Skip to main content
Log in

Perceptual access reasoning: developmental stage or system 1 heuristic?

  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In contrast with the two dominant views in Theory of Mind development, the Perceptual Access Reasoning hypothesis of Fabricius and colleagues is that children don’t understand the mental state of belief until around 6 years of age. Evidence for this includes data that many children ages 4 and 5, who pass the standard 2-location false belief task, nonetheless fail the true belief task, and often fail a 3-location false belief task by choosing the irrelevant option. These findings can be explained by the PAR hypothesis but pose challenges for the two dominant views. I argue against an alternate hypothesis which is proposed by Anika Fiebich in a recent paper. According to Fiebich, PAR is not a distinct transitional stage in children’s theory of mind development, but is a fast and frugal System 1 heuristic which fades once children become fluent in social reasoning. However, I point out a number of problems with Fiebich’s proposal and argue for the superiority of the PAR hypothesis. I also present five reasons to be skeptical about the findings of Perner and Horn which purportedly show that 4- and 5-year-olds can pass the 3-location false belief task when suitably modified. This is a further difficulty for Fiebich’s proposal, since she relies on these findings in her fluency theory. Finally, I sketch a dual systems theory of mind account based upon the PAR hypothesis which is different from Fiebich’s.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For example, Henry Wellman, one of the pioneers of the ToM field, and his colleagues recently write (Wellman et al. 2011)…

    Our measure of theory of mind is a battery of false belief tasks. Explicit false-belief understanding is a milestone, universal theory-of-mind achievement of the preschool years (Wellman et al. 2001), and is the most commonly used measure in research examining individual differences in theory of mind during the preschool years… (p. 321)

  2. Perner and Horn (2003) tested the PAR hypothesis using a variation of the three-alternative false belief procedure designed to be simpler than that used by Fabricius and Khalil, and they concluded that their findings refuted the hypothesis. However, I provide a number of reasons to doubt these findings in Section 4.1 below.

  3. Dennett (1978), Harman (1978), Bennett (1978), and Pylyshyn (1978), commenting on studies of chimpanzee theory of mind, all suggested that an adequate test of belief understanding should involve the ability to predict the actions of an agent with a false belief. The false belief task (Wimmer and Perner 1983) was based upon the suggestions of these philosophers. Some philosophers had already stressed the importance of understanding false belief in order to count as having the concept BELIEF; Donald Davidson (1975), e.g., argues that “Someone cannot have a belief unless he understands the possibility of being mistaken, and this requires grasping the contrast between truth and error—true belief and false belief” (p. 170).

  4. Other versions of the false and true belief tasks were used by Fabricius and Khalil (2003) and Fabricius et al. (2010), but they have been left out of this streamlined exposition in order to keep it simple. These included for example the false contents or “Smarties” task (Hogrefe et al. 1986), the appearance/reality or false identity task (Flavell et al. 1983), and modified versions of these as true belief tasks (Fabricius et al. 2010). For descriptions and discussion see also Hedger and Fabricius (2011) and Fiebich (2014).

  5. Of course, according to Perner and Horn (2003) children use BR consistently at this stage, and according to Fabricius and colleagues children use PAR consistently at this stage, while Fiebich’s idea contains a switching back and forth between the two reasoning strategies, depending upon the task. I am tempted to appeal to parsimony here, but I’m also aware that these sorts of debates all too often become an irreconcilable conflict of intuitions, and so I set that worry aside for the remainder of the paper.

  6. For those interested in the details, the standard 2-option false contents task (or Smarties task) is a second false belief task (Hogrefe et al. 1986). The child is shown a familiar candy container, such as an M&M bag, and asked what he thinks is inside. After the child says “M&M’s,” it is revealed that something unexpected is inside, such as a pencil. After the pencil is placed back inside the bag, the subject is informed that a friend of the experimenter’s (named “Elmo” e.g.,) is waiting outside. The test question is: “If he just looks at it, what will Elmo think is inside the bag?” The correct answer is to attribute to Elmo a false belief that M&M’s are inside the bag. The “typical box” task of Perner and Horn (2003) followed this procedure, except that in the 3-option version the protagonist removes the pencil and exchanges it with a pebble before asking the test question. This was similar to the 3-option contents task used by Fabricius and Khalil (2003), and in both studies some subjects chose the irrelevant option (a pencil in this particular case), which is consistent with what the PAR hypothesis would predict. (A child using PAR should reason that Elmo doesn’t see what’s inside the container, and therefore won’t know what’s in the container and will “get it wrong.” Thus, given a forced choice she should choose randomly between the false belief contents and the irrelevant contents, since both options are incorrect.) In the neutral box task of Perner and Horn (2003), a plain box with no markings or color was used in place of the familiar candy container.

  7. Out of 21 subjects, 14 passed the two option location task and 8 passed each of the two versions of the two option contents tasks (for a total of 16 out of 42). Subjects also found the three option location task to be much easier than the three option contents tasks.

  8. Perner and Horn (2003) admit that they don’t have an explanation for this anomaly (p. 269).

  9. It has long been pointed out by anti-realists that we find widespread disagreement amongst professional philosophers, and yet we seem to find no discomfort or attempt to reconcile beliefs in Western philosophy’s 2700 year history. The same is true in the political sphere, or at any time when people are aware of disagreeing with someone else.

  10. I must admit, however, that as an anonymous reviewer points out this evidence is only suggestive and not decisive. Nonetheless, I do not find the reviewer’s examples convincing. For instance, it is suggested that agents can be conscious of a process which is not under conscious control, such as a knee-jerk reflex. The issue though is that although subjects can be aware of the outputs of these processes, they are not aware of the processing itself. For example, people are aware that they recognize faces and judge language strings as ungrammatical. However, subjects are unable to report about how they do it. In contrast, subjects in Fabricius et al. (2010) are not only aware of the predictions about where Maxi will look (and the judgments about what Maxi knows)—i.e., the outputs of PAR reasoning—they are also aware of the steps of the reasoning itself, and the process by which they arrive at those predictions and judgments.

  11. He also says in Chapter 5 that repeated experience is a cause of cognitive ease.

  12. I strongly disagree with this manner of speaking, because I don’t think a child using RR or PAR thinks or attributes anything about beliefs; but I’ll reluctantly adopt it throughout the rest of this paragraph for ease of explanation. However, if the PAR hypothesis is correct (and children at this stage aren’t reasoning about beliefs), then this provides another reason to reject the dissonance story.

  13. Of course, the concept used by children in the PAR stage of development is not the same concept of knowledge used by adults. The limited conceptions of perception and knowledge used in PAR is an important topic, but one that would take us too far astray from the main points of this paper.

  14. In other words, Rule A may exist simultaneously in adult cognition along with BR, along the lines of a Dual Systems model such as Kahneman (2011). This could be tested by using the “eye gaze” methodology developed for children under 4 years of age (Clements and Perner 1994; Garnham and Perner 2001; Garnham and Ruffman 2001; Ruffman et al. 2001), in which they have passed two-option false belief tasks by showing unconscious anticipatory looking to the correct location. However, in order to know whether correct anticipatory looking in the false belief task indicates attribution of false beliefs or use of Rule A, the methodology needs to include a true belief task in which there is some interruption in the agent’s connection to the situation that is comparable to what occurs in the false belief task. The previous eye gaze studies have not included such true belief tasks.

  15. On modularity and psychology, see Fodor (1983) and Barrett and Kurzban (2006).

  16. Although the sketch of a dual-systems account presented here is superficially similar to the one proposed by Fiebich (2014), they are importantly different for at least four reasons: According to my proposal (but not Fiebich’s) (1) Rule A and PAR are distinct psychological mechanisms, (2) when using a conscious process as in a psychological test such as the verbal false belief task, subjects will use the effortful, deliberative reasoning process, (3) this latter process is different depending upon which stage of theory of mind development a subject is in—RR, PAR, or BR, and (4) the features that might make a BR subject revert to Rule A would be perhaps time constraints or anticipatory looking procedures, but not features of a particular task. Thus, 3-year-olds fail the 2-location false belief task when tested using a verbal report method (by using RR), but pass using an AL measure (by using Rule A).

  17. The PAR/ Rule A hypothesis also seems to be consistent with the general considerations raised by De Bruin and Newen (2014), although I am unsure about the specifics of their Association Module/ Operating System account (but see footnote 21 below).

  18. On the hypothesis that ToM ability is the result of a module, see Baron-Cohen (1995), Carruthers (2013) and Leslie (1994). The details of Baron-Cohen’s view are unimportant for our purposes, but it should perhaps be noted that his model includes four separate mindreading components, some of which (e.g., the Shared Attention Mechanism) are impaired in ASD while others (such as the Intentionality Detector) remain intact (Baron-Cohen 1995).

  19. Neurotypical adults did demonstrate anticipatory looking toward the correct location during the false belief task (which they also verbally passed), but a true belief task was not used in this study.

  20. See Perner and Ruffman (2005) for one attempt to salvage the Traditional View in light of the infant studies; I argue against this putative explanation in an unpublished manuscript.

  21. Insofar as the Rule A conjecture and Carey’s explanation are correct, that would seem to be evidence against Georgieff and Jeannerod (1998)’s shared representation hypothesis that perception systems and action systems utilize the same representational space. Because of this, the PAR Hypothesis dual-systems account may be incompatible with the specifics of De Bruin and Newen (2014)’s proposal (see e.g. p. 307).

  22. As an anonymous reviewer points out, Fiebich (2014) proposes an empirical test of her Fluency hypothesis (pp. 941–942). I believe that the reasoning in Section 4 of this paper is sufficient to show that the hypothesis is implausible, but even if one disagrees with that, there are other problems with the first of Fiebich’s experimental paradigms. First she suggests testing whether 4- and 5-year-olds experience more cognitive strain in the 2-location false belief task than in the true belief task of Fabricius et al. (2010). The difficulty here is that, first, I’m not sure that there are accepted objective signals of cognitive strain in general, much less in children. Second, even if we did find more cognitive strain in the false belief task, that would not in any way count as evidence against the PAR hypothesis.

    She also suggests adding variables that induce cognitive strain to the true belief task in order to test whether that allows 4- and 5-year-olds to pass. Again, even if this test confirmed Fiebich’s hypothesis I’m not sure that would count as evidence against PAR, but I do accept that it would perhaps lend support to the fluency hypothesis, if the internal inconsistencies of the theory could somehow be resolved. If we indeed found that making a task more difficult improved the performance of 4- and 5-year-olds, then that would seem to at least be evidence for a 2-systems account of some kind or other, and could perhaps be some evidence against the Rule A 2-systems proposal of Hedger and Fabricius (2011).

  23. Thanks to Bill Fabricius, Bob Van Gulick, and two anonymous referees for comments on earlier drafts of this paper. Thanks also to Jesse Prinz for a helpful conversation about this project.

References

  • Apperly, I. A., & Butterfill, S. A. (2009). Do humans have two systems to track beliefs and belief-like states? Psychological Review, 116, 953–970.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Apperly, I. A., Riggs, K. J., Simpson, A., Chiavarino, C., & Samson, D. (2006). Is belief reasoning automatic? Psychological Science, 17, 841–844.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baillargeon, R., Scott, R. M., & He, Z. (2010). False belief understanding in infants. Trends in Cognitive Science, 14, 110–118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baron-Cohen, S. (1989a). Perceptual role-taking and protodeclaritive pointing in autism. British Journal of Developmental Psychology, 7, 113–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baron-Cohen, S. (1989b). Are autistic children behaviorists? An examination of their mental-physical and appearance-reality distinctions. Journal of Autism and Developmental Disorders, 19, 579–600.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baron-Cohen, S. (1992). Out of sight or out of mind: another look at deception in autism. Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, 33, 1141–1155.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baron-Cohen, S. (1995). Mindblindness: An essay on autism and theory of mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baron-Cohen, S., Leslie, A., & Frith, U. (1985). Does the autistic child have a theory of mind? Cognition, 21, 37–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barrett, H. C., & Kurzban, R. (2006). Modularity in cognition: framing the debate. Psychological Review, 113, 628–647.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, J. (1978). Some remarks about concepts. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 1, 557–560.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berthier, N. E., DeBlois, S., Poirer, C. R., Novak, M. A., & Clifton, R. K. (2000). Where’s the ball? Two- and three-year-olds reason about unseen events. Developmental Psychology, 36, 394–401.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buttelmann, D., Carpenter, M., & Tomasello, M. (2009). Eighteen-month-old infants show false belief understanding in an active helping paradigm. Cognition, 112, 337–342.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carey, S. (2009). The origin of concepts. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. (2013). Mindreading in infancy. Mind & Language, 28, 141–172.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1965). Aspects of the theory of syntax. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clements, W. A., & Perner, J. (1994). Implicit understanding of belief. Cognitive Development, 9, 377–395.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1975). Inquiries into truth and interpretation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Bruin, L. C., & Newen, A. (2014). The developmental paradox of false belief understanding: a dual-system solution. Synthese, 191, 297–320.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1978). Beliefs about beliefs. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 1, 568–570.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fabricius, W. V., & Imbens-Bailey, A. L. (2000). False beliefs about false beliefs. In P. Mitchell & K. Riggs (Eds.), Children’s reasoning about the mind (pp. 267–280). Hove: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fabricius, W. V., & Khalil, S. L. (2003). False beliefs or false positives? Limits on children’s understanding of mental representation. Journal of Cognition and Development, 4, 239–262.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fabricius, W. V., Boyer, T., Weimer, A. A., & Carroll, K. (2010). True or false: do five-year-olds understand belief? Developmental Psychology, 46, 1402–1416.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Festinger, L. (1957). A theory of cognitive dissonance. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fiebich, A. (2014). Mindreading with ease? Fluency and belief reasoning in 4- to 5-year-olds. Synthese, 191, 929–944.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Flavell, J. H., Flavell, E. R., & Green, F. L. (1983). Development of the appearance-reality distinction. Cognitive Psychology, 15, 85–120.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1983). The modularity of mind. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1992). A theory of the child’s theory of mind. Cognition, 44, 283–296.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, O., Griffen, R., Brownell, H., & Winner, E. (2003). Problems with the seeing = knowing rule. Developmental Science, 6, 505–513.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garnham, W. A., & Perner, J. (2001). Actions really do speak louder than words—but only implicitly: young children’s understanding of false belief in action. British Journal of Developmental Psychology, 19, 413–432.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garnham, W. A., & Ruffman, T. (2001). Doesn’t see, doesn’t know: is anticipatory looking really related to understanding of belief? Developmental Science, 4, 94–100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Georgieff, N., & Jeannerod, M. (1998). Beyond consciousness of external reality: a “Who” system for consciousness and action and self-consciousness. Consciousness and Cognition, 7, 465–487.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, A., & Wellman, H. (1992). Why the child’s theory of mind really is a theory. Mind & Language, 7, 145–171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hare, B., Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (2001). Do chimpanzees know what conspecifics know? Animal Behaviour, 61, 139–151.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1978). Studying the chimpanzee’s theory of mind. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 1, 576–77.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • He, Z., Bolz, M., & Baillargeon, R. (2011). False-belief understanding in 2.5-year-olds: evidence from violation-of expectation change-of-location and unexpected-contents tasks. Developmental Science, 14, 292–305.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hedger, J. A., & Fabricius, W. V. (2011). True belief belies false belief: recent findings of competence in infants and limitations in 5-year-olds, and implications for theory of mind development. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 2, 429–447.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hogrefe, G. J., Wimmer, H., & Perner, J. (1986). Ignorance versus false belief: a developmental lag in attributing epistemic states. Child Development, 57, 567–582.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hood, B., Carey, S., & Prasada, S. (2000). Predicting the outcomes of physical events: two-year-olds fail to reveal knowledge of solidity and support. Child Development, 71, 1540–1554.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking, fast and slow. London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaminski, J., Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (2008). Chimpanzees know what others know, but not what they believe. Cognition, 109, 224–234.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keysar, B., Lin, S., & Barr, D. J. (2003). Limits on theory of mind use in adults. Cognition, 89, 25–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lagattuta, K. H., Sayfan, L., & Blattman, A. J. (2010). Forgetting common ground: six- to seven-year-olds have an overinterpretive theory of mind. Developmental Psychology, 46, 1417–1432.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leekam, S., Baron-Cohen, S., Perrett, D., Milders, M., & Brown, S. (1997). Eye-direction detection: a dissociation between geometric and joint attention skills in autism. British Journal of Developmental Psychology, 15, 77–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leslie, A. M. (1987). Pretense and representation: the origins of ‘theory of mind.’. Psychological Review, 94, 412–426.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leslie, A. M. (1994). ToMM, ToBy, and agency: core architecture and domain specificity. In L. Hirschfeld & S. Gelman (Eds.), Mapping the mind: Domain specificity in cognition and culture. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leslie, A. M. (2005). Developmental parallels in understanding minds and bodies. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 9, 459–462.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lin, S., Keysar, B., & Epley, N. (2010). Refelexively mindblind: using theory of mind to interpret behavior requires effortful attention. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 46, 551–556.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Onishi, K. H., & Baillargeon, R. (2005). Do 15-month-old infants understand false beliefs? Science, 308, 255–258.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Perner, J. (1988). Developing semantics for theories of mind: From propositional attitudes to mental representation. In J. W. Astington, P. L. Harris, & D. R. Olson (Eds.), Developing theories of mind (pp. 141–172). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perner, J. (1991). Understanding the representational mind. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perner, J., & Horn, R. (2003). Knowledge or false negatives: do children of 4 to 5 years simulate belief with “not knowing = getting it wrong?”. Journal of Cognition and Development, 4, 263–273.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Perner, J., & Ruffman, T. (2005). Infants’ insight into the mind: how deep? Science, 308, 214–216.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Perner, J., Frith, U., Leslie, A., & Leekam, S. (1989). Exploration of the autistic child’s theory of mind: knowledge, belief, and communication. Child Development, 60, 689–700.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pillow, B. H. (1989). Early understanding of perception as a source of knowledge. Journal of Experimental Child Psychology, 47, 116–129.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pratt, C., & Bryant, P. (1990). Young children understand that looking leads to knowing (so long as they are looking into a single barrel). Child Development, 61, 973–982.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn, Z. (1978). When is attribution of belief justified? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 1, 592–593.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roth, D., & Leslie, A. M. (1998). Solving belief problems: toward a task analysis. Cognition, 66, 1–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ruffman, T. (1996). Do children understand the mind by means of simulation or a theory? Evidence from their understanding of inference. Mind and Language, 11, 388–414.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ruffman, T., Garnham, W., Import, A., & Connelly, D. (2001). Does eye gaze indicate implicit knowledge of false belief? Charting transitions in knowledge. Journal of Experimental Child Psychology, 80, 201–224.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russo, N., Mottron, L., Burack, J. A., & Jemel, B. (2012). Parameters of semantic multisensory integration depend on timing and modality order among people on the autism spectrum: evidence from event-related potentials. Neuropsychologia, 50, 2131–2141.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saxe, R., Carey, S., & Kanwisher, N. (2004). Understanding other minds: linking developmental psychology and functional neuroimaging. Annual Review of Psychology, 55, 87–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scott, R. M., & Baillargeon, R. (2009). Which penguin is this? Attributing false beliefs about object identity at 18 months. Child Development, 80, 1172–1196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scott, R. M., Baillargeon, R., Song, H., & Leslie, A. M. (2010). Attributing false beliefs about non-obvious properties at 18 months. Cognitive Psychology, 61, 366–395.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Senju, A., Southgate, V., White, S., & Frith, U. (2009). Mindblind eyes: an absence of spontaneous theory of mind in asperger syndrome. Science, 325, 883–885.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Song, H., & Baillargeon, R. (2008). Infants’ reasoning about others’ false perceptions. Developmental Psychology, 44, 1789–1795.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Southgate, V. (2014). Early manifestations of mind reading. In S. Baron-Cohen, H. Tager-Flusberg & M. Lombardo (Eds.), Understanding Other Minds, 3rd Edition. Oxford University Press.

  • Southgate, V., Chevallier, C., & Csibra, G. (2010). Seventeen-month-olds appeal to false beliefs to interpret others‘referential communication. Developmental Science, 13, 907–912.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spelke, E. S., Breilinger, K., Macomber, J., & Jacobsen, K. (1992). Origins of knowledge. Psychological Review, 99, 605–632.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Surian, L., Caldi, S., & Sperber, D. (2007). Attribution of beliefs by 13-month-old infants. Psychological Science, 18, 580–586.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wellman, H. M., Cross, D., & Watson, J. (2001). Meta-analysis of theory-of-mind development: the truth about false belief. Child Development, 72, 655–684.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wellman, H. M., Lane, J. D., LaBounty, J., & Olson, S. L. (2011). Observant, nonaggressive temperament predicts theory of mind development. Developmental Science, 14(2), 319–326.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wimmer, H., & Perner, J. (1983). Beliefs about beliefs: representation and constraining function of wrong beliefs in young children’s understanding of deception. Cognition, 13, 103–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Joseph A. Hedger.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Hedger, J.A. Perceptual access reasoning: developmental stage or system 1 heuristic?. Phenom Cogn Sci 15, 207–226 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-015-9412-4

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-015-9412-4

Keywords

Navigation