Skip to main content
Log in

Lotteries and justification

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The lottery paradox shows that the following three individually highly plausible theses are jointly incompatible: (i) highly probable propositions are justifiably believable, (ii) justified believability is closed under conjunction introduction, (iii) known contradictions are not justifiably believable. This paper argues that a satisfactory solution to the lottery paradox must reject (i) as versions of the paradox can be generated without appeal to either (ii) or (iii) and proposes a new solution to the paradox in terms of a novel account of justified believability.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In fairness to deniers of NC, it should be noted that this argument might turn out dialectically ineffective against those who reject NC. After all, if you are willing to reject NC, you will likely not be too attached to NMP either. At the same time, for the many who do not want to give up NC, it does provide an additional reason for not so doing: they would have to give up a further plausible principle governing justified believability. Thus, even if these considerations do not move foes of NC, I take them to provide some reason to think that NC is not the culprit of the paradox. Of course, if NC is not the culprit, it’ll have to be either CC or ST.

  2. Notice that, besides receiving support by the plausible MCH and NC, MCN is independently plausible. After all, it captures the epistemic force of reductio arguments (Kaplan 1981).

  3. Douven and Williamson also argue that their result applies to the most prominent solutions to the lottery paradox that venture to replace ST by ST’, including the ones in Pollock (1995), Ryan (1996) and Douven’s own earlier proposal in Douven (2002).

  4. See Kelp ang Ghijsen (forthcoming) and Kelp (forthcoming b) for some such comparisons.

  5. See (Kelp 2014a, b, c) for arguments that knowledge is the goal of inquiry.

  6. I do not mean to suggest that there is nothing of philosophical substance to be said about the nature of knowledge. In fact, I am inclined to think that the nature of knowledge is given by the thesis that knowledge is the goal of inquiry.

  7. There may be cases in which one has other ways of forming beliefs about lottery propositions available to one. For instance, one may have been told by a reliable informant that a certain ticket will lose the lottery because the lottery is rigged against it. Since, at least in certain conditions, believing lottery propositions on the basis of the informant’s say-so disposes one to acquire knowledgeable beliefs about lottery propositions, in this situation one is in a position to believe the lottery proposition via an exercise of an ability to know. By JBY, the lottery proposition is justifiably believable for one. I take this to be the right result.

References

  • Bird, A. (2007). Justified judging. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 74, 81–110.

  • Douven, I. (2002). A new solution to the paradoxes of rational acceptability. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 53, 391–410.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Douven, I., & Williamson, T. (2006). Generalising the lottery paradox. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 57, 755–779.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Foley, R. (1979). Justified inconsistent beliefs. American Philosophical Quarterly, 16, 247–257.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greco, J. (2010). Achieving knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jenkins Ichikawa, J. (2014). Justification is potential knowledge. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 44, 184–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, M. (1981). A Bayesian theory of rational acceptance. The Journal of Philosophy, 78, 305–330.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kelp, C. (2014a). Two for the knowledge goal of inquiry. American Philosophical Quarterly, 51, 227–232.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelp, C. (2014b). No justification for lottery losers. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 95, 205–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kelp, C. (2014c). Knowledge, understanding, and virtue. In A. Fairweather (Ed.), Virtue scientia. Virtue epistemology and philosophy of science. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelp, C. (forthcoming a). Knowledge first virtue epistemology. In A. Carter, E. Gordon, & B. Jarvis (Eds.), Knowledge first: Approaches in epistemology and mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Kelp, C. (forthcoming b). Justified belief: Knowledge first-style. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research.

  • Kelp, C., & Ghijsen, H. (forthcoming). Perceptual justification: Factive reasons and fallible virtues. In C. Mi, M. Slote, & E. Sosa (Eds.), Moral and intellectual virtues in Western and Chinese philosophy. London: Routlege.

  • Kyburg, H. (1961). Probability and the logic of rational belief. Middletown, CT: Wesleyan University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kyburg, H. (1970). Conjunctivitis. In M. Swain (Ed.), Induction, acceptance and rational belief. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kyburg, H. (1997). Probabilistic acceptance. In Proceedings of the Thirteenth Conference on Uncertainty in Artificial Intelligence, UAI’97, pp. 326–333.

  • Littlejohn, C. (2013). The Russellian retreat. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 113, 293–320.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millar, A. (2010). Perceptual knowledge and recognitional abilities. In D. Pritchard, A. Millar, & A. Haddock (Eds.), The nature and value of knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. (2000). On clear and confused ideas. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Miracchi, L. (2015). Competence to know. Philosophical Studies, 172, 29–56.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pollock, J. (1995). Cognitive carpentry. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey, F. (1990/1929). F.P. Ramsey: Philosophical papers. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Reynolds, S. (2013). Justification as the appearance of knowledge. Philosophical Studies, 163, 367–383.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ryan, S. (1996). The epistemic virtues of consistency. Synthese, 109, 121–141.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, M. (2014). Knowledge, justification and normative coincidence. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 89, 273–295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smithies, D. (2012). The normative role of knowledge. Noûs, 46, 265–288.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sosa, E. (2010). How competence matters in epistemology. Philosophical Perspectives, 24, 465–475.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sutton, J. (2007). Without justification. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (forthcoming). Justifications, excuses, and sceptical scenarios. In J. Dutant & F. Dorsch (Eds.), The new evil demon. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Download references

Acknowledgments

Thanks to the audiences of the following conferences for helpful feedback on the material of this paper: 2012 EEN Meeting, Universities of Bologna and Modena (2012); CCPEA, Academia Sinica, Taipei (2012); 2013 Bled Philosophical Conferences, Bled (2013); Epistemic Justification and Reasons, University of Luxembourg (2013); Neue Perspektiven der Epistemischen Rechtfertigung, University of Dresden (2013), Saving Safety, Bonn (2013), Yonsei Philosophy Summer Conference, Yonsei University (2014); Normative Epistemic Reasons, University of Luxembourg (2014), The Virtue Turn, University of Taipei (2014); 2015 Bled Philosophical Conferences, Bled (2015). Thanks also to the Leuven Epistemology Group and two anonymous referees of this journal for their feedback on the paper. Special thanks to Harmen Ghijsen and Mona Simionescu for commenting on various versions of the paper. This work was funded by grants from KU Leuven’s Special Research Fund (BOF) and Research Foundation Flanders (FWO).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Christoph Kelp.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Kelp, C. Lotteries and justification. Synthese 194, 1233–1244 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0989-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0989-5

Keywords

Navigation