Skip to main content
Log in

Modulation : an alternative to instructions and forces

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

It is widely believed that neural elements interact by communicating messages. Neurons, or groups of neurons, are supposed to send packages of data with informational content to other neurons or to the body. Thus, behavior is traditionally taken to consist in the execution of commands or instructions sent by the nervous system. As a consequence, neural elements and their organization are conceived as literally embodying and transmitting representations that other elements must in some way read and conform to. In opposition to this conception, growing approaches such as enactivism and ecological psychology hold that neurons are not in the business of representing. However, by insisting that neural causation is not of a representational kind, these anti-representationalist approaches seem to be left with only one rather implausible alternative, viz. that behavior is the result of nothing but basic physical causation such as push-pull forces. In this paper it is argued that a third form of causation—termed “modulation”—exists and is at work in the coordination of animal behavior. Modulation is the quasi-direct guidance of dynamical systems through specific yet emerging trajectories. By setting the constraints that coordinate the free interaction of multi-element systems, modulation influences without forcing nor representing goal states. The basic properties of modulatory causation are analyzed and shown to be present in some fundamental aspects of neural and bodily interaction.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See, e.g., (Clark 2008; Pfeifer and Bongard 2006) for an extensive use of this notion.

  2. Fred Keijzer (2001, p. 117), used the notion of “modulation” to characterize Raibert and Hodgins’ notion of “suggestion”. This paper can be considered as an endeavor to render Keijzer’s insight more systematic.

  3. I thank an anonymous reviewer of an earlier draft for warning against the risk of this circularity.

  4. I thank an anonymous reviewer for drawing my attention to Craver’s treatment of filler terms.

  5. More on the conditions for being a representation below.

  6. There is also the modular version of patchy representationalism where connectionist modules or “resources” are believed to co-exist with computational ones in the same network and the agent must choose which resource to use according to the task (Minsky 2006).

  7. I am assuming a processor manufacturing process that hasn’t yet reached the size of a single atom.

  8. An anonymous reviewer has expressed his or her concern for my choice of “structural isomorphism” as it seems to restrict too much the class of representational formats that my paper addresses. He or she suggests, instead, that I consider “functional” isomorphism instead of “structural”. I want to make clear that I completely agree with this. I do not mean by “structural” a “physical” isomorphism as that between a sculpture and its model. By using the term “structural” I am only referring to the fact that there must be a structure somewhere doing the representing, even if it is not the shape of this structure per se that bears the isomorphism and some additional process is needed, such as decoding, or translation from sentences into a matrix, etc. Clearly, whatever the format, the isomorphism must be functional ; but also, whatever the format, there must be a structure subserving it. That’s all I mean by “structural isomorphism”.

  9. To be sure, it does transmit its temperature, but this property is irrelevant in the sense that it doesn’t belong to the chosen explanandum, which is composed of the mentioned geometrical patterns.

  10. Other names have been attributed to the same kind of system, in particular, “synergy” is synonymous with “coordinative structure” and “dissipative structure” (Kugler et al. 1980).

  11. This is actually an oversimplification. Not even this relatively simple value is completely specified by the nervous system. As Turvey stresses, \(\lambda \), which constitutes a control parameter, is itself an abstract global value emerging from other parameters and factors at a lower level (Turvey 2007, p. 663)!

  12. I use the notion of “autonomy” here in its largest and weakest sense. A stronger notion, often employed by enactivists and ecological psychologists, would imply that synergies alone are autonomous. While it makes sense to distinguish enactive autonomy from representational autonomy, my focus here is on the difference between these two systems and mechanically driven systems that don’t fall under any concept of autonomous system.

References

  • Abrahamsen, A., & Bechtel, W. (2012). From reactive to endogenously active dynamical conceptions of the brain. In T. Reydon & K. Plaisance (Eds.), Philosophy of behavioral biology (pp. 329–366). New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Balasubramaniam, R., & Feldman, A. G. (2004). Guiding movements without redundancy problems. In V. Jirsa & S. J. A. Kelso (Eds.), Coordination dynamics: Issues and trends (pp. 155–176). New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Barandiaran, X. (2008). Mental life: A naturalized approach to the autonomy of cognitive agents. Doctoral dissertation. PhD thesis. University of the Basque Country, Spain.

  • Bechtel, W. (1998). Representations and cognitive explanations: Assessing the dynamicist’s challenge in cognitive science. Cognitive Science, 22(3), 295–317.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. (2001). The compatibility of complex systems and reduction: A case analysis of memory research. Minds and Machines, 11(4), 483–502.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. (2013). Addressing the vitalist’s challenge to mechanistic science: Dynamic mechanistic explanation. In S. Normandin & C. T. Wolfe (Eds.), Vitalism and the scientific image in post-enlightenment life science, 1800–2010 (pp. 345–370). New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., & Abrahamsen, A. (2010). Dynamic mechanistic explanation: Computational modeling of circadian rhythms as an exemplar for cognitive science. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 41(3), 321–333.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., & Abrahamsen, A. (2011). Complex biological mechanisms: Cyclic, oscillatory, and autonomous. In H. Cliff (Ed.), Philosophy of complex systems. Handbook of the philosophy of science (Vol. 10, pp. 257–285). New York: Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Buzsaki, G. (2006). Rhythms of the brain. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cham, J. G., Bailey, S. A., & Cutkosky, M. R. (2000). Robust dynamic locomotion through feedforward-preflex interaction. ASME IMECE proceedings (pp. 5–10). Florida: Orlando.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chemero, A. (2009). Radical embodied cognitive science. Cambridge: MIT Cambridge press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chiel, H. J., & Beer, R. D. (1997). The brain has a body: Adaptive behavior emerges from interactions of nervous system, body and environment. Trends in Neuroscience, 20, 553–557.

  • Clark, A. (1997a). Being there: Putting brain, body, and world together again. Cambridge, MA: MIT Cambridge Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (1997b). The dynamical challenge. Cognitive Science, 21(4), 461–481.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2008). Supersizing the mind: Embodiment, action, and cognitive extension. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 3, 7–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A., & Toribio, J. (1994). Doing without representing? Synthese, 101(3), 401–431.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F. (2007). Explaining the brain. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Crick, F., & Koch, C. (1998). Constraints on cortical and thalamic projections: The no-strong-loops hypothesis. Nature, 391(6664), 245–250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, R. (1989). Meaning and mental representation (p. 138). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, R. (1996). Representations, targets, and attitudes. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, A. G. (2009). New insights into action-perception coupling. Experimental Brain Research, 194(1), 39–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, A. G., & Levin, M. F. (2009). The equilibrium-point hypothesis past, present and future. In D. Sternad (Ed.), Progress in motor control (pp. 699–726). New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Flament-Fultot, M. (2014). On genic representations. Biological Theory, 9, 149–162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1998). In critical condition: Polemical essays on cognitive science and the philosophy of mind. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (2008). LOT 2: The language of thought revisited. OUP

  • Fowler, C. A., & Turvey, M. T. (1978). Skill acquisition: An event approach with special reference to searching for the optimum of a function of several variables. In G. Stelmach (Ed.) Information processing in motor control and learning (pp. 2–40). New York: Academic Press.

  • Gibson, J. J. (1979). The ecological approach to visual perception. Hillsdale: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2000). On the theoretical role of ‘genetic coding’. Philosophy of Science, 5, 26–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haselager, P., van Dijk, J., & van Rooij, I. (2008). A lazy brain? Embodied embedded cognition and cognitive neuroscience. Handbook of Cognitive Science: An Embodied Approach, 5, 273–287.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haugeland, J. (1985). Artificial intelligence: The very idea. Cambridge: MIT press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D., & Myin, E. (2013). Radicalizing enactivism: Basic minds without content. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keijzer, F. A. (2001). Representation and behavior. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keijzer, F. A. (2003). Self-steered self-organization. In W. Tschacher & J. P. Dauwalder (Eds.), The dynamical systems approach to cognition (pp. 243–259). New York: World Scientific.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Keijzer, F. A., van Duijn, M., & Lyon, P. (2013). What nervous systems do: early evolution, input-output, and the skin brain thesis. Adaptive Behavior, 21, 67–85.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kelso, J. A. S. (1995). Dynamic patterns: The self organization of brain and behaviour. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelso, J. A. S. (2009). Synergies: Atoms of brain and behavior. In D. Sternad (Ed.), Progress in motor control (pp. 83–91). New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kelso, J. A. S., & Kay, B. A. (1987). Information and control: A macroscopic analysis of perception-action coupling. In H. Heuer & A. F. Sanders (Eds.), Perspectives on perception and action (pp. 3–32). Hillsdale NJ: L. Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirkaldy, J. S. (1965). Thermodynamics of the human brain. Biophysical Journal, 5(6), 981–986.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirsh, D., & Maglio, P. (1994). On distinguishing epistemic from pragmatic action. Cognitive Science, 18(4), 513–549.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kugler, P. N., Scott Kelso, J. A., & Turvey, M. T. (1980). On the concept of coordinative structures as dissipative structures: I. Theoretical lines of convergence. Advances in Psychology, 1, 3–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kugler, P. N., & Turvey, M. T. (1988). Self-organization, flow fields, and information. Human Movement Science, 7(2), 97–129.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Latash, M. L. (2008). Synergy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Latash, M. L. (2010). Motor synergies and the equilibrium-point hypothesis. Motor Control, 14(3), 294–322.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Latash, M. L., Shim, J. K., Smilga, A. V., & Zatsiorsky, V. M. (2005). A central back-coupling hypothesis on the organization of motor synergies: A physical metaphor and a neural model. Biological Cybernetics, 92(3), 186–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lucia, U. (2013). Entropy generation, brain dynamics, and thomas aquinas. Journal of Human Thermodynamics, 9(4), 55–64.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machamer, P., Darden, L., & Craver, C. F. (2000). Thinking about mechanism. Philosophy of Science, 67(1), 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. G. (1995). Pushmi-pullyu representations. Philosophical Perspectives, 9, 185–200.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Minsky, M. (2006). The emotion machine: Commonsense thinking, artificial intelligence, and the future of the human mind. New York: Simon and Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ostry, D. J., & Feldman, A. G. (2003). A critical evaluation of the force control hypothesis in motor control. Experimental Brain Research, 153(3), 275–288.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pfeifer, R., & Bongard, J. (2006). How the body shapes the way we think: A new view of intelligence. Cambridge: MIT press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raibert, M. H., & Hodgins, J. K. (1993). Legged Robots. In R. Beer, R. Ritzman, & T. McKenna (Eds.), Biological neural networks in invertebrate neuroethology and robotics (pp. 319–354). Boston, MA: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, L. (2010). Embodied cognition. Hillsdale: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stegmann, U. E. (2005). Genetic information as instructional content. Philosophy of Science, 72(3), 425–443.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Swenson, R., & Turvey, M. T. (1991). Thermodynamic reasons for perception-action cycles. Ecological Psychology, 3(4), 317–348.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turvey, M. T. (2004). Impredicativity, dynamics, and the perception-action divide. In V. Jirsa & S. J. A. Kelso (Eds.), Coordination dynamics: Issues and trends (pp. 1–20). New York: Springer.

  • Turvey, M. T. (2007). Action and perception at the level of synergies. Human Movement Science, 24(4), 657–697.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turvey, M. T., & Fonseca, S. T. (2009). Nature of motor control: Perspectives and issues. In D. Sternad (Ed.), Progress in motor control (pp. 93–123). New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Turvey, M. T., & Fonseca, S. T. (2014). The medium of haptic perception: A tensegrity hypothesis. Journal of Motor Behavior, 46(3), 143–187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turvey, M. T., & Kugler, P. N. (1984). An ecological approach to perception and action. Human Motor Actions: Bernstein Reassessed. H. T. A Whiting, (Ed.) Vol. 17. Advances in Psychology. Elsevier Science, pp. 373–413.

  • van Gelder, T. (1995). What might cognition be, if not computation. The Journal of Philosophy, 92(7), 345–381.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Gelder, T. (1996). Dynamics and cognition. In J. Haugeland (Ed.), Mind design II: Philosophy, psychology, artificial intelligence (pp. 421–454). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Gelder, T. (1998). The dynamical hypothesis in cognitive science. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 21(3), 615–628.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J. (1979). Principles of biological autonomy. New York: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. J., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (1991). The embodied mind: Cognitive science and human experience. Cambridge: MIT press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varpula, S. A. A., & Beck, C. (2012). Thoughts about thinking: Cognition according to the second law of thermodynamics. Advanced Studies in Biology, 5(3), 135–149.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallot, S., & van Orden, G. (2012). Ultrafast cognition. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 19(5–6), 141–160.

    Google Scholar 

  • Warren, W. H. (2006). Dynamics of perception and action. Psychological Review, 113, 358–389.

  • Webb, B. (1994). Robotic experiments in cricket phonotaxis. In: From Animals to Animats 3: Proceedings of the Third International Conference on Simulation of Adaptive Behavior. D. Cliff et al. (Ed.) pp. 45–54.

  • Wheeler, M. (2001). Two threats to representation. Synthese, 129(3), 211–231.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, M. (2005). Reconstructing the cognitive world: The next step. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, M., & Clark, A. (1999). Genic representation: Reconciling content and causal complexity. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 50(1), 103–135.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I thank Jan Degenaar, Fred Keijzer, Erik Myin, Michael Turvey and two anonymous reviewers for their useful comments on previous drafts of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Martin Flament Fultot.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Flament Fultot, M. Modulation : an alternative to instructions and forces. Synthese 194, 887–916 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0976-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-015-0976-x

Keywords

Navigation