Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Towards a Cognitive Neuroscience of Intentionality

  • Published:
Minds and Machines Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We situate the debate on intentionality within the rise of cognitive neuroscience and argue that cognitive neuroscience can explain intentionality. We discuss the explanatory significance of ascribing intentionality to representations. At first, we focus on views that attempt to render such ascriptions naturalistic by construing them in a deflationary or merely pragmatic way. We then contrast these views with staunchly realist views that attempt to naturalize intentionality by developing theories of content for representations in terms of information and biological function. We echo several other philosophers by arguing that these theories over-generalize unless they are constrained by a theory of the functional role of representational vehicles. This leads to a discussion of the functional roles of representations, and how representations might be realized in the brain. We argue that there’s work to be done to identify a distinctively mental kind of representation. We close by sketching a way forward for the project of naturalizing intentionality. This will not be achieved simply by ascribing the content of mental states to generic neural representations, but by identifying specific neural representations that explain the puzzling intentional properties of mental states.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This strategy underlies a great deal of research in philosophy of mind throughout the late twentieth century; Fodor (1987) makes the strategy explicit.

  2. For influential philosophical discussions of the mechanistic explanatory paradigm that is widely regarded as the dominant mode of explanation throughout the life sciences, see Bechtel and Richardson (2010), Machamer et al. (2000). For a discussion of how attempts to explain life fit within the mechanistic paradigm, see Bechtel (2011).

  3. For arguments that computational cognitive neuroscience provides psychological explanations that fit within the mechanistic paradigm, see Bechtel (2008), Kaplan (2011), Piccinini and Craver (2011), Boone and Piccinini (2016).

  4. The distinction here echoes the distinction between ‘content’ and ‘state’ views of non-conceptual content (Heck 2000).

References

  • Amit, D. (1989). Modelling brain function: The world of attractor neural networks. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Anscombe, E. (1957). Intention. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bartels, A. (2006). Defending the structural concept of representation. Theoria, 21(55), 7–19.

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. (1998). Representations and cognitive explanations: Assessing the dynamicist’s challenge in cognitive science. Cognitive Science, 22(3), 295–318.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. (2008). Mental mechanisms. New York: Taylor and Francis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. (2011). Mechanism and biological explanation. Philosophy of Science, 78(4), 533–557.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., & Richardson, R. (2010). Discovering complexity: Decomposition and localization as strategies in scientific research. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blakemore, R., & Frankel, R. (1981). Magnetic navigation in bacteria. Scientific American, 6, 58–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (1986). Advertisement for a semantics for psychology. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 10, 615–678.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boone, W., & Piccinini, G. (2016). The cognitive neuroscience revolution. Synthese, 193(5), 1509–1534.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bourget, D., and Mendelovici, A. (2017). Phenomenal intentionality. In Edward N. Zalta (ed.) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2017 Edition), forthcoming https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2017/entries/phenomenal-intentionality/.

  • Brentano, F. (1874 [1995]). Psychology from an empirical standpoint. London: Routledge.

  • Brooks, R. (1991). Intelligence without representation. Artificial Intelligence, 47(1–3), 139–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Caston, V. (2008). Intentionality in ancient philosophy. In E. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2008 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2008/entries/intentionality-ancient/.

  • Chisholm, R. (1955). Sentences about believing. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 56, 125–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chisholm, R. (1957). Perceiving: A philosophical study. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1995). Language and nature. Mind, 104, 1–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. S., & Sejnowski, T. J. (1992). The computational brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A., & Toribio, J. (1994). Doing without representing? Synthese, 101(3), 401–431.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craik, K. (1943). The nature of explanation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, R. (1983). The nature of psychological explanation. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, R. (1989). Meaning and mental representation. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, R. (1996). Representations, targets, and attitudes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1980). Essays on actions and events. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (1978). Artificial intelligence as philosophy and as psychology. In his ‘Brainstorms’ (pp. 109–126). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. (1987). The intentional stance. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Denève, S., Duhamel, J.-R., & Pouget, A. (2007). Optimal sensorimotor integration in recurrent cortical networks: A neural implementation of kalman filters. Journal of Neuroscience, 27(21), 5744–5756.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1981). Knowledge and the flow of information. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1986). Misrepresentation. In R. Bogdan (Ed.), Form, content, and function (pp. 157–173). Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1988). Explaining behavior: Reasons in a world of causes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Egan, F. (2014). How to think about mental content. Philosophical Studies, 170(1), 115–135.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Eliasmith, C., & Anderson, C. (2003). Neural engineering: Computation, Representation, and dynamics in neurobiological systems. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1975). The language of thought. New York, NY: Crowell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1987). Psychosemantics: The problem of meaning in the philosophy of mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1990). A theory of content and other essays. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallistel, C. (1990). Representations in animal cognition: An introduction. Cognition, 37(1–2), 1–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallistel, C. (2008). Learning and representation. In J. Byrne (Ed.), Learning and memory: A comprehensive reference (pp. 227–242). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Grice, P. (1957). Meaning. Philosophical Review, 66, 377–388.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grush, R. (2003). In defense of some ‘Cartesian’ assumptions concerning the brain and its operation. Biology and Philosophy, 18(1), 53–93.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grush, R. (2004). The emulation theory of representation: Motor control, imagery, and perception. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 27(3), 377–396.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grush, R. (2008). Representation reconsidered by William M. Ramsey, Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews.

  • Harman, G. (1970). Sellars’ semantics. The Philosophical Review, 79(3), 404–419.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1973). Thought. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1987). (Non-solipsistic) conceptual role semantics. In E. Lepore (Ed.), New directions in semantics. London: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. (1988). Wide functionalism. In S. Schiffer & S. Steele (Eds.), Cognition and representation. Boulder: Westview.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hebb, D. (1949). The organization of behavior: A neuropsychological theory. New York, NY: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heck, R. (2000). Nonconceptual content and the ‘Space of Reasons’. Philosophical Review, 109(4), 483–523.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horgan, T., & Tienson, J. (2002). The intentionality of phenomenology and the phenomenology of intentionality. In D. Chalmers (Ed.), Philosophy of mind: Classical and contemporary readings (pp. 520–933). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutto, D., & Myin, E. (2013). Radicalizing enactivism. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Isaac, A. (2013). Objective similarity and mental representation. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 91(4), 683–704.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jacob, P. (1997). What minds can do: Intentionality in a non-intentional world. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jacob, P., (2014). “Intentionality”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2014 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2014/entries/intentionality/.

  • Kaplan, D. (2011). Explanation and description in computational neuroscience. Synthese, 183(3), 339–373.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kriegel, U. (Ed.). (2013). Phenomenal intentionality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kriegel, U. (2016). Brentano’s mature theory of intentionality. Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy, 4(2), 1–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loar, B. (1981). Mind and meaning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loar, B. (2003). Phenomenal intentionality as the basis of mental content. In M. Hahn & B. Ramberg (Eds.), Reflections and replies: Essays on the philosophy of Tyler Burge (pp. 229–258). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, J. (1824 [1696]). The works of John Locke (Vol. 3, 12th Ed.). Rivington: London.

  • Machamer, P., et al. (2000). Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 67(1), 1–25.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • McCulloch, W., & Pitts, W. (1943). A logical calculus of the ideas immanent in nervous activity. Bulletin of Mathematical Biophysics, 5, 115–133.

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. (1984). Language, thought, and other biological categories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. (1989). Biosemantics. The Journal of Philosophy, 86(6), 281–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. (1993). White queen psychology and other essays for Alice. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. (2000). Naturalizing intentionality. The Proceedings of the Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy, 9, 83–90.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, A. (2014). Representations gone mental. Synthese, 191(2), 213–244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Brien, G., & Opie, J. (2004). Notes toward a structuralist theory of mental representation. In H. Clapin, P. Staines, & P. Slezac (Eds.), Representation in mind (pp. 1–20). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke, C. (1992). A study of concepts. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Piccinini, G. (2004). The first computational theory of mind and brain: A close look at McMulloch and Pitts’s ‘Calculus of Ideas Immanent in Nervous Activity’. Synthese, 141(2), 175–215.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Piccinini, G. (forthcoming). Nonnatural mental representation. In K. Dolega, T. Schlicht, J. Smortchkova (Eds.), What are mental representations? Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Piccinini, G., & Craver, C. (2011). Integrating psychology and neuroscience: Functional analyses as mechanism sketches. Synthese, 183(3), 283–311.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pietroski, P. (1992). Intentionality and teleological error. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 73(3), 267–282.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pitt, D. (2017). “Mental Representation”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2017 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), forthcoming https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2017/entries/mental-representation/.

  • Pylyshyn, Z. (1984). Computation and cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. (1960). Word and object. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey, W. (2007). Representation reconsidered. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey, W. (2016). Untangling two questions about mental representation. New Ideas in Psychology, 40, 3–12.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rolls, E. (2007). Memory, attention, and decision-making: A unifying computational neuroscience approach. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ryder, R. (2004). SINBAD neurosemantics: A theory of mental representation. Mind and Language, 19(2), 211–240.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Samsonovich, A., & McNaughton, B. (1997). Path Integration and cognitive mapping in a continuous attractor neural network model. Journal of Neuroscience, 17(15), 5900–5920.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. (1983). Intentionality: An essay in the philosophy of mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W. (1954). Some reflections on language games. Philosophy of Science, 21, 204–228.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W. (1956). Empiricism and the philosophy of mind. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 1(19), 253–329.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seung, S. (1998). Continuous attractors and oculomotor control. Neural Networks, 11(7–8), 1253–1258.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shagrir, O. (2012). Structural representations and the brain. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 63(3), 519–545.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shannon, C. (1948). A mathematical theory of communication. The Bell System Technical Journal, 27(7), 379–423.

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Shepard, R., & Chipman, S. (1970). Second-order isomorphism of internal representations: Shapes of states. Cognitive Psychology, 1(1), 1–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sprevak, M. (2011). Review of Representation Reconsidered by William Ramsey. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62, 669–675.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. (1995). Basic minds. Philosophical Perspectives, 9, 251–270.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stich, S. (1983). From folk psychology to cognitive science: The case against belief. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Swoyer, C. (1991). Structural representation and surrogative reasoning. Synthese, 87(3), 449.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Turing, A. (1936). On computable numbers, with an application to the Entscheidungsproblem. Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society, 42(2), 230–265.

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Tye, M. (1995). Ten problems of consciousness: A representational theory of the phenomenal mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Gelder, T. (1995). What might cognition be, if not computation. The Journal of Philosophy, 92(7), 345–381.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wang, X. (2001). Synaptic reverberation underlying mnemonic persistent activity. Trends in Neurosciences, 24(8), 455–463.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Watson, J. (1913). Psychology as the behaviorist views it. Psychological Review, 20(2), 158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wolpert, D., et al. (2003). A unifying computational framework for motor control and social interaction. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 358(1431), 593–602.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thanks to Anne Jacobson, Jonathan Kaplan, Nelson Mauro Maldonado, Marcin Miłkowski, Alessio Plebe, Michael Schmitz, Leonardo Wykrota, and two anonymous referees for helpful comments. This material is partially based upon work supported by the National Science Foundation under Grant No. SES-1654982.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Gualtiero Piccinini.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Morgan, A., Piccinini, G. Towards a Cognitive Neuroscience of Intentionality. Minds & Machines 28, 119–139 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11023-017-9437-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11023-017-9437-2

Keywords

Navigation