Skip to main content
Log in

What guides pretence? Towards the interactive and the narrative approaches

  • Published:
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper will explore one aspect of the relationship between pretence and narratives. I look at proposals about how scripts play guiding roles in our pretend play practices. I then examine the views that mental representations are needed to guide pretend play, reviewing two importantly different pictures of mental guiders: the Propositional Account and the Model Account. Both accounts are individualistic and internalistic; the former makes use of language-like representations, the latter makes use of models, maps and images. The paper will discuss some worries with the notion of mental guiders, and offer some positive suggestions about what else might be playing the guiding role in pretence. I propose that environmental affordances and socially scaffolded engagements provide the basis of pretence guiders (the Interactive Account), and suggest that engagement in narrative practices further frames and allows elaborations of acts of pretend play (the Narrative Account). I take first steps in developing a new embodied, enactive and intersubjective understanding of pretence, showing why it is a viable alternative to the mental representational accounts of pretence.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Mental representations are typically understood as objects with semantic properties (content, reference, truth-conditions, truth-value, etc.), which fulfill some conditions of satisfaction (truth, accuracy, etc.) and thereby determine the meaning of a thought. In order to explain pretence, mental representations with contents that fulfill some condition of satisfaction are usually invoked.

  2. Van Leeuwen’s proposal of imagination as guider is the most recent and enactive of the available accounts. He argues against Nichols and Stich’s (2003) conditional belief account, as well as against replacement theories of Velleman 2000; Currie and Ravenscroft 2002 and Doggett and Egan 2007, which hold that “imaginings take two forms – one form corresponding to beliefs and one to desires – and they effectively replace beliefs and desires in producing actions” (61). The replacement theories are not discussed further in this paper.

  3. Aside actual scripts, whether behaviours and norms count as a genuine scripts per se depends on one’s notion of a ‘script’; they can, however, be thought of as guiders in accordance with the minimal description given earlier in the paper.

  4. Of course, the same point can be made about following physical scripts like screenplays; even a command “and now sight” does not give one all the details of how to act out a sigh – the actor must already possess embodied skill of sighing, and the actor is guided further (e.g., by the director showing or describing further how to do it). However, invoking sub-personal structures like belief boxes to explain how one’s behaviour is guided from the ‘inside’ through internalized rules of behaviour demands these rules to be more specific.

  5. Thanks to the anonymous reviewer for this point.

  6. This section does not deal with the ‘forward model’ aspect of the Model Account due to space limitations. However, worries with AORs (constructs similar to forward models) have been further explicated by i.e. by Hutto (2013). Also, as mental images guide together with forward models, undermining the role of mental images undermines in extension the whole account.

  7. Possibly a simulation account could take care of this worry, but then the activity would be happening subpersonally and should not be compared to the act of imitating.

  8. As Davisdson already noted, to represent ‘imagistic contents’ cententfully demands ‘the gift of tongues’ (1985, 473).

  9. This problem is relevant to all accounts that introduce mental representations not just accounts of pretence (but it is relevant to them as well).

  10. F&S’s example of the external guider to pretending being a bird in flight is Tony’s friends pretending to be birds in flight. They say: “even if Tony’s action is guided exclusively by the behaviour of others (…), Tony can still be fully in control of his pretense, as well as fully accountable for it”, for his pretence to count as genuine action” (312).

  11. Mimicry is a likely first step towards individual pretence due to its developmental priority (Stern 1985; Tomasello 1999).

  12. De Jaegher and Di Paolo (2007) discuss further the case of charades in the context of Participatory Sense Making, a theory about how we make sense of others through coordinated interaction.

  13. Social referencing is a very important factor in shared pretence, as children constantly check whether the other participants or spectators are aware of the situation being just a game. Meyers in Mitchell (2002) notices that “as long as other players tolerate (the pretender’s) cryptic and unaccountable behaviour, [the pretender] need not explain herself or respond to language and so carry on in an idiosyncratic way” (159).

  14. There is strong conviction that such non-representational accounts cannot handle the notion of absence or abstraction. The intuition is that in the absence of a ‘bird in flight’ to guide movements, one is guided by its image that has to be created in the absence of the bird in flight, or recreated from memory. However, the sensorimotor account of presence in absence (Noë 2004) or phenomenological account of presence of absence (Sartre 1957) can shed light on alternative accounts of absence, just as the novel, developing, non-representational account of absence (Degenaar and Myin 2014) and memory (Myin and Zahidi 2013) do. On their account, memory is extensive, involving both organism and environment to begin with.

  15. This is something like the ‘initial premise’, but not intellectualized as a mental representation.

  16. Even Strawson (2004), who criticises narratives, does not deny that they exist as social practices.

References

  • Cappuccio, M., & Wheeler, M. (2012). Ground-Level Intelligence: Action-Oriented Representations and the Dynamics of the Background. In Z. Radman (Ed.), Knowing Without Thinking: The Background in Philosophy of Mind (pp. 13–36). Basingstoke: Palgrave.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chemero, A. (2009). Radical Embodied Cognitive Science. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Currie, G. (2006). Rationality, decentring, and the evidence for pretence in non-human animals. In S. Hurley & M. Nudds (Eds.), Rational Animals? Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Currie, G., & Ravenscroft, I. (2002). Recreative Minds: Imagination in Philosophy and Psychology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1985). Rational Animals. Actions and Events: Perspectives on the Philosophy of Donald Davidson, Lepore and MacLaughlin (eds.). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

  • De Jaegher, H., & Di Paolo, E. (2007). Participatory sense-making: an inactive approach to social cognition. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 6(4), 485–507.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Degenaar, J. & Myin, E. (2014). Representation-hunger reconsidered. Synthese.

  • Doggett, T., & Egan, A. (2007). Wanting things You Don’t want: the case for an imaginative analogue of desire. Philosophers’ Imprint, 7(9), 1–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Funkhouser, E., & Spaulding, S. (2009). Imagination and other scripts. Philosophical Studies, 143, 291–314.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2013). An education in narratives. Educational Philosophy and Theory. doi:10.1080/00131857.2013.779213.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S., & Miyahara, K. (2012). Neo-pragmatism and enactive intentionality. In J. Schulkin (Ed.), Action, Perception and the Brain (pp. 117–46). Basingstoke: Palgrave-Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, J. J. (1979). The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris, P. L. (1994). Understanding pretense. In C. Lewis & P. Mitchell (Eds.), Children’s early understanding of mind: origins and development (pp. 235–259). Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris, P.L. & Kavanaugh, R.D. (1993). Young children’s understanding of pretense. Monographs of the Society for Research in Child Development 58, No. 1.

  • Hutto, D. D. (2008). Folk Psychological Narratives: The sociocultural basis of understanding reasons. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D. (2012). Exposing the background: Deep and local. In Z. Radman (Ed.), Knowing without thinking: The background in philosophy of mind (pp. 37–56). Palgrave Macmillan: Basingstoke.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D. (2013). Exorcising action oriented representations: ridding cognitive science of its nazgûl. Adaptive Behaviour, 21(1), 142–150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D. D., & Myin, E. (2013). Radicalizing Enactivism: Basic Minds without Content. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Langland-Hassan, P. (2014). What is to pretend. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly.

  • Leslie, A. (1987). Pretense and representation: the origins of “theory of mind.”. Psychological Review, 94, 412–426.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, C., & Mitchell, P. (1994). Children’s early understanding of mind: Origins and Development. Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Liao, S., & Gendler, T. (2011). Pretence and Imagination. Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Cognitive Science, 2(1), 79–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lillard, A. (1994). Making sense of pretense. In C. Lewis and P. Mitchell, p. 211–234.

  • Mitchell, R.W. (Ed.) (2002). Pretending and Imagination in Animals and Children. Cambridge University Press.

  • Myin, E. & Zahidi, K. (2013). The Extent of Memory: From Extended to Extensive Mind. Proceedings of 36th Wittgenstein Conference, Mind, Language and Action.

  • Nichols, S., & Stich, S. (2000). A cognitive theory of pretense. Cognition, 74, 115–147.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S., & Stich, S. (2003). Mindreading: An Integrated Account of Pretence, Self-Awareness and Understanding of Other Minds. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. (2004). Action in Perception. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Regan, J. K., & Noë, A. (2001). A sensorimotor account of vision and visual consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 24(5), 939–1031.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Perner, J. (1991). Understanding the representational mind. MIT Press.

  • Piaget, J. (1962). Play, dreams, and imitation in childhood. Translated by C. Gattegno and F. M. Hodgson. New York: Norton.

  • Rakoczy, H., Tomasello, M., & Striano, T. (2005). How children turn objects into symbols: A cultural learning account. In L. Namy (Ed.), Symbol Use and Symbol Representation (pp. 67–97). New York: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rucinska, Z. (2014). Basic pretending as sensorimotor engagement? contemporary sensorimotor theory, studies in applied philosophy. Epistemology and Rational Ethics, 15(2014), 175–187.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (1949). The Concept of Mind. London: Hutchinson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sainsbury, R. M. (2009). Fiction and Fictionalism. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, J.P. (1957). Being and Nothingness. An Essay on Phenomenological Ontology. Translated and with an Introduction by Hazel E. Barnes. London; printed in USA.

  • Stern, D. N. (1985). The Interpersonal World of the Infant. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, G. (2004). Against narrativity. Ratio XVII, 4, 428–430.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M. (1999). The Cultural Origins of Human Cognition. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Leeuwen, N. (2011). Imagination is where the action is. The Journal of Philosophy, 108(2), 55–77.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Velleman, J. D. (2000). The Possibility of Practical Reasoning. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vygotsky, L.S. (1987). Thinking and speech (N. Minick, Trans.). In R.W. Rieber & A.S. Carton (Eds.), The collected works of L.S. Vygotsky: Vol. 1. Problems of general psychology (pp. 39–285). New York: Plenum Press. (Original work published 1934).

Download references

Acknowledgments

This work was funded by the Marie-Curie Initial Training Network TESIS: Towards an Embodied Science of InterSubjectivity (FP7-PEOPLE-2010-ITN, 264828). I would like to thank Dan Hutto, Sam Coleman, Shaun Gallagher, Erik Myin, Thomas Fuchs, fellows from the TESIS project, colleagues from the University of Hertfordshire as well as Leon de Bruin and the anonymous reviewers for the support received in relation to the work presented in the paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Zuzanna Rucińska.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Rucińska, Z. What guides pretence? Towards the interactive and the narrative approaches. Phenom Cogn Sci 15, 117–133 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-014-9381-z

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-014-9381-z

Keywords

Navigation