Skip to main content
Log in

Outlines of a theory of structural explanations

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper argues that in some explanations mathematics are playing an explanatory rather than a representational role, and that this feature unifies many types of non-causal or non-mechanistic explanations that some philosophers of science have been recently exploring under various names (mathematical, topological, etc.). After showing how mathematics can play either a representational or an explanatory role by considering two alternative explanations of a same biological pattern—“Bergmann’s rule”—I offer an example of an explanation where the bulk of the explanatory job is done by a mathematical theorem, and where mechanisms involved in the target systems are not explanatorily relevant. Then I account for the way mathematical properties may function in an explanatory way within an explanation by arguing that some mathematical propositions involving variables non directly referring to the target system features constitute constraints to which a whole class of systems should comply, provided they are describable by a mathematical object concerned by those propositions. According to such “constraint account”, those mathematical facts are directly entailing the explanandum (often a limit regime, a robustness property or a steady state), as a consequence of such constraints. I call those explanations “structural”, because here properties of mathematical structures are accounting for the explanandum; various kinds of mathematical structures (algebraic, graph-theoretical, etc.) thereby define various types of structural explanations.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Some mechanicists like Bechtel or Glennan are reluctant regarding an ontic conception because they think that the model of the mechanism itself explains, while the mechanism stands in the world. Hence they view themselves as favoring an epistemic view of explanation—but this difference is not relevant for my present purposes.

  2. See also Rice (2012) for a non-causal understanding of optimality explanations.

  3. The FTNS is easily derived from the Price equation, an analytic formulation of the intergenerational change of the phenotypic value of a trait—when one takes fitness itself as a focal trait. See among others Price (1972) and Gardner (2009).

  4. See Price (1972), Frank and Slatkin (1992) and Edwards (1994) for various demonstrations.

  5. Provisionally, this term names all the explanations cited here, to the extent that they refer to formal properties. A full justification of this label is given in Sect. 4.

  6. Mechanisms may be very abstract—the issue of distinguishing abstract mechanisms, or very abstract types of representation of mechanisms (this distinction is not crucial here) from the types of explanations considered here will be addressed in Sect. 5—but see also Felline (2015) and Huneman (2015): the upshot here is that if a mechanism is too abstract, it trivializes the very idea of a mechanism.

  7. I use “generality” about the fact that propositions holds for a wide variety of cases, abstracting away for their specificities. By contrast “genericity” points to the difference of ontological domains in which a property holds. “Generic” behaviors are for instance features of phase transition, that are identical in epidemiology, condensed matter physics or financial markets, considered as networks. Genericity is often defined in terms of limit behaviors that are manifest through a passage to an infinite limit, like in the paradigmatic case of phase transitions.

  8. Given that this paper intends to be as neutral as possible regarding the ontology of mathematics, I won’t assume more than that. I clearly touch upon issues that are not unrelated with problems familiar to philosophers of mathematics: ontology of mathematical entities, indispensability of mathematics, abstraction, explanations within mathematics. However, since I aim at outlining a theory of explanation for the empirical sciences I try to minimally assume theses from the philosophy of mathematics.

  9. See Huneman (2015) for a critique of the argument that topological explanations are indeed the description of very abstract mechanisms.

  10. See Gaucherel et al. (2011) for this issue in ecology.

  11. To prevent any objection based on the preceding discussion, notice that in the case of optimality reasoning, the function involving fitness did not describe a process taking place anywhere—in the sense that no single entity is converting each phenotypic value unit into a fitness value, but the ‘converter’ is each time a distinct organism.

  12. Notice that simplifying animal shapes by treating them as spheres is a rather conservative estimate since this figure has the smallest surface area to volume ratio. For all other shapes, the rule is even more justified.

  13. The role of counterfactual dependence in those non-causal explanations is sketched in Huneman (2010) for topological explanations, and more generally studied by Reutlinger (2006).

  14. This is approximated here as a sphere, but the only important point is that forms are comparable, which obtains since we consider a given clade or genera.

  15. One could see those facts as physical facts represented in mathematics; however, they are still different from physical facts such as the melting temperature of iron—since they are properties that space necessarily should have. Mathematics is the set of those necessary facts. Physical space has the features it has—for instance, that any triangle build with a diameter of a circle and a point on this circle will be a rectangular triangle—in virtue of those mathematical facts, that are by themselves necessary. The question of the relation of these facts to physical facts commits one to an interpretation of the status of mathematical truths, which I don’t want to address here. The account of mathematical properties as standing in scientific explanations should be as independent as possible from such kinds of issues proper to the philosophy of mathematics.

  16. The distribution need not be normal, indeed.

  17. An exact formulation of the Lindeberg condition is not needed here. See Ash (2000, 307). Lyon (2014) has a sophisticated critique of the use of the CLT to justify normal distributions, but it wouldn’t change the sense of the example here.

  18. I focused here on the case of normal distributions because it was the easiest one and the most familiar.

  19. Later sections will answer the objection that this could be only a very abstract mechanism—yet the above mentioned papers by Felline and Huneman suggest answers to this objection, yet not in the present context of trying to define mathematical explanatoriness.

  20. Unlike for instance Bergmann’s rule, where the assumption that a specific “mechanism” causing dominant phenotypes is at work.

  21. See Humphreys (2014) for a development on the role satisfaction of a condition plays in an explanation—and its discussion below in Sect. 5.

  22. They can also be physically represented, for sure, but this representation can in turn often be mathematically captured.

  23. Actually there is even one journal in mathematics devoted to fixed-point theorems: Fixed-point theory.

  24. Actually Nash uses also Brouwer’s theorem in another demonstration in his dissertation, but of course the logics of the argument is the same (Hofbauer 2000).

  25. When brought about by migration they are by definition rare at the beginning.

  26. I considered here functions and analysis, but an analogous reasoning easily holds for other mathematical objects such as matrices etc.

  27. It is also the topic of the more general “category theory” but this paper does not intend to commit to category theory.

  28. Of course a function can be seen as a set of n-tuples and therefore the sets of sets and the functions of functions are isomorphic. This plays a crucial role when addressing the issue of (non-)equivalence between different kinds of structural explanations distinguished by the nature of the mathematical properties involved—see below.

  29. The question of the interpretation of those probabilities can be left aside. There is a way of interpreting them causally that would turn such independence into causal independence and open the way for an argument where this condition is in the end a causal condition—but the point made here is supposed to hold independently, or prior to any interpretation of probabilities. Moreover Strevens (2015) shows how causal and probabilistic independence are not in principle equivalent.

  30. Reutlinger (ms) develops a strong critique of the argument that derives non-causality from the abstractness of explanations.

  31. Note that all this should hold whatever the correct position regarding mathematical entities (fictionalism, Platonism, etc.).

  32. A second issue untouched here is the relation of this account to category theory, which is in mathematics a very recent and general theory precisely concerned with the structures proper to various mathematical theories and their relations. This should be done but the main point of this paper was to introduce and describe this kind of explanations in general. Thus, this specific mathematical theory, whose use is often controversial, needs not be brought into the picture for now—though it will be when the question of the relations between those “subfamilies” will come to the fore.

    Another issue is the relation between those explanations and structural realism. It’s left for another investigation. From their notion of structural explanations, Dorato and Felline (2011) suggest an account of that.

  33. Lange has just published a book about non-causal explanations (Lange 2016), which develops the views presented in (2013a, b). Given that the present paper has been written before the publication of this book, I won’t compare its theory to the ones he elaborates there. This would anyway be much too long here and will be left for a coming work.

  34. Humphreys’ paper also includes a consideration of the mathematical hierarchy, connected with the generality and depth of explanations—which concurs with the ideas of reference and hierarchies used here in order to make sense of explanatoriness.

  35. Actually this distinction is exactly the one made in terms of distinct why-questions when Huneman (2010) about topological explanations distinguishes the explanation of the stability properties of a ecosystem having given topological properties from the explanation of the fact that a given ecosystem indeed has a network of interaction that realizes those properties.

References

  • Altenberg, L. (2004). Open problems in the spectral analysis of evolutionary dynamics. In A. Menon (Ed.), Frontiers of evolutionary computation (pp. 73–102). Boston: Kluwer.

  • Altenberg, L., & Feldman, M. W. (1987). Selection, generalized transmission, and the evolution of modifier genes. I. The reduction principle. Genetics, 117, 559–572.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ash, R. (2000). Probability and measure theory. London: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ariew, A., Rice, C., & Rohwer, Y. (2014). Autonomous-statistical explanations and natural selection. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 1–24

  • Baker, A. (2009). Mathematical explanation in science. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 60, 611–633.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Batterman, R. (2002). The devil in the details: Asymptotic reasoning in explanation, reduction, and emergence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Batterman, R. (2010). On the explanatory role of mathematics in empirical science. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 61, 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Batterman, R., & Rice, C. (2014). Minimal model explanations. Philosophy of Science, 81(3), 349–376.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., & Abrahamsen, A. (2005). Explanation: A mechanistic alternative. Studies in History and Philosophy of the Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 36, 421–441.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Charnov, E. L. (1976). Optimal foraging: The marginal value theorem. Theoretical Population Biology, 9, 129–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Charnov, E. L., & Krebs, J. L. (1974). On clutch size and fitness. Ibis, 116, 217–219.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clancy, S. (2008). RNA splicing: Introns, exons and spliceosome. Nature Education, 1(1), 31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Colizza, V., Pastor-Satorras, R., & Vespignani, A. (2007). Reaction–diffusion processes and metapopulation models in heterogeneous networks. Nature Physics, 3, 276–282.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. (2007). Explaining the brain. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C., & Darden, L. (2013). In search for mechanisms: Discovery across the life sciences. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Darden, L. (2006). Reasoning in biological discoveries: Essays on mechanisms, interfield relations, and anomaly resolution. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Dorato, M., & Felline, L. (2011). Scientific explanation and scientific structuralism. In A. Bokulich & P. Bokulich (Eds.), scientific structuralism (pp. 161–177). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duarte, C. M., Amthor, J., DeAngelis, D. L., Joyce, L. A., Maranger, R. J., Pace, M. L., Pastor, J., Running, S. (2003). The limits to models in ecology. In C. D. Canham, J. J. Cole, & W. K. Lauenroth (Eds.), Models in ecosystem science (pp. 437–451). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

  • Edwards, A. W. F. (1994). The fundamental theorem of natural selection. Biological Reviews of the Cambridge Philosophical Society, 69(4), 443–474.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ewens, W. J. (1989). An interpretation and proof of the fundamental theorem of natural selection. Theoretical Population Biology, 36(2), 167–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Felline, L. (2015). Mechanisms meet structural explanation. Synthese. doi:10.1007/s11229-015-0746-9.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher, R. (1930). The genetical theory of natural selection. London: Methuen.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Frank, S. A. (2009). The common patterns of nature. Journal of Evolutionary Biology, 22, 1563–1585.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frank, S. A., & Slatkin, M. (1992). Fisher’s fundamental theorem of natural selection. Trends in Ecology and Evolution, 7, 92–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. (1974). Explanation and scientific understanding. Journal of Philosophy, 71, 5–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gardner, A. (2009). Adaptation as organism design. Biology Letters, 5, 861–864.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gaucherel, C., Munoz, F., & Bérard, S. (2011). Equation against algorithm: Differences and choosing between them? Acta Biotheoretica, 59(1), 67–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gillespie, J. H. (2004). Population genetics: A concise guide. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glennan, S. (ms). The new mechanical philosophy.

  • Glennan, S. (1996). Mechanisms and the nature of causation. Erkenntnis, 44, 49–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grafen, A. (2002). A first formal link between the Price equation and an optimisation program. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 217, 75–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grafen, A. (2007). The formal Darwinism project: A mid-term report. Journal of Evolutionary Biology, 20, 1243–1254.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gross, J. L., & Tucker, T. W. (1987). Topological graph theory. Reading, MA: Wiley Interscience.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hall, N. (2004). Two concepts of cause. In J. Collins, N. Hall, & L. A. Paul (Eds.), Causation and counterfactuals (pp. 225–276). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hofbauer, J. (2000). From Nash and Brown to Maynard—Smith: Equilibria, dynamics and ESS. Selection, 1, 81–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Humphreys, P. (2014). Explanation as condition satisfaction. Philosophy of Science, 81(5), 1103–1116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huneman, P. (2010). Topological explanations and robustness in biological sciences. Synthese, 177(2), 213–245.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huneman, P. (2015). Diversifying the picture of explanations in biological sciences: Ways of combining topology with mechanisms. Synthese. doi:10.1007/s11229-015-0808-z.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jones, N. (2014). Bowtie structures, pathway diagrams, and topological explanation. Erkenntnis, 89(5), 1355–1555.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Karlin, S. (1982). Classifications of selection–migration structures and conditions for a protected polymorphism. In M. K. Hecht, B. Wallace, & G. T. Prance (Eds.), Evolutionary biology (Vol. 14, pp. 61–204). Berlin: Plenum Publishing Corporation.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1989). Explanatory unification and the causal structure of the world. In P. Kitcher & W. Salmon (Eds.), Scientific explanation (pp. 410–505). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuorikoski, J. (2007). Explaining with equilibria. In J. Persson & P. Ylikoski (Eds.), Rethinking explanation (pp. 149–162). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lange, M. (2013a). Really statistical explanations and genetic drift. Philosophy of Science, 80(2), 169–188.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lange, M. (2013b). What makes a scientific explanation distinctively mathematical? British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 64, 485–511.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lange, M. (2016). Because without cause. New-York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Levins, R. (1966). The strategy of model building in population biology. American Scientist, 54, 421–431.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1973). Causation. Journal of Philosophy, 70, 556–67. Reprinted with Postscripts in Lewis, 1986, 159–213

  • Lusternik, N., & Sobolev, V. (1961). Elements of functional analysis. London: Frederick Ungar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lyon, A. (2014). Why are normal distributions normal? British Journal for Philosophy of Science, 65(3), 621–649.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machamer, P., Darden, L., & Craver, C. (2000). Thinking of mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 67(1), 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • May, R., Levin, S., & Sugihara, G. (2008). Complex systems: Ecology for bankers. Nature, 451, 893–895.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meyn, S., & Tweedie, R. (1993). Markov chains and stochastic stability. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Morrison, M. (2014). Complex systems and renormalization group explanations. Philosophy of Science, 81(5), 1144–1156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nash, J. (1950). Equilibrium points in n-person games. PNAS, 36, 48–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Price, G. R. (1972). Fisher’s fundamental theorem made clear. Annals of Human Genetics, 36, 129–140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rathkopf, C. (2015). Network representation and complex systems. Synthese. doi:10.1007/s11229-015-0726-0.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reutlinger. (ms). Are explanations non-causal by virtue of being abstract?

  • Reutlinger, A. (2006). Is there a monist theory of causal and noncausal explanations? The counterfactual theory of scientific explanation. Philosophy of Science, 83(5), 733–745

  • Rice, C. (2012). Optimality explanations: A plea for an alternative approach. Biology and Philosophy, 27(5), 685–703.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ruelle, D. (1989). Chaotic evolution and strange attractors. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. (1984). Scientific explanation and the causal structure of the world. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seung, S. H. (2012). Connectome: How the brain’s wiring makes us who we are. New York: Houghton Mifflin Harcourt Trade.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, L. (2015). Mechanism or bust? Explanation in psychology. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. doi:10.1093/bjps/axv062.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (1983). Equilibrium Explanation. Philosophical Studies, 43(2), 201–210.

  • Solé, R. V., & Montoya, J. M. (2001). Complexity and fragility in ecological networks. Proceedings of the Royal Society of London, Series B: Biological Sciences, 268, 2039–2045.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, M. (2015). Stochastic independence and causal connection. Erkenntnis, 80(Suppl 3), 605–627.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turing, A. (1952). The chemical basis of morphogenesis. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London. Series B, Biological sciences, 237(641), 37–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walsh, D. (2015). Variance, invariance and statistical explanation. Erkenntnis, 80(3), 469–489.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Watts, D. J., & Strogatz, S. H. (1998). Collective dynamics in “small-world” networks. Nature, 393, 440–442.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Winther, R. (2011). Part-whole science. Synthese, 178, 397–427.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen: A theory of causal explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2013). II—Mechanistic explanation: Its scope and limits. Aristotelian Society Supplementary, 87(1), 39–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am grateful to Carl Craver, Stuart Glennan, Paul Humphreys and Anya Plutynski for insightful comments and constructive criticism on drafts of this paper, and to Robert Batterman, Laura Felline, Tom Polger, Larry Shapiro and Rasmus Winther for discussions on the arguments. Thanks to Andrew McFarland for a thorough language checking of the text. I also warmly thank an anonymous reviewer for critiques and suggestions that substantially improved the paper. This work is supported by the Grant ANR 13 BSH3 0007 “Explabio”.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Philippe Huneman.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Huneman, P. Outlines of a theory of structural explanations. Philos Stud 175, 665–702 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-017-0887-4

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-017-0887-4

Keywords

Navigation