Skip to main content
Log in

Metaphysical Nihilism and Modal Logic

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper I argue, that if it is metaphysically possible for it to have been the case that nothing existed, then it follows that the right modal logic cannot extend D, ruling out popular modal logics S4 and S5. I provisionally defend the claim that it is possible for nothing to have existed. I then consider the various ways of resisting the conclusion that the right modal logic is weaker than D.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Baldwin (1996), van Inwagen (1996), Bricker (2001), Rodriguez-Pereyra (2004), Coggins (2010). Bricker and Rodriguez-Pereyra are concerned to argue that modal realism is in fact compatible with the version of metaphysical nihilism restricted to concreta, though Rodriguez-Pereyra acknowledges that it is not compatible with the more radical nihilism considered here.

  2. Cf. Salmon (1989) on this and some related issues.

  3. In this example, tense is important; there is a still a possible world in which I had instead baked bread in the first place. But this is more of a backward-looking metaphysical possibility rather than the practical possibility in question.

  4. Accordingly, “possibly φ” might be false in a world w either because in w there are no states of affairs that include φ or because none of the states of affairs that include φ are possible. The argument below turns on this fact.

  5. Cf. Numeroff (1991).

  6. K itself is the result of adding to classical logic the axiom schema □(φ→ψ)→( □φ→□ψ) and the rule of necessitation: if φ has been proved from no assumptions, then infer □φ.

  7. Yli-Vakurri and Hawthorne (2020: 560). This quotation shows that I do not have an idiosyncratic take on the literature in claiming that S5 is widely accepted as the right modal logic.

  8. The subtraction argument was subsequently tweaked by Rodriguez-Pereyra (1997), criticized by Paseau (2002) and (2006), and defended by Efird and Stoneham (2005) and Rodriguez-Pereyra (2013). Cameron (2006) is a more neutral examination of the subtraction argument, criticizing the assumptions of both the argument itself as well as various counterarguments, leading to the conclusion that “we have seen no good reason to accept either nihilistic thesis, or to reject them” (218).

  9. Balaguer (2016) suggests a fourfold taxonomy including alongside Platonism and Aristotelianism (which he calls immanent realism), conceptualism—which holds that abstracta are mental objects—and nominalism. The conceptualist will be subject to a similar argument for nihilism as the Aristotelian. The nominalist can grant the possibility of nihilism but will avoid my main argument by objecting to the use of possible worlds in the first place.

  10. Or something along those lines. The devil lies in the details, of course.

  11. As Cowling (2017: 83) puts it, “since [Aristotelian] universals are located where and only where they are instantiated, such views typically hold that properties like mass exist in only some worlds, namely those worlds where mass is instantiated.”

  12. Cf. Rosen (2002: 292–5) on the question of whether Platonism without modal extremism is coherent.

  13. In the taxonomy of Cowling (2017: 202–3), the denial of modal extremism I have in mind would be called serious mutabilism.

  14. For instance, see Rosen (2002) for discussion of some arguments against modal extremism. Field (1993) argues for the related claim that the existence of abstract objects is not conceptually necessary.

  15. This and similar arguments are often produced to show that numbers must exist necessarily, e.g. Hale and Wright (1992). See Field (1993) for a forceful reply to Hale and Wright (1992) and Tennant (1997) for further critical discussion of the debate. Tennant in particular is sensitive to the role of a free logic.

  16. This objection was raised by Damon Stanley.

  17. I owe this point to an anonymous referee.

  18. In general of course there will not be a unique state of affairs in which φ holds. There are various ways of interpreting the expression “the maximal state of affairs such that φ”, but the points I will make about substitutional quantification will not turn on these issues, so I will ignore the further complications that they entail.

  19. For just a few examples, see Lewis (1968), Plantinga (1974), Dummett (1991), and Williamson (2013).

  20. Related issues concerning worlds being only contingently possible are discussed in Armstrong (1989) and Salmon (1989), but neither of these authors is concerned with the possibility of nihilism. Armstrong’s preferred modal logic is S4, and Salmon’s is T.

References

  • Adams, R. M. (1974). Theories of Actuality. Noûs, 8, 211–231

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, D. M. (1989). A Combinatorial Theory of Possibility. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Balaguer, M. (2016). Platonism in Metaphysics. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy

  • Baldwin, T. (1996). There Might Be Nothing. Analysis, 56(4), 231–238

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brenner, A. (2020). Explaining Why There is Something Rather than Nothing. Erkenntnis. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-020-00277-6

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bricker, P. (2001). Island universes and the analysis of modality. In G. Preyer, & F. Siebelt (Eds.), Reality and Humean Supervenience. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield

    Google Scholar 

  • Cameron, R. (2006). Much ado about nothing: a study of metaphysical nihilism. Erkenntnis, 64, 192–222

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coggins, G. (2010). Could There Have Been Nothing? Against Metaphysical Nihilism. New York: Palgrave-Macmillan

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cowling, S. (2017). Abstract Entities. New York: Routledge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. (1991). The Logical Basis of Metaphysics. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Efird, D., & Stoneham, T. (2005). The Subtraction Argument for Metaphysical Nihilism. Journal of Philosophy, 102(6), 303–325

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. (1993). The Conceptual Contingency of Mathematical Objects. Mind, 102, 285–299

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hale, R., & Wright, C. (1992). Nominalism and the Contingency of Abstract Objects. Journal of Phlosophy, 89, 111–135

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1981). Naming and Necessity. Malden, MA: Blackwell

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1968). Counterpart Theory and Quantified Modal Logic. Journal of Philosophy, 65(5), 113–126

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1986). On the Plurality of Worlds. Malden, MA: Blackwell

    Google Scholar 

  • Menzel, C. (1991). The True Modal Logic. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 20, 331–374

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nozick, R. (1981). Philosophical Explanations. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Numeroff, L. (1991). If You Give a Moose a Muffin. New York: HarperCollins

    Google Scholar 

  • Paseau, A. (2002). Why the subtraction argument does not add up. Analysis, 62, 72–75

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paseau, A. (2006). The subtraction argument(s). Dialectica, 60(2), 145–156

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A. (1974). The Nature of Necessity. Oxford: Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Rodriguez-Pereyra, G. (1997). There might be nothing: the subtraction argument improved. Analysis, 57, 159–166

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rodriguez-Pereyra, G. (2004). Modal Realism and Metaphysical Nihilism. Mind, 113(452), 683–704

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rodriguez-Pereyra, G. (2013). The Subtraction Arguments for Metaphysical Nihilism: compared and defended. In Tyron, & Goldschmidt (Eds.), The Puzzle of Existence: Why is There Something Rather than Nothing? (pp. 197–214). Routledge

  • Rosen, G. (2002). A Study in Modal Deviance. In J. Hawthorne, & Tamar Gendler (Eds.), Conceivability and Possibility (pp. 283–307). Oxford: Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, N. (1989). The Logic of What Might Have Been. Philosophical Review, 98(1), 3–34

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tennant, N. (1997). On the Necessary Existence of Numbers. Nous, 31(3), 3–7

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Inwagen, P. (1986). Two Concepts of Possible Worlds. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, XI, 185–213

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Inwagen, P. (1996). Why is there anything at all? Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary, 70, 95–120

  • Williamson, T. (2013). Modal Logic as Metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Yablo, S. (2014). Aboutness. Princeton: Princeton University Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Yli-Vakurri, J., & Hawthorne, J. (2020). The Necessity of Mathematics. Nous, 54(3), 549–577

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ethan Brauer.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Brauer, E. Metaphysical Nihilism and Modal Logic. Philos Stud 179, 2751–2763 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-022-01793-7

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-022-01793-7

Keywords

Navigation