Reductionism about people is the view that people exist but they’re not a fundamental part of the world. The view is perhaps best explained through David Hume’s analogy with reductionism about nations.Footnote 1 Most of us are reductionists about nations: We believe that nations exist but also that their existing consists in more basic facts, such as the existence of citizens who organize themselves in certain ways on certain territories. So we could, in principle, provide a complete description of the world (and these more basic facts) without asserting that nations exist. In this manner, reductionism about people says that the world could, in principle, be completely described without asserting that people exist.Footnote 2

Given reductionism about people, personal persistence must fundamentally consist in an impersonal continuity relation holding over time. Some standard candidates for this impersonal continuity are different kinds of psychological, physical, and phenomenal continuity. Typically, these continuity relations can (at least in principle) branch by holding from one person at one time to two or more people at other times. And, if these relations can branch, the analysis of personal persistence must include a non-branching clause in order to avoid either of two problems, namely, the problem of non-transitive identities and the problem of multiple occupancy.Footnote 3 In this paper, I shall explore what form this non-branching clause should take.Footnote 4 I shall argue that previous accounts are implausible. But, with the help of some ideas from these accounts, I shall develop a new proposal.

Assuming a perdurance framework, we analyse personal persistence in terms of person-stages at different times being I-related, that is, being stages of the same continuant person.Footnote 5 A person, on this framework, is a maximal aggregate of I-related person-stages, that is, an aggregate of person-stages such that (i) each stage in the aggregate is I-related to all stages in the aggregate and (ii) no person-stage that isn’t in the aggregate is I-related to all stages in the aggregate.Footnote 6

Person-stages can (but need not) be extended in time, that is, they can be present not only at a single instant but also at each point in an interval of time.Footnote 7 This opens up for some ambiguities about temporal order, which we should try to avoid. Let us say that a person-stage x is simultaneous with a person-stage y if and only if there is a time at which x and y are both present. Let us say that a person-stage x is present before a person-stage y if and only if there is a time at which x is present which is earlier than all times at which y is present. And let us say that a person-stage x is present after a person-stage y if and only if there is a time at which x is present which is later than all times at which y is present.Footnote 8

Given reductionism about people, Relation I is analysed in terms of some basic kind of connectedness, such as psychological, physical, or phenomenal connectedness. Psychological accounts take the relevant kind of connectedness between person-stages to be direct psychological connections, such as one stage’s having an experience memory (or quasi-memory) of the experiences of the other.Footnote 9 Physical accounts take the relevant kind of connectedness between person-stages to be their sharing a sufficiently large portion of their brains.Footnote 10 And phenomenal accounts take the relevant kind of connectedness between person-stages to be their sharing the same stream of consciousness.Footnote 11 For the purposes of our discussion, we can, for the most part, leave open which one of these kinds of connectedness is the relevant one. Let Relation C be a temporally ordered version of the relevant kind of connectedness:

  • Temporally Ordered Connectedness

  • Person-stage x is C-related to person-stage y (xCy) \(=_{\mathrm {df}}\)x and y are connected by the right kind of connection and x is either simultaneous with y or present earlier than y.

And let Relation \(C'\) be a temporally unordered version:

  • Temporally Unordered Connectedness

  • Person-stage x is C′-related to person-stage y (\(xC'y\)) \(=_{\mathrm {df}}\)x and y are connected by the right kind of connection.

We shall assume that Relation C is reflexive and that Relation \(C'\) is reflexive and symmetric over person-stages.Footnote 12

Consider, first, a direct analysis of Relation I as Relation \(C'\):

  1. (1)

    Person-stage x is I-related to person-stage y if and only if \(xC'y\).

One example of an account of this kind is the memory criterion of personal identity.Footnote 13 This simple account is open to Thomas Reid’s well known counter-example, The Brave Officer:

Suppose a brave officer to have been flogged when a boy at school, for robbing an orchard, to have taken a standard from the enemy in his first campaign, and to have been made a general in advanced life: Suppose also, which must be admitted to be possible, that when he took the standard, he was conscious of his having been flogged at school, and that when made a general he was conscious of his taking the standard, but had absolutely lost the consciousness of his flogging.Footnote 14

That is, as an officer, a man remembers being a boy and, as a general, the man remembers being an officer but not being a boy.Footnote 15 Suppose that The Boy, The Officer, and The General are person-stages from the three periods of the man’s life. Then, if the relevant kind of connections are memories, The Officer is connected both to The Boy and to The General but The General isn’t connected to The Boy. The pattern of connections in this case can be represented diagrammatically as follows, where the double-headed arrows represent \(C'\)-relations:

  • The Brave Officer\((C'\)-relations)

  • figure a

In The Brave Officer, (1) yields that The Officer is I-related both to The Boy and to The General and that The Boy isn’t I-related to The General. Accordingly, we have an instance of multiple occupancy, that is, one person-stage is a stage of two or more people. Given (1), we have two maximal aggregates of I-related person-stages in this case: one consisting of The Boy and The Officer and one consisting of The Officer and The General. The Officer is a stage of one person who has The Boy as a stage and of one person who has The General as a stage. These people cannot be identical, since The Boy isn’t I-related to The General.

In order to avoid multiple occupancy in The Brave Officer, we shall—instead of a connectedness relation—rely on a continuity relation of overlapping connectedness. Let Relation R be the relevant kind of temporally ordered continuity (we shall consider temporally unordered continuity later):

  • Temporally Ordered Continuity

  • Person-stage x is R-related to person-stage y (xRy) \(=_{\mathrm {df}}\) either xCy or yCx, or there are person-stages \(z_1\), \(z_2\), ..., \(z_n\) such that either

    1. (i)

      \(xCz_1\), \(z_1Cz_2\), ..., \(z_{n-1}Cz_n\), \(z_nCy\) or

    2. (ii)

      \(yCz_1\), \(z_1Cz_2\), ..., \(z_{n-1}Cz_n\), \(z_nCx\).

Given the reflexivity of Relation C, Relation R is reflexive and symmetric over person-stages.

John Perry and David Lewis both suggest

  1. (2)

    Person-stage x is I-related to person-stage y if and only if xRy.Footnote 16

This proposal avoids multiple occupancy in The Brave Officer: In that case, it yields that all person-stages are I-related.

Even so, (2) still allows for multiple occupancy. It will do so in division cases such as Derek Parfit’s case My Division. Parfit presents My Division as follows:

My body is fatally injured, as are the brains of my two brothers. My brain is divided, and each half is successfully transplanted into the body of one of my brothers. Each of the resulting people believes that he is me, seems to remember living my life, has my character, and is in every other way psychologically continuous with me. And he has a body that is very like mine.Footnote 17

The pattern of connections in this case can be represented diagrammatically as follows, where Wholly is the person-stage before the division and Lefty and Righty are the two resulting person-stages afterwards:Footnote 18

  • My Division \((C'\) -relations)

  • figure b

In this case, each of (1) and (2) yields that Wholly is I-related both to Lefty and to Righty while Lefty isn’t I-related to Righty. Wholly is then a person-stage of two persons: one who has Lefty as a stage and one who has Righty as a stage.

To preserve the transitivity of Relation I and to avoid multiple occupancy, reductionist accounts of personal persistence typically include a non-branching clause.Footnote 19 Parfit first suggested that

The criterion might be sketched as follows. “X and Y are the same person if they are psychologically continuous and there is no person who is contemporary with either and psychologically continuous with the other.”Footnote 20

In terms of perdurance, we can state this suggestion as follows:Footnote 21

  1. (3)

    Person-stage x is I-related to person-stage y if and only if xRy and there is no person-stage z such that either

    1. (i)

      xRz and y and z are distinct and simultaneous or

    2. (ii)

      yRz and x and z are distinct and simultaneous.

This proposal yields the desired result in My Division: Wholly, Lefty, and Righty are all I-unrelated to each other.

Nevertheless, consider the following unbalanced variant of My Division, which is just like My Division except that the man with the left half of the brain lives on longer than the man with the right half:Footnote 22

  • My Unbalanced Division \((C'\) -relations)

  • figure c

Like Lefty, Old Lefty is a person-stage with the left half of the brain. But Old Lefty is a later stage than Lefty, existing at \(t_3\) after the man with the right half has died. (The \(C'\)-relation between Wholly and Old Lefty won’t be crucial for our discussion, because Wholly would still be R-related to Old Lefty if this connection were removed.)

In My Unbalanced Division, (3) yields that Wholly is I-related to Old Lefty, since they are R-related and neither of them is simultaneous with any other person-stage. Likewise, (3) yields that Old Lefty is I-related to Lefty, since they are R-related and—even though Lefty is simultaneous with Righty—Old Lefty isn’t R-related to Righty. But, according to (3), Wholly isn’t I-related to Lefty, since Wholly is R-related to Righty and Righty is simultaneous with Lefty. So (3) yields that Wholly is I-related to Old Lefty, Old Lefty is I-related to Lefty, and Wholly isn’t I-related to Old Lefty. Hence, given (3), we have a non-transitive Relation I and thus multiple occupancy. Moreover, it’s implausible that Wholly is I-related to Old Lefty, especially given that Wholly isn’t I-related to Lefty.

Consider, furthermore, the following variant of The Brave Officer, where The General is connected to The Boy but not to The Officer:Footnote 23

  • The Senile General \((C'\) -relations)

  • figure d

This pattern of connections could occur if the relevant kind of connections are memories and The General has irrevocably lost all memories of the experiences of The Officer but, just like The Officer, The General remembers the experiences of The Boy. This pattern of connections could also be realized on some physical accounts of the relevant kind of connections. Consider a variant of My Division, where the transplant of the right half of the brain is delayed and the man with the left half dies before the transplant of the right half:

  • My Asynchronous Division \((C'\) -relations; The Senile General pattern)

  • figure e

The idea here is that, even though the right half of the brain exists at \(t_2\), nothing with the right half qualifies as a person-stage while the man with the left half is alive. Furthermore, if the relevant kind of connections could be preserved through travel by teletransportation, the same pattern of connections could be realized in a teletransportation case. Consider a case where I step into a scanner on Earth at \(t_1\). My body is then scanned and destroyed. My scanned information is beamed both to the Moon and to Mars. My information reaches the Moon first, where a replica is created at \(t_2\). Later on, my information reaches Mars, where another replica is created at \(t_3\). The replica on the Moon, however, has died before \(t_3\). Let Earthy be the person-stage being scanned on earth, let Moony be a person-stage of the man on the Moon, and let Marsy be a person-stage of the man on Mars:

  • My Asynchronous Replication \((C'\) -relations; The Senile General pattern)

  • figure f

I mention these variants of The Senile General in order to illustrate different ways in which this pattern of connections could arise given different views on the relevant kind of connectedness. For the purposes of our discussion, however, the differences between these cases won’t matter much.

In The Senile General, (3) yields that The Boy is I-related both to The Officer and to The General, since The Boy is R-related to The Officer and to The General while there are no distinct and simultaneous person-stages in that case—so the non-branching clause in (3) doesn’t apply. And, given (3), The Officer isn’t I-related to The General, since these stages are not R-related. So, like before, we have a non-transitive Relation I and hence multiple occupancy. This result is problematic, since the motivation for having a non-branching clause is to retain the transitivity of Relation I and avoid multiple occupancy. If non-transitivity and multiple occupancy weren’t problematic, we could stick with (2), which is simpler than (3), or with (1), which is simpler still.

Parfit later put forward the following suggestion:

The Psychological Criterion: [i] There is psychological continuity if and only if there are overlapping chains of strong connectedness. X today is one and the same person as Y at some past time if and only if [ii] X is psychologically continuous with Y, [iii] this continuity has the right kind of cause, and [iv] there does not exist a different person who is also psychologically continuous with Y.Footnote 24

In terms of perdurance, this suggestion can be interpreted as follows:Footnote 25

  1. (4)

    Person-stage x is I-related to person-stage y if and only if xRy and there is no person-stage z such that either

    1. (i)

      xRz and not yIz or

    2. (ii)

      yRz and not xIz.

This proposal has been charged with circularity since it analyses Relation I partly in terms of itself.Footnote 26 Analysing a relation partly in terms of the same relation needn’t be a problem, however; this is a standard feature of recursive definitions. Rather, the problem with (4) is incompleteness. Consider, for example, The Brave Officer where (4) is both compatible with (a) The Boy, The Officer, and The General all being I-related and compatible with (b) The Boy, The Officer, and The General all being I-unrelated to each other. To see that (4) is compatible with (a), note that, if The Boy, The Officer, and The General are all I-related, then clauses (i) and (ii) in (4) will never hold. To see that (4) is compatible with (b), note that, if The Boy, The Officer, and The General are all I-unrelated to each other, then one of clauses (i) and (ii) in (4) will always hold for some person-stage z. Hence (4) is compatible both with (a) and with (b). So (4) can’t provide a complete account of which person-stages are I-related.

In addition to incompleteness, there’s a further problem with (4). Consider a version of My Division which is extended before the fission, highlighting that the man who divides lived undivided for an extended period of time before the division:

  • My Extended Pre-Division \((C'\) -relations)

  • figure g

This is, of course, how My Division is usually understood; the difference is merely that we highlight Wholly’s extended past in the model. (The \(C'\)-relations between Young Wholly and Lefty and between Young Wholly and Righty won’t be crucial for our discussion, because Young Wholly would still be R-related both to Lefty and to Righty if these connections were removed.)

In My Extended Pre-Division, it seems that Young Wholly should be I-related to Wholly. But this is ruled out by (4). For proof by contradiction, assume that Young Wholly is I-related to Wholly. Since the non-branching clause in (4) then cannot rule out that Young Wholly is I-related to Wholly, it is not the case that Young Wholly is R-related to Lefty while Wholly isn’t I-related to Lefty. Therefore, since Young Wholly is R-related to Lefty, we have that Wholly is I-related to Lefty. According to (4), Lefty isn’t I-related to Righty, since Lefty isn’t R-related to Righty. Therefore, since Wholly is R-related to Righty while Lefty isn’t I-related to Righty, the non-branching clause in (4) rules out that Wholly is I-related to Lefty. We then have the contradiction that Wholly both is and is notI-related to Lefty.

Parfit’s final suggestion was the following:Footnote 27

  1. (5)

    Person-stage x is I-related to person-stage y if and only if xRy and there is no person-stage z such that either

    1. (i)

      xRz and not yRz or

    2. (ii)

      yRz and not xRz.

This suggestion is better. In fact, it avoids all problems we have discussed so far. And, given (5), Relation I is an equivalence relation—that is, it is reflexive, symmetric, and transitive—over person-stages.

But (5) is still unsatisfactory. Consider a variant of My Division where Lefty and Righty are reunited some time after the division by a second round of transplants in which the two halves are reunited in a single body:

  • My Temporary Division \((C'\) -relations)

  • figure h

Note that the double-headed arrow between Wholly and Old Wholly just represents a direct connection between these stages and not the existence of a further person-stage at \(t_2\) in addition to Lefty and Righty. This connection won’t matter for our discussion. For our discussion, we may just as well consider a variant without this connection:

  • My Forgetful Temporary Division \((C'\)-relations)

  • figure i

In My Temporary Division or My Forgetful Temporary Division, (5) yields that the only I-related person-stages are Wholly and Old Wholly. To see this, note that, for all distinct pairs of person-stages other than the pair of Wholly and Old Wholly, one of Lefty and Righty is R-related to one stage in the pair but not to the other. So, for these pairs, the non-branching clause in (5) rules out that Relation I holds. Wholly and Old Wholly, however, are R-related to the same person-stages. It seems odd that Wholly and Old Wholly would be I-related, because there is branching in the continuity between them (especially in My Forgetful Temporary Division).

We can get around this problem with the following proposal from Sydney Shoemaker:Footnote 28

  1. (6)

    Person-stage x is I-related to person-stage y if and only if xRy and there is no person-stage z such that

    1. (i)

      z is not present before each of x and y is present,

    2. (ii)

      z is not present after each of x and y is present,

    3. (iii)

      zRx,

    4. (iv)

      zRy, and

    5. (v)

      there are two distinct and simultaneous person-stages u and v such that \(zC'u\) and \(zC'v\).

In My Temporary Division and My Forgetful Temporary Division, (6) yields that all person-stages are I-unrelated to each other. According to (6), Lefty and Righty are not I-related, since they’re not R-related. And neither Wholly nor Old Wholly is I-related to any person-stage given (6), since they are both \(C'\)-related to the distinct and simultaneous Lefty and Righty. Note, however, that this entails that Wholly and Old Wholly are not I-related to themselves. So (6) violates the reflexivity of the Relation I. Obviously, each person-stage should be I-related to itself.

In My Extended Pre-Division, (6) yields—just like (4)—the implausible result that Young Wholly isn’t I-related to Wholly. Young Wholly’s being I-related to Wholly is ruled out by the non-branching clause in (6), since Young Wholly is R-related to Wholly while Wholly is R-related to itself and is \(C'\)-related both to Lefty and to Righty.

In The Senile General, the non-branching clause in (6) doesn’t apply, because there are no distinct and simultaneous person-stages in that case. So (6) yields that The Boy is I-related both to The Officer and to The General (since The Boy is R-related to them) and that The Officer isn’t I-related to The General (since they’re not R-related). Hence we get a non-transitive Relation I and thus multiple-occupancy, which defeats the purpose of having a non-branching clause.

Finally, consider a variant of My Extended Pre-Division where Righty isn’t connected to Wholly while Lefty isn’t connected to Young Wholly:

  • My Forgetful Division \((C'\)-relations)

  • figure j

Suppose, for example, that the relevant kind of connections are memories and that the brain transplants cause irrevocable losses of memory: Lefty remembers Wholly but can’t remember Young Wholly; Righty remembers Young Wholly but can’t remember Wholly. And suppose that the transplants happen between \(t_2\) and \(t_3\); so, at \(t_2\), the brain halves are still united in Wholly.

In My Forgetful Division, (6) yields that Young Wholly is I-related both to Lefty and to Righty, even though there is clearly branching here given that Lefty and Righty are distinct and simultaneous person-stages.Footnote 29 Clause (v) in (6) doesn’t hold in this case, because no person-stage is \(C'\)-related to each of two simultaneous person-stages.

Anthony Brueckner maintains that, in The Senile General, The Officer should be I-related to The General. To get this result, Brueckner argues that Relation I needs to be analysed in terms of temporally unordered continuity, rather than the temporally ordered variety. Let Relation \(R'\) be the temporally unordered variant of Relation R:

  • Temporally Unordered Continuity

  • Person-stage x is \(R'\)-related to person-stage y (\(xR'y\)) \(=_{\mathrm {df}}\)\(xC'y\) or there are person-stages \(z_1\), \(z_2\), ..., \(z_n\) such that \(xC'z_1\), \(z_1C'z_2\), ..., \(z_{n-1}C'z_n\), \(z_nC'y\).

Given the reflexivity and symmetry of Relation \(C'\), Relation \(R'\) is reflexive, symmetric, and transitive over person-stages.

Brueckner considers, but does not defend, the following temporally unordered variant of (5):Footnote 30

  1. (7)

    Person-stage x is I-related to person-stage y if and only if \(xR'y\) and there is no person-stage z such that either

    1. (i)

      \(xR'z\) and not \(yR'z\) or

    2. (ii)

      \(yR'z\) and not \(xR'z\).

The main problem with (7) is that, since Relation \(R'\) is already transitive, the non-branching clause in (7) doesn’t rule out anything: (7) is equivalent to an account that identifies Relation I with Relation \(R'\). So, in My Division, (7) yields that all person-stages are I-related. Hence we have that Lefty is I-related to Righty even though they are distinct and simultaneous person-stages, which seems wrong.

Brueckner also considers a temporally unordered variant of (3):Footnote 31

  1. (8)

    Person-stage x is I-related to person-stage y if and only if \(xR'y\) and there is no person-stage z such that either

    1. (i)

      \(xR'z\) and y and z are distinct and simultaneous or

    2. (ii)

      \(yR'z\) and x and z are distinct and simultaneous.

One problem with (8) is that it yields an implausible result in My Unbalanced Division, namely, that Wholly and Old Lefty are the only person-stages that are I-related to each other.Footnote 32 Given (8), Wholly and Old Lefty are I-related, since they are \(R'\)-related and neither of them is simultaneous with another person-stage. The non-branching clause in (8) rules out that Lefty or Righty is I-related to any person-stage, since Lefty and Righty are distinct, simultaneous, and \(R'\)-related to each other. This also entails that Relation I is not reflexive given (8), because it entails that Lefty isn’t I-related to Lefty and that Righty isn’t I-related to Righty.

Harold W. Noonan amends (8) as follows:Footnote 33

  1. (9)

    Person-stage x is I-related to person-stage y if and only if \(xR'y\) and there are no distinct and simultaneous person-stages u and v such that either

    1. (i)

      \(uR'x\), \(uR'y\), and \(vR'x\) or

    2. (ii)

      \(uR'x\), \(uR'y\), and \(vR'y\).

Yet, in My Unbalanced Division, (9) does not yield the desired result that Lefty is I-related to Old Lefty. And, given (9), Relation I still fails to be reflexive, because (9) yields that no person-stage in My Unbalanced Division is I-related to itself.Footnote 34 To see this, note that all person-stages are \(R'\)-related in My Unbalanced Division. Hence the non-branching clause in (9) yields that no person-stages are I-related, since each person-stage is \(R'\)-related to the distinct and simultaneous Lefty and Righty.

Consider once more My Unbalanced Division as diagrammed earlier together with an alternative diagrammatic representation of the case—where, unlike in the earlier diagrams, the double-headed arrows this time represent \(R'\)-relations rather than \(C'\)-relations:

  • My Unbalanced Division \((C'\)-relations)

  • figure k
  • My Unbalanced Division \((R'\)-relations)

  • figure l

Since there is a temporally unordered chain of \(C'\)-relations linking all person-stages in My Unbalanced Division, we get that all person-stages in My Unbalanced Division are \(R'\)-related. In terms of Relation \(R'\), there is just as much branching between Wholly at \(t_1\) and the person-stages at \(t_2\) as there is between the person-stages at \(t_2\) and Old Lefty at \(t_3\). Rather than a tree-structured pattern of relationships, we have a collection of person-stages all of which are \(R'\)-related to all the others. Plausibly, Lefty and Old Lefty belong to the same branch while Righty and Old Lefty do not. The trouble is that there is no way of accounting for this in terms of any sort of branching of Relation \(R'\), because, in terms of Relation \(R'\), Old Lefty’s relations to Lefty are symmetrical with Old Lefty’s relations to Righty. Hence any approach, like (8) or (9), that tries to analyse non-branching personal identity just in terms of constructions out of Relation \(R'\) will fail.Footnote 35

What Noonan has in mind, however, is probably a variant of (9) with temporally ordered, rather than unordered, continuity:

  1. (10)

    Person-stage x is I-related to person-stage y if and only if xRy and there are no distinct and simultaneous person-stages u and v such that either

    1. (i)

      uRx, uRy, and vRx or

    2. (ii)

      uRx, uRy, and vRy.

This proposal yields that Lefty is I-related to Old Lefty in My Unbalanced Division.

Even so, (10) yields the wrong result in My Extended Pre-Division. The non-branching clause in (10) rules out that Young Wholly is I-related to Wholly. This is because Lefty and Righty are distinct and simultaneous and Lefty is R-related both to Young Wholly and to Wholly while Righty is R-related to Wholly. And (10) yields that Young Wholly and Wholly are not I-related to themselves, because they are R-related to the distinct and simultaneous Lefty and Righty. Hence (10) violates the reflexivity of Relation I.

Moreover, in The Senile General, (10) yields that The Boy is I-related both to The Officer and to The General while The Officer is not I-related to The General. This is because there are no distinct and simultaneous person-stages in that case; so all person-stages are I-related except The Officer and The General. The Officer and The General are not I-related, since they’re not R-related. Hence, as with (3) and (6), we get a non-transitive Relation I and thus multiple occupancy.

We have seen that the previously proposed non-branching clauses don’t work. But there is, I shall argue, a better approach. I propose

  1. (11)

    Person-stage x is I-related to person-stage y if and only if xRy and there are no person-stages u and v such that

    1. (i)

      neither u nor v is present before each of x and y is present,

    2. (ii)

      neither u nor v is present after each of x and y is present,

    3. (iii)

      uRx,

    4. (iv)

      vRy, and

    5. (v)

      there is a person-stage z such that either (a) uRz and not vRz or (b) vRz and not uRz.

Given (11), Relation I is an equivalence relation over person-stages. For a proof of reflexivity, see Appendix A. For a proof of symmetry, see Appendix B. And, for a proof of transitivity, see Appendix C.

The idea behind the non-branching clause in (11) is to characterize the intuitive idea of there being two person-stages u and v in different branches in the continuity between x and y. Clauses (i) and (ii) make sure that the relevant branching doesn’t occur before or after both x and y; so we avoid the problem (4), (6), and (10) had with ruling out that, in My Extended Pre-Division, Young Wholly and Wholly are I-related. Clauses (iii) and (iv) make sure that u and v are part of the relevant continuities to or from x and y respectively. Finally, clause (v) makes sure that u and v belong to different branches in the sense that there is a person-stage that is continuous with one of them but not with the other. Clause (v) is similar to the non-branching clause in (5), but, unlike the non-branching clause in (5), it doesn’t require that u and v are identical with x and y respectively; so it rules out, in My Temporary Division or My Forgetful Temporary Division, that Wholly is I-related to Old Wholly.

Note also that, (11) doesn’t rely on the identity or distinctness of person-stages, which (3), (4), (6), (8), (9), and (10) all rely on. This lets (11) sidestep any worries about the alleged circularity in relying on Relation I, identity, or distinctness between person-stages in an account of Relation I.Footnote 36 And (11)—unlike (1), (2), and (7)—yields the desired result in My Division, namely, that all person-stages are I-unrelated to each other. It also yields acceptable results in the other cases. In these cases, (11) yields the following: In The Brave Officer, all person-stages are I-related. In The Senile General, My Temporary Division, and My Forgetful Temporary Division, all person-stages are I-unrelated to each other. In My Unbalanced Division, the only I-related person-stages are Lefty and Old Lefty. In My Extended Pre-Division, the only I-related person-stages are Young Wholly and Wholly. And, in My Forgetful Division, the only I-related person-stages are Wholly and Lefty.

One might be worried about the result in The Senile General.

First, one might think that The Officer should be I-related to The General.Footnote 37 If so, one might be tempted to rely on Relation \(R'\) rather than Relation R; but, as I argued earlier, relying on temporally unordered continuity doesn’t fit with some plausible ideas about branching in cases like My Unbalanced Division. If there is a possible case structured like The Senile General such that it seems that the stage corresponding to The Officer should be I-related to the stage corresponding to The General, then a more promising approach is to revise the criteria for what counts as the relevant kind of connectedness so that these stages will be connected.Footnote 38

Second, one might think that The Boy should be I-related to The Officer. And one might think that whether The Boy at \(t_1\) is I-related to The Officer at \(t_2\) shouldn’t depend on what person-stages The General at \(t_3\) (after both \(t_1\) and \(t_2\)) is connected to. If The General had a connection to The Officer like in The Brave Officer, then The Boy would be I-related to The Officer. For similar reasons, one might think that, in My Forgetful Division, Young Wholly should be I-related to Wholly.Footnote 39 As long as the connections between person-stages are structured like they are in these cases and we rely on temporally ordered continuity, it is hard to deny that the continuity branches between \(t_1\) and \(t_2\). If this dependence on the future is implausible, there is a more promising way to avoid such dependence than to rely on temporally unordered continuity, namely, to restrict the relevant kinds of connectedness so that it only holds between person-stages without any temporal gaps between them.Footnote 40 Given this restriction, the connection in The Senile General between The Boy and The General would be invalidated, and then (11) would yield that The Boy is I-related to The Officer. Similarly, in My Forgetful Division, this restriction would invalidate the connection between Young Wholly and Righty, and then (11) would yield that Young Wholly is I-related to Wholly.