Skip to main content
Log in

Complementarity in information studies

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The principle of complementarity in physics can be generalized and extended to information studies. It helps explain the dilemma faced by information studies today. The prevailing endeavor that going beyond the limitation of formal theories and to develop a unified theory of information falls in the dilemma which is structurally homologous to the dilemmas in quantum physics. The dilemma is caused by an epistemological paradox called assignment paradox. The paradox can be removed through generalized complementarity. It means that the concept of information embodying in different theoretical contexts are different phenomenon. They are complementary to each other. The analysis brings bad news to methodologically reductionism and fundamentalism but good news to transdisciplinary approach.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. A systematic study on the generalization and application of Bohr’s Principle of Complementarity can see von Stillfried’s dissertation Theoretical and Emprical Exploration of “Generalized Quntum Theory” (2010).

  2. Philosophers of language have made a distinction between reference and meaning since Frege (1892). However, I will ignore the distinction here because information is much more basic than language. Whether can we apply the analysis of language to information is still open.

  3. When saying about academic usages of information, I do not hold the notion that there is an academic definition of information with which researchers from different disciplines all agree with. In fact, comes to mathematical theories of information, we can even say there are more divergences than consensus. More can see in Burgin (2010).

  4. Some may argue that Shannon did not intend to develop a theory involving Ref and Nor as he said at the very beginning of his classic paper (1948), thus he did not intentionally assign Ref and Nor to information in his theory. The argument is fair. However, as Bar-Hillel has argued, many has ignored Shannon’s warning and equaled the information discussed in the theory to information in daily usage. The “people” in my claim refers to these.

References

  • Barbour, I. G. (1966). Issues in science and religion. Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bar-Hillel, Y. (1955). An examination of information theory. Philosophy of Science,22(2), 86–105.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bar-Hillel, Y. & Carnap, R. (1953). An outline of a theory of semantic information. Reprinted in Bar-Hillel, Y. (1964). Language and information: Selected essays on their theory and application (pp. 221–274). Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley.

  • Barwise, J., & Perry, J. (1983). Situations and attitudes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bateson, G. (1972). Steps to an ecology of mind: Collected essays in anthropology, psychiatry, evolution, and epistemology. Chicago, Illinois: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bateson, G. (1979). Mind and nature: A necessary unity. Hampton: Hampton Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bedau, H., & Oppenheim, P. (1961). Complementarity in quantum physics. Synthese,13(3), 201–232.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bohr, N. (1937). Causality and complementarity. Philosophy of Science IV,3, 289–298.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brier, S. (2008). Cybersemiotics: Why information is not enough. Toronto, Ontario: University of Toronto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brier, S. (2015). Finding an information concept suited for a universal theory of information? Progress in Biophysics & Molecular Biology,119(3), 622–633.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brody, N., & Oppenheim, P. (1969). Applications of Bohr’s principle of complementarity to the mind–body problem. The Journal of Philosophy,66, 97–113.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burgin, M. (2010). Theory of information: Fundamentality, diversity and unification. Singapore: World Scientific.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R., & Bar-Hillel, Y. (1952). Semantic information. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science,4(14), 147–157.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cashman, T. (2008). What connects the map to the territory. In M. Barbieri & J. Hoffmyer (Eds.), A legacy for living systems: Gregory Bateson as precursor to biosemiotics (pp. 45–58). New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chaitin, G. J. (1987). Algorithmic information theory. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (1995). Facing up to the problem of consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies,2(3), 200–219.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (1996). The conscious mind: In search of a fundamental theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collier, J. (1996). Information originates in symmetry breaking. Symmetry: Culture & Science,7, 247–256.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collier, J. (2003). Hierarchical dynamical information system with a focus on biology. Entropy,5, 102.

    Google Scholar 

  • Collier, J. (2015). What must the world be like to have information about it? In Proceedings of summit of international society for information science. Austria: Bertalanffy Center for System Science Studies, Technology University of Vienna.

  • Deacon, T. (2007). Shannon–Boltzmann–Darwin: Redefining information. Part 1. Cognitive Semiotics,1, 123–148.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deacon, T. (2008). Shannon–Boltzmann–Darwin: Redefining information. Part 2. Cognitive Semiotics,2, 167–194.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deacon, T. (2010). What is missing from information. In P. Davies & N. Gregersen (Eds.), Information and the nature of reality: From physics to metaphysics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deacon, T. (2012). Incomplete nature: How mind emerged from matter. New York: W. W. Nordon & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deacon, T. (2015). Steps to a theory of reference & significance in information. FIS discussion paper, September.

  • Dodig Crnkovic, G. (2011). Dynamics of information as natural computation. Information,2(3), 460–477.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1981). Knowledge and the flow of information. Oxford: Blackwell; reprinted, Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications, 1999.

  • Fisher, R. A. (1925). Theory of statistical estimation. Proceedings Cambridge Philosophical Society, 22(5), 700–725.

    Google Scholar 

  • Floridi, L. (2004). Outline of a theory of strongly semantic information. Minds and Machines,14(2), 197–222.

    Google Scholar 

  • Floridi, L. (2005/2015) Semantic conceptions of information. In E. N. Zalta (Eds.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2014 Edn). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/information-semantic/.

  • Floridi, L. (2010). Information: A very short introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Floridi, L. (2011). The philosophy of information. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1892/1993). On sense and reference. In P. Geach & M. Black (Eds.), Translations from the philosophical writings of Gottlob Frege (pp. 56–78). Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1960.

  • Gregersen, N. (2010). God, matter, and information: Towards a stoicizing logos christology. In P. Davies & N. Gregersen (Eds.), Information and the nature of reality: From physics to metaphysics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hofkirchner, W. (Ed.). (1999). The quest for a unified theory of information. Amsterdam: Gordon and Breach.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hofkirchner, W. (2013). Emergent information: A unified information framework. Singapore: World Scientific.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1936). The crisis of European science and transcendental phenomenology (D. E. Carr, Trans and introduction). Evanston: Northwesterm University Press. (1970).

  • Kolmogorov, A. N. (1965). Three approaches to the quantitative definition of information. Problems of Information Transmission,1(1), 1–7.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lindenberg, S., & Oppenheim, P. (1974). Generalization of complementarity. Synthese,28, 117–139.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mackay, D. M. (1969). Information, mechanism and meaning. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Penrose, O. (1970). Foundations of statistical mechanics: A deductive treatment. Oxford: Pergamon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmidhuber, J. (1997). A computer scientist’s view of life, the universe, and everything. In C. Freksa (Ed.), Foundations of computer science: Potential-theory-cognition (pp. 201–208)., Lecture notes in computer science Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shannon, C. (1948). A mathematical theory of communication. Bell System Technical Journal, 27(3), 379–423.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solomonoff, R. J. (1964a). A formal theory of inductive inference, part I. Information and Control,7(1), 1–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solomonoff, R. J. (1964b). A formal theory of inductive inference, part II. Information and Control,7(2), 224–254.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stonier, T. (1997). Information and meaning: An evolutionary perspective. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Neumann, J. (1955). Mathematische Grundlagen der Quantenmechanik. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Stillfried, N. (2010). Theoretical and Empirical Explorations of “Generalized Quantum Theory”. Eingereicht an der Kulturwissenschaftlichen Fakultät der, Europa-Universität Viadrina. Frankfurt an der Oder.

  • Weaver, W. (1949). Recent contributions to the mathematical theory of communication. In C. Shannon & W. Weaver (Eds.), The mathematical theory of communication. Urbana: The University of Illinois Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, J. A. (1989). Information, physics, quantum: The search for links. In W. Zurek (Ed.), Complexity, entropy, and the physics of information. Redwood City, CA: Addison-Wesley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolframe, S. (2002). A new kind of science. Champaign: Wolframe Media, Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wu, K. (2005). Information philosophy: Theory, system and methods [信息哲学:理论、系统与方法]. Beijing: The Commercial Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zhong, Y. X. (2017). the law of information conversion and intelligence creation. In M. Burgin & W. Hofkirchner (Eds.), Information studies and the quest for transdisciplinarity: Unity through diversity. Singapore: World Scientific.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zhou, L. Q., & Brier, S. (2015). The metaphysics of Chinese information philosophy: A critical analysis of WuKun’s philosophy of information. Cybernetics & Human Knowing,22(1), 35–56.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zuse, K. (1967). Rechnender Raum. Elektronische Datenverarbeitung,8, 336–344.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I thank anonymous referees for their insightful critiques and suggestions which improve the paper substantially. The paper is supported by China Postdoctoral Science Foundation Grant 2017M611789.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Liqian Zhou.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Zhou, L. Complementarity in information studies. Synthese 197, 293–310 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-1786-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-1786-8

Keywords

Navigation