Skip to main content
Log in

From the fixity of the past to the fixity of the independent

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

There is an old but powerful argument for the claim that exhaustive divine foreknowledge is incompatible with the freedom to do otherwise. A crucial ingredient in this argument is the principle of the “Fixity of the Past” (FP). A seemingly new response to this argument has emerged, the so-called “dependence response,” which involves, among other things, abandoning FP for an alternative principle, the principle of the “Fixity of the Independent” (FI). This paper presents three arguments for the claim that FI ought to be preferred to FP.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This argument has been around, in some form or another, for quite some time. See Pike (1965) for the classic presentation.

  2. See Merricks (2009, 2011), McCall (2011), Westphal (2011), and Swenson (2016). For dissent, see Fischer and Todd (2011), Todd and Fischer (2013), and Fischer and Tognazzini (2014). Arguably, the dependence response even has ancient roots. See Origen (c. 246/2002).

  3. This formulation is slightly amended from Fischer (2011). For further discussion of FP see Fischer (1994; ch. 4) and Holliday (2012).

  4. One might wonder about cases of overdetermination, where two unrelated facts are both full explanations for some third. This definition implies that the third fact is explanatorily dependent on both facts, which might seem strange. For the purposes of this paper, I’ll put the issue of overdetermination aside. Thank you to Ryan Wasserman for bringing this to my attention.

  5. See Swenson (2016, pp. 660–61) for discussion of similar examples. For expository purposes, I’ll sometimes have the “explanatory dependence” relation take events rather than facts as relata. Nothing of substance hangs on this.

  6. This formulation is inspired by, albeit distinct from, Swenson's formulation (2016), as Swenson restricts FI to explanatorily independent past facts.

  7. One might wonder what sense of “because” is at play here. Wasserman (forthcoming) argues that the dependence theorist ought to understand it in a causal sense; others, like Merricks (2009), seem to understand it in a logical or metaphysical sense. I’ll set this issue aside, as I’ll be arguing that if God’s relevant past beliefs are explained in any sense by the agent’s behavior, then God’s relevant past beliefs are no threat to freedom.

  8. Again, see Merricks (2009, 2011), McCall (2011), Westphal (2011), Swenson (2016), Cyr and Law (forthcoming), and Wasserman (forthcoming).

  9. Arguably, other authors who deny the first claim of the dependence response but are willing to accept the second include Todd (2013a) and (unsurprisingly) Todd and Fischer (2013).

  10. Merricks (2009) also focuses on this asymmetry, although Merricks’s argument is unsatisfactory in at least two ways. First, he does not explicitly formulate FI and consider its relation to FP. Second, he does not spend adequate time considering alternative explanations of this asymmetry (or related ones).

  11. Many have discussed this claim, but a particularly insightful and pertinent discussion is in Sartorio (2015).

  12. For a thorough defense of the growing-block theory, see Tooley (1997).

  13. First, since the growing-block theory of time is a version of the A-theory of time, it inherits all of the objections to the A-theory. See Mellor (1998) and Sider (2001). Second, there are objections unique to the growing-block theory. See Merricks (2006), Forrest (2006), and Briggs and Forbes (2012) for discussion.

  14. It might be claimed that FI is inconsistent with Presentism, the view that only the present time is real, as FI seems to require cross-temporal relations, and Presentism has difficulty accommodating such relations. (Finch and Rea (2008) raise this worry for Ockhamist views and Presentism, but it seems a parallel worry could also be pressed on FI.) This is a deep issue, but the basic argument seems mistaken to me. Either Presentism can accommodate cross-temporal relations (like causation) or it can’t. If it can, then FI can be reformulated so as to be compatible with Presentism; if it can’t, then Presentism is too implausible to take seriously. See Swenson (2016, pp. 666–668) for a different take.

  15. For clearly related but less lucid statements, see Pike (1965) and Hasker (1989).

  16. Thank you to Neal Tognazzini for helping me get clear on this.

  17. Again, see Wasserman (forthcoming) for a discussion of this issue.

  18. The classic proposal is the “entailment criterion.” See Adams (1967). More recently, Todd (2013b) has given an importantly different (and to my mind, far more plausible) proposal.

  19. See Fischer (1986) for discussion of this point.

  20. This restriction is arguably the most in line with the spirit of FP because past light cones are the closest one gets to an “absolute past” in standard interpretations of relativity.

  21. To be clear, the situation is this: Galileo and his friend are at rest relative to one another, and so will eventually judge the supernova to have occurred at the same time in the past. But since Galileo is a bit further away from the supernova, he has to wait a while longer to witness it and make that judgment.

  22. Here are two other ways of formulating FP in a standard relativistic setting: (i) restrict FP to all of the facts deemed past from the agent’s frame of reference and (ii) restrict FP to all of the facts outside of the agent’s future light cone. While I cannot fully elaborate here, both of these suffer problems. In short, (i) suffers a version of the second problem that FP-cone faces, namely, that it appears somewhat arbitrary, as an agent’s frame of reference is determined by her velocity; meanwhile, (ii) suffers a version of the first problem, namely, that it is equivalent to holding fixed all of those facts that are causally independent of the agent’s current behavior. Thanks to Neal Tognazzini for help here.

  23. It is true that the notion of a global time is not well-defined in certain models of relativity, but FI need only be formulated in terms of a local time.

  24. See Godfrey-Smith (1979), Forrest (2008), and Crisp (2007), respectively.

References

  • Adams, M. M. (1967). Is the existence of god a “hard fact”? Philosophical Review, 76(4), 492–503.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Briggs, R., & Forbes, G. A. (2012). The real truth about the unreal future. In K. Bennett & D. Zimmerman (Eds.), Oxford studies in metaphysics (Vol. 7, pp. 257–304). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Crisp, T. M. (2007). Presentism, eternalism, and relativity physics. In W. L. Craig & Q. Smith (Eds.), Einstein, relativity, and absolute simultaneity (pp. 262–278). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cyr, T. W., & Law, A. (forthcoming). Freedom, foreknowledge, and dependence: A dialectical intervention. American Philosophical Quarterly.

  • Finch, A., & Rea, M. (2008). Presentism and Ockham’s way out. In J. L. Kvanvig (Ed.), Oxford studies in philosophy of religion (Vol. 1, pp. 1–17). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, J. M. (1986). Hard-type soft facts. Philosophical Review, 95(4), 591–601.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, J. M. (1994). The metaphysics of free will: An essay on control. Malden: Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, J. M. (2011). Foreknowledge, freedom, and the fixity of the past. Philosophia, 39(3), 461–474.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, J. M. (2017). Replies to my critics. European Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 9(4), 63–85.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, J. M., & Todd, P. (2011). The truth about freedom: A reply to Merricks. Philosophical Review, 120(1), 97–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, J. M., & Tognazzini, N. A. (2014). Omniscience, freedom, and dependence. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 88(2), 346–367.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forrest, P. (2006). Uniform grounding of truth and the growing block theory: A reply to Heathwood. Analysis, 66(2), 161–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forrest, P. (2008). Relativity, the passage of time, and the cosmic clock. Philosophy and Foundations of Physics, 4, 245–253.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, W. (1979). Special relativity and the present. Philosophical Studies, 36(3), 233–244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hasker, W. (1989). God, time, and knowledge. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holliday, W. H. (2012). Freedom and the fixity of the past. Philosophical Review, 121(2), 179–207.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCall, S. (2011). The supervenience of truth: Free will and omniscience. Analysis, 71(3), 501–506.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mellor, D. H. (1998). Real time II. New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Merricks, T. (2006). Good-bye growing block. In D. Zimmerman (Ed.), Oxford studies in metaphysics (Vol. 2, pp. 103–110). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merricks, T. (2009). Truth and freedom. Philosophical Review, 118(1), 29–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merricks, T. (2011). Foreknowledge and freedom. Philosophical Review, 120(4), 567–586.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Origen. (c.246/2002). Commentary on the epistle to the romans: Books 610 (T. P. Scheck, Trans.). Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America Press.

  • Pike, N. (1965). Divine omniscience and voluntary action. Philosophical Review, 74(1), 27–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sartorio, C. (2015). The problem of determinism and free will is not the problem of determinism and free will. In A. Mele (Ed.), Surrounding free will: Philosophy, psychology, neuroscience (pp. 255–273). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sider, T. (2001). Four-dimensionalism: An ontology of persistence and time. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Swenson, P. (2016). Ability, foreknowledge, and explanatory dependence. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 94(4), 658–671.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Todd, P. (2013a). Prepunishment and explanatory dependence: A new argument for incompatibilism about foreknowledge and freedom. Philosophical Review, 122(4), 619–639.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Todd, P. (2013b). Soft facts and ontological dependence. Philosophical Studies, 164(3), 829–844.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Todd, P., & Fischer, J. M. (2013). The truth about foreknowledge. Faith and Philosophy, 30(3), 286–301.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tooley, M. (1997). Time, tense, and causation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wasserman, R. (forthcoming). Freedom, foreknowledge, and dependence. Noûs.

  • Westphal, J. (2011). The compatibility of divine foreknowledge and free will. Analysis, 71(2), 246–252.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thank you to John Martin Fischer, Jonah Nagashima, Michael Nelson, Carolina Sartorio, Phillip Swenson, and Ryan Wasserman for feedback on previous drafts. A special thank you to Taylor Cyr and Neal Tognazzini for extensive feedback on multiple drafts. Also, thank you to an anonymous referee at the Australasian Journal of Philosophy as well as the audiences at the 2018 USC-UCLA Graduate Student Conference and the 2018 Pacific Division of the American Philosophical Association.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Andrew Law.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Law, A. From the fixity of the past to the fixity of the independent. Philos Stud 178, 1301–1314 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-020-01476-1

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-020-01476-1

Keywords

Navigation