in payoff secure games. Economic Theory, 48, 5–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prokopovych, P. (2013). The single deviation property in games with discontinuous payoffs. Economic Theory, 53, 383–402.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prokopovych, P. (2015). Majorized correspondences and equilibrium existence in discontinuous games. Economic Theory, 61, 541–552.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prokopovych, P., & Yannelis, N. C. (2014). On the existence of mixed strategy Nash equilibria. Journal of Mathematical Economics, 52, 87–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reny, P. (1999). On the existence of pure and mixed strategy Nash equilibria in discontinuous games. Econometrica, 67, 1029–1056.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reny, P. (2009). Further results on the existence of Nash equilibria in discontinuous games. University of Chicago, Working Paper.

  • Reny, P. (2011). Strategic approximations of discontinuous games. Economic Theory, 48, 17–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reny, P. (2016a). Nash equilibrium in discontinuous games. Economic Theory, 61, 553–569.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reny, P. (2016b). Introduction to the symposium on discontinuous games. Economic Theory, 61, 423–429.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rothstein, P. (2007). Discontinuous payoffs, shared resources, and games of fiscal competition: Existence of pure strategy Nash equilibrium. Journal of Public Economic Theory, 9, 335–368.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simon, L. (1987). Games with discontinuous payoffs. Review of Economic Studies, 54, 569–597.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simon, L., & Zame, W. (1990). Discontinuous games and endogenous sharing rules. Econometrica, 58, 861–872.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tian, G. (2015). On the existence of equilibria in games with arbitrary strategy spaces and preferences. Journal of Mathematical Economics, 60, 9–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vives, X. (1990). Nash equilibrium with strategic complementarities. Journal of Mathematical Economics, 19, 305–321.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Rabia Nessah.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Appendix

Appendix

Proof of Theorem 3.1

Define a new game \(\tilde{G}\) that includes all of the original players \(i\in I\) and a new player \(i=0\notin I\). Thus the new set of players is \(N=I\cup \{0\}\). Player 0’s strategy set is X and the strategy set of player \(i\in I\) is \(X_i\). If player 0 chooses \(z\in X\) and each player \(i\in I\) chooses \(x_i\in X_i\), then the payoff to player 0 is

$$\begin{aligned} v_0(z,x)=\left\{ \begin{array}{ll} 1, &{}\;\;\text {if }z=x\\ 0, &{}\;\;\text {otherwise} \end{array} \right. \end{aligned}$$

and the payoff to player \(i\in I\) is

$$\begin{aligned} v_i(z,x)={\overline{u}}_i(x_i,z). \end{aligned}$$

Suppose that the game G does not have an equilibrium in X. Let \({\overline{x}}\in X\) be a nonequilibrium of \(\tilde{G}\). Then by the weakly continuity secure of G, \(\tilde{G}\) is correspondence secure with respect to I. Consequently, \(\tilde{G}\) game satisfies the hypotheses of Theorem 5.6 in Reny (2016a) and, therefore, possesses a pure strategy Nash equilibrium \(({\overline{z}},{\overline{x}})\). Payoff of player 0 implies that \({\overline{z}}={\overline{x}}\). For each player \(j\in I\), his payoff implies that \({\overline{x}}_j\) maximizes \({\overline{u}}_j(y_j,{\overline{x}}_{-j})\). By weakly continuity secure of G, there exists a player i and a neighborhood \({{\mathcal {N}}}\) of \({\overline{x}}\), a well-behaved correspondence \(\phi :\mathcal{N}\twoheadrightarrow X\) such that

\({\overline{u}}_i(y_i,{\overline{x}})> {\overline{u}}_i({\overline{x}}_i,{\overline{x}})\), for each \(y_i\in \phi _{i}({\overline{x}})\), which contradicts that \({\overline{x}}_i\) maximizes \({\overline{u}}_i(.,{\overline{x}})\). \(\square \)

Proof of Proposition 3.1

Assume that G is weakly reciprocal upper semicontinuous at \({\overline{x}}\) (\({\overline{x}}\) is not an equilibrium) and it is not pseudo upper semicontinuous at \({\overline{x}}\). Then, by definition, for each neighborhood \({{\mathcal {N}}}\) of \({\overline{x}}\) and \(\epsilon >0\), there exists \(z\in {{\mathcal {N}}}\), so that \(\sup _{y_i\in X_i} u_i(y_i,{\overline{x}}_{-i})< {\underline{u}}_i(z)+\epsilon \), for each \(i\in I\). Thus, for a directed system of neighborhoods \(\{\mathcal{N}^{k}\}_{k}\) of \({\overline{x}}\) and a sequence \(\{\epsilon ^k\}_k\) that converges to 0, there exists a sequence \(\{z^{k}\}_k\) with \(z^{k}\in {{\mathcal {N}}}^k\) so as \(\{z^{k}\}_k\) converges to \({\overline{x}}\) and for each \(i\in I\), we have

$$\begin{aligned} \underset{y_i\in X_i}{\sup }u_i(y_i,{\overline{x}}_{-i})< {\underline{u}}_i(z^k)+\epsilon ^k\le u_i(z^k)+\epsilon ^k. \end{aligned}$$

Assume that \(\{u({z}^k)\}_k\) converges and let \({\overline{u}}= {\lim }_{k\rightarrow \infty }u(z^{k})\). Then \(({\overline{x}},{\overline{u}})\) is in the closure of the graph of G. If \(({\overline{x}},{\overline{u}})\) is not in the frontier of G, then \({\overline{u}}=u({\overline{x}})\) and consequently \(\sup _{y_i\in X_i} u_i(y_i,{\overline{x}}_{-i})\le u_i({\overline{x}})\), for each \(i\in I\), which is a contradiction, because \({\overline{x}}\) is not a Nash equilibrium. Then \(({\overline{x}},{\overline{u}})\) is on the frontier of G. By weakly reciprocal upper semicontinuity of G, there exists a player j who has a strategy \({\hat{y}}_j\in X_j\) such that \(u_j({\hat{y}}_j,{\overline{x}}_{-j})>{\overline{u}}_j\ge \sup _{y_j\in X_j} u_j(y_j,{\overline{x}}_{-j})\), which is impossible. \(\square \)

Proof of Proposition 3.2

Let \(x\in X\) be such that it is not an equilibrium. Then, by pseudo upper semicontinuity of G, there exist a neighborhood \({{\mathcal {N}}}\) of x and \(\epsilon >0\) such that for each \(z\in {{\mathcal {N}}}\) nonequilibrium, there exists a player \(i\in I\) so that \(\sup _{y_i\in X_i} u_i(y_i,x_{-i})> {\underline{u}}_i(z)+2\epsilon \). For \(\epsilon >0\), there exists \({\hat{y}}\) so as \(u_i({\hat{y}}_i,x_{-i})\ge \sup _{y_i\in X_i} u_i(y_i,x_{-i})-\epsilon \). By generalized payoff security in \(({\hat{y}}_i,x_{-i})\), for \(\epsilon >0\), and \(i\in I\), there exist a neighborhood \({{\mathcal {N}}}^i\) of \(x_{-i}\), and a well-behaved correspondence \(\phi _{x,i}:{{\mathcal {N}}}\twoheadrightarrow X_i\) so that \(u_i(y_i,t_{-i})\ge u_i({\hat{y}}_i,{\overline{x}}_{-i})-\epsilon \), for each \((t_{-i},y_i)\in \text {Graph}(\phi _{x,i})\). We also have \({\underline{u}}_i(y_i,t_{-i})\ge \inf _{(t'_{-i},y'_i)\in \text {Graph}(\phi _{x,i})}\;u_i(y'_i,t'_{-i})\), for each \((t_{-i},y_i)\in \text {Graph}(\phi _{x,i})\).

Let \(\overline{{{\mathcal {N}}}}=\bigcap _{i\in I}\left( X_i\times {{\mathcal {N}}}^i\right) \bigcap {{\mathcal {N}}}\) be a neighborhood of x. Then for each \(z\in \overline{{{\mathcal {N}}}}\) nonequilibrium, there exists a player \(i\in I\) so that for each \((t_{-i},y_i)\in \text {Graph}(\phi _{x,i})\):

$$\begin{aligned} {\underline{u}}_i(y_i,t_{-i})+2\epsilon \ge u_i({\hat{y}}_i,x_{-i})+\epsilon \ge \sup _{y_i\in X_i} u_i(y_i,x_{-i})> {\underline{u}}_i(z) +2\epsilon . \end{aligned}$$

Since the game is quasiconcave, then it is g-weakly continuous secure. \(\square \)

Proof of Proposition 3.3

See the proof of Theorem 3.1. \(\square \)

Proof of Proposition 4.1

Suppose that G is continuous secure at x, where x is not an equilibrium. Then there is a neighborhood \({{\mathcal {N}}}\) of x, \(\alpha \in {\mathbb {R}}^n\) and a well-behavedFootnote 14 correspondence \(\phi _{x}:\mathcal{N}\twoheadrightarrow X\), so that

  1. (1)

    for each \(t\in {{\mathcal {N}}}\), and \(i\in I\), we have \(\phi _{x,i}(t)\subseteq B_i(t,\alpha _i)\), and

  2. (2)

    for each \(z\in {{\mathcal {N}}}\), there exists a player j for whom, \(z_j\notin co B_j(z,\alpha _j)\).

where \(B_i(x,\alpha _i)=\{y_i\in X_i\text { such that }u_i(y_i,x_{-i})\ge \alpha _i\}\).

Condition (1) implies that for each \(i\in I\), \(t\in {{\mathcal {N}}}\) and \(y_i\in \phi _{x,i}(t)\), \(u_i(y_i,t_{-i})\ge \alpha _i\). Therefore, \({\inf }_{(t,y_i)\in \text {Graph}(\phi _{x,i})}\;u_i(t_i,z_{-i})\ge \alpha _i\). We have for each \((t,y_i)\in \text {Graph}(\phi _{x,i})\),

$$\begin{aligned} {\underline{u}}_i(y_i,t_{-i})\ge \underset{(t',y'_i)\in \text {Graph}(\phi _{x,i})}{\inf }\;u_i(t'_i,z'_{-i})\ge \alpha _i. \end{aligned}$$

Assume that for some \(\tilde{z}\in {{\mathcal {N}}}\) nonequilibrium and for each player \(i\in I\), there exists \((\tilde{x},\tilde{y}_i)\in \text {Graph}(\phi _{x,i})\) so that

$$\begin{aligned} \tilde{z}_i\in co \{t_i\in X_i\text { such that }{\underline{u}}_i(t_i,\tilde{z}_{-i})\ge {\underline{u}}_i(\tilde{y}_i,\tilde{x}_{-i})\}. \end{aligned}$$

There is a finite set \(A_i=\{t_i^1,...,t_i^{p_i}\}\subseteq \{t_i\in X_i,\;{\underline{u}}_i(t_i,\tilde{z}_{-i})\ge {\underline{u}}_i(\tilde{y}_i,\tilde{x}_{-i})\}\) so that \(\tilde{z}_i\in co A_i\). Therefore, for each \(i\in I\), and \(h=1,...,p_i\), we have

$$\begin{aligned} {\underline{u}}_i(t^h_i,\tilde{z}_{-i})\ge {\underline{u}}_i(\tilde{y}_i,\tilde{x}_{-i}) \ge \alpha _i. \end{aligned}$$

By condition (2), for \(\tilde{z}\in {{\mathcal {N}}}\), there exists a player \(j\in I\) so as \(\tilde{z}_j\notin co B_j(\tilde{z},\alpha _j)\). If \(A_j\subseteq B_j(\tilde{z},\alpha _j)\), then we obtain a contradiction \(\tilde{z}_j\in co A_j\subseteq coB_j(\tilde{z},\alpha _j)\). Thus \(A_j\nsubseteq B_j(\tilde{z},\alpha _j)\), and therefore, there is \(h_0=1,...,p_j\) such that \(t_j^{h_0}\notin B_j(\tilde{z},\alpha _j)\), i.e., \(\alpha _j>u_j(t_j^{h_0},\tilde{z}_{-j})\). Let \(\epsilon =\frac{1}{2}[\alpha _j-u_j(t_j^{h_0},\tilde{z}_{-j})]>0\). Then for \(\epsilon >0\), there exists a neighborhood \(\mathcal{N}_{\tilde{z}}\) so that

$$\begin{aligned} u_j(t_j^{h_0},\tilde{z}_{-j})\ge \alpha _j-\epsilon =\frac{1}{2}\alpha _j+\frac{1}{2}u_j(t_j^{h_0},\tilde{z}_{-j}). \end{aligned}$$

Thus \(u_j(t_j^{h_0},\tilde{z}_{-j})\ge \alpha _j>u_j(t_j^{h_0},\tilde{z}_{-j})\) which is a contradiction. \(\square \)

Proof of Proposition 4.3

For each \(x\in X\), we have \({\underline{u}}^u_j(x_j,x)\le 0\). Indeed, if \({\underline{u}}^u_j(x_j,x)>0\) for some \(i\in I\) and \(x\in X\), choose \(\epsilon >0\) such that \({\underline{u}}^u_i(x,x_i)>2\epsilon \). Then there exists a neighborhood \({{\mathcal {N}}}\) of x and a well-behaved correspondence \(\phi :{{\mathcal {N}}}\twoheadrightarrow X_i\) with \(x_i\in \phi _i(x)\) such that for each \((z,y_{i})\in \text {Graph}(\phi _i)\), we have \(u_i(y_i,z_{-i})>u_i(z_i,z_{-i})+\epsilon \). Then for \(z=x\) and \(y_i=x_i\), we obtain \(u_i(x)>u_i(x)+\epsilon \), i.e., \(\epsilon <0\) which is impossible.

Now, assume that G is generalized weakly transfer continuous. Then if \(x\in X\) is not an equilibrium, there exist a player i, a neighborhood \({{\mathcal {N}}}\) of x and a well-behaved correspondence \(\varphi _i:{{\mathcal {N}}}\twoheadrightarrow X_i\) such that \(\inf _{(x^{'},y^{'}_i)\in \text {Graph}(\varphi _i)}\;\left[ u_i(y^{'}_i, x'_{-i})-u_i(x')\right] >0\). Thus for each \(z\in {{\mathcal {N}}}\), there exists a player \(j=i\) for whom, \({\overline{u}}^u_j(y_j,t)\ge \inf _{(x^{'},y^{'}_j)\in \text {Graph}(\varphi _j)}\;\left[ u_j(y^{'}_j, x'_{-j})-u_j(x')\right] >0\ge {\overline{u}}^u_j(z_j,z)\), for each \((t,y_j)\in \text {Graph}(\phi _{x,j})\). \(\square \)

Proof of Proposition 4.4

For each \(x\in X\), we have \({\underline{u}}^{{\underline{u}}}_j(x_j,x)\le 0\). Now, assume that G is quasi-weakly transfer continuous. Then if \(x\in X\) is not an equilibrium, there exist a player i, a neighborhood \({{\mathcal {N}}}\) of x, \(\epsilon >0\) and a strategy \(y_i\in X_i\) such that \(u_i(y_i, t_{-i})>{\underline{u}}_i(t)+\epsilon \), for each \(t\in {{\mathcal {N}}}\). Let us consider the following well-behaved correspondence \(\phi _x:\mathcal{N}\twoheadrightarrow X\) defined by \(\phi _x(z)=\{(y_1,y_2)\}\). Since for each \((t,y^{'}_j)\in \text {Graph}(\phi _{x,j})\), we have \({\underline{u}}^{{\underline{u}}}_j(y^{'}_j,t)\ge \inf _{(t',y^{''}_j)\in \text {Graph}(\phi _{x,j})} [u_j(y^{''}_j,t'_{-j})-{\overline{u}}_j(t')]\). Thus for each \(z\in {{\mathcal {N}}}\) nonequilibrium, there exists a player \(j=i\) for whom, \({\underline{u}}^{{\underline{u}}}_j(y^{'}_j,t)>0\ge {\overline{u}}^{{\overline{u}}}_j(z_j,z)\), for each \((t,y^{'}_j)\in \text {Graph}(\phi _{x,j})\). \(\square \)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Nessah, R. Weakly continuous security and nash equilibrium. Theory Decis 93, 725–745 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-022-09869-w

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-022-09869-w

Keywords

Navigation