Advertisement

Minds and Machines

, Volume 28, Issue 1, pp 119–139 | Cite as

Towards a Cognitive Neuroscience of Intentionality

Article

Abstract

We situate the debate on intentionality within the rise of cognitive neuroscience and argue that cognitive neuroscience can explain intentionality. We discuss the explanatory significance of ascribing intentionality to representations. At first, we focus on views that attempt to render such ascriptions naturalistic by construing them in a deflationary or merely pragmatic way. We then contrast these views with staunchly realist views that attempt to naturalize intentionality by developing theories of content for representations in terms of information and biological function. We echo several other philosophers by arguing that these theories over-generalize unless they are constrained by a theory of the functional role of representational vehicles. This leads to a discussion of the functional roles of representations, and how representations might be realized in the brain. We argue that there’s work to be done to identify a distinctively mental kind of representation. We close by sketching a way forward for the project of naturalizing intentionality. This will not be achieved simply by ascribing the content of mental states to generic neural representations, but by identifying specific neural representations that explain the puzzling intentional properties of mental states.

Keywords

Intentionality Representation Cognitive neuroscience Mechanisms 

Notes

Acknowledgements

Thanks to Anne Jacobson, Jonathan Kaplan, Nelson Mauro Maldonado, Marcin Miłkowski, Alessio Plebe, Michael Schmitz, Leonardo Wykrota, and two anonymous referees for helpful comments. This material is partially based upon work supported by the National Science Foundation under Grant No. SES-1654982.

References

  1. Amit, D. (1989). Modelling brain function: The world of attractor neural networks. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefMATHGoogle Scholar
  2. Anscombe, E. (1957). Intention. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
  3. Bartels, A. (2006). Defending the structural concept of representation. Theoria, 21(55), 7–19.MathSciNetMATHGoogle Scholar
  4. Bechtel, W. (1998). Representations and cognitive explanations: Assessing the dynamicist’s challenge in cognitive science. Cognitive Science, 22(3), 295–318.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Bechtel, W. (2008). Mental mechanisms. New York: Taylor and Francis.Google Scholar
  6. Bechtel, W. (2011). Mechanism and biological explanation. Philosophy of Science, 78(4), 533–557.MathSciNetCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Bechtel, W., & Richardson, R. (2010). Discovering complexity: Decomposition and localization as strategies in scientific research. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  8. Blakemore, R., & Frankel, R. (1981). Magnetic navigation in bacteria. Scientific American, 6, 58–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Block, N. (1986). Advertisement for a semantics for psychology. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 10, 615–678.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Boone, W., & Piccinini, G. (2016). The cognitive neuroscience revolution. Synthese, 193(5), 1509–1534.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Bourget, D., and Mendelovici, A. (2017). Phenomenal intentionality. In Edward N. Zalta (ed.) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2017 Edition), forthcoming https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2017/entries/phenomenal-intentionality/.
  12. Brentano, F. (1874 [1995]). Psychology from an empirical standpoint. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  13. Brooks, R. (1991). Intelligence without representation. Artificial Intelligence, 47(1–3), 139–159.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Caston, V. (2008). Intentionality in ancient philosophy. In E. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2008 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2008/entries/intentionality-ancient/.
  15. Chisholm, R. (1955). Sentences about believing. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 56, 125–148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Chisholm, R. (1957). Perceiving: A philosophical study. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
  17. Chomsky, N. (1995). Language and nature. Mind, 104, 1–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Churchland, P. S., & Sejnowski, T. J. (1992). The computational brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.MATHGoogle Scholar
  19. Clark, A., & Toribio, J. (1994). Doing without representing? Synthese, 101(3), 401–431.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Craik, K. (1943). The nature of explanation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  21. Cummins, R. (1983). The nature of psychological explanation. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  22. Cummins, R. (1989). Meaning and mental representation. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  23. Cummins, R. (1996). Representations, targets, and attitudes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  24. Davidson, D. (1980). Essays on actions and events. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  25. Dennett, D. (1978). Artificial intelligence as philosophy and as psychology. In his ‘Brainstorms’ (pp. 109–126). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  26. Dennett, D. (1987). The intentional stance. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  27. Denève, S., Duhamel, J.-R., & Pouget, A. (2007). Optimal sensorimotor integration in recurrent cortical networks: A neural implementation of kalman filters. Journal of Neuroscience, 27(21), 5744–5756.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Dretske, F. (1981). Knowledge and the flow of information. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.MATHGoogle Scholar
  29. Dretske, F. (1986). Misrepresentation. In R. Bogdan (Ed.), Form, content, and function (pp. 157–173). Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
  30. Dretske, F. (1988). Explaining behavior: Reasons in a world of causes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  31. Egan, F. (2014). How to think about mental content. Philosophical Studies, 170(1), 115–135.MathSciNetCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Eliasmith, C., & Anderson, C. (2003). Neural engineering: Computation, Representation, and dynamics in neurobiological systems. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  33. Fodor, J. (1975). The language of thought. New York, NY: Crowell.Google Scholar
  34. Fodor, J. (1987). Psychosemantics: The problem of meaning in the philosophy of mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  35. Fodor, J. (1990). A theory of content and other essays. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  36. Gallistel, C. (1990). Representations in animal cognition: An introduction. Cognition, 37(1–2), 1–22.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Gallistel, C. (2008). Learning and representation. In J. Byrne (Ed.), Learning and memory: A comprehensive reference (pp. 227–242). Amsterdam: Elsevier.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Grice, P. (1957). Meaning. Philosophical Review, 66, 377–388.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Grush, R. (2003). In defense of some ‘Cartesian’ assumptions concerning the brain and its operation. Biology and Philosophy, 18(1), 53–93.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Grush, R. (2004). The emulation theory of representation: Motor control, imagery, and perception. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 27(3), 377–396.Google Scholar
  41. Grush, R. (2008). Representation reconsidered by William M. Ramsey, Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews.Google Scholar
  42. Harman, G. (1970). Sellars’ semantics. The Philosophical Review, 79(3), 404–419.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Harman, G. (1973). Thought. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  44. Harman, G. (1987). (Non-solipsistic) conceptual role semantics. In E. Lepore (Ed.), New directions in semantics. London: Academic Press.Google Scholar
  45. Harman, G. (1988). Wide functionalism. In S. Schiffer & S. Steele (Eds.), Cognition and representation. Boulder: Westview.Google Scholar
  46. Hebb, D. (1949). The organization of behavior: A neuropsychological theory. New York, NY: Wiley.Google Scholar
  47. Heck, R. (2000). Nonconceptual content and the ‘Space of Reasons’. Philosophical Review, 109(4), 483–523.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  48. Horgan, T., & Tienson, J. (2002). The intentionality of phenomenology and the phenomenology of intentionality. In D. Chalmers (Ed.), Philosophy of mind: Classical and contemporary readings (pp. 520–933). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  49. Hutto, D., & Myin, E. (2013). Radicalizing enactivism. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  50. Isaac, A. (2013). Objective similarity and mental representation. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 91(4), 683–704.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  51. Jacob, P. (1997). What minds can do: Intentionality in a non-intentional world. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  52. Jacob, P., (2014). “Intentionality”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2014 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2014/entries/intentionality/.
  53. Kaplan, D. (2011). Explanation and description in computational neuroscience. Synthese, 183(3), 339–373.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  54. Kriegel, U. (Ed.). (2013). Phenomenal intentionality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  55. Kriegel, U. (2016). Brentano’s mature theory of intentionality. Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy, 4(2), 1–15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  56. Loar, B. (1981). Mind and meaning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  57. Loar, B. (2003). Phenomenal intentionality as the basis of mental content. In M. Hahn & B. Ramberg (Eds.), Reflections and replies: Essays on the philosophy of Tyler Burge (pp. 229–258). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  58. Locke, J. (1824 [1696]). The works of John Locke (Vol. 3, 12th Ed.). Rivington: London.Google Scholar
  59. Machamer, P., et al. (2000). Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 67(1), 1–25.MathSciNetCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  60. McCulloch, W., & Pitts, W. (1943). A logical calculus of the ideas immanent in nervous activity. Bulletin of Mathematical Biophysics, 5, 115–133.MathSciNetCrossRefMATHGoogle Scholar
  61. Millikan, R. (1984). Language, thought, and other biological categories. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  62. Millikan, R. (1989). Biosemantics. The Journal of Philosophy, 86(6), 281–297.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  63. Millikan, R. (1993). White queen psychology and other essays for Alice. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  64. Millikan, R. (2000). Naturalizing intentionality. The Proceedings of the Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy, 9, 83–90.Google Scholar
  65. Morgan, A. (2014). Representations gone mental. Synthese, 191(2), 213–244.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  66. O’Brien, G., & Opie, J. (2004). Notes toward a structuralist theory of mental representation. In H. Clapin, P. Staines, & P. Slezac (Eds.), Representation in mind (pp. 1–20). Amsterdam: Elsevier.Google Scholar
  67. Peacocke, C. (1992). A study of concepts. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.MATHGoogle Scholar
  68. Piccinini, G. (2004). The first computational theory of mind and brain: A close look at McMulloch and Pitts’s ‘Calculus of Ideas Immanent in Nervous Activity’. Synthese, 141(2), 175–215.MathSciNetCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  69. Piccinini, G. (forthcoming). Nonnatural mental representation. In K. Dolega, T. Schlicht, J. Smortchkova (Eds.), What are mental representations? Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  70. Piccinini, G., & Craver, C. (2011). Integrating psychology and neuroscience: Functional analyses as mechanism sketches. Synthese, 183(3), 283–311.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  71. Pietroski, P. (1992). Intentionality and teleological error. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 73(3), 267–282.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  72. Pitt, D. (2017). “Mental Representation”, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2017 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), forthcoming https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2017/entries/mental-representation/.
  73. Pylyshyn, Z. (1984). Computation and cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  74. Quine, W. (1960). Word and object. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.MATHGoogle Scholar
  75. Ramsey, W. (2007). Representation reconsidered. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  76. Ramsey, W. (2016). Untangling two questions about mental representation. New Ideas in Psychology, 40, 3–12.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  77. Rolls, E. (2007). Memory, attention, and decision-making: A unifying computational neuroscience approach. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  78. Ryder, R. (2004). SINBAD neurosemantics: A theory of mental representation. Mind and Language, 19(2), 211–240.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  79. Samsonovich, A., & McNaughton, B. (1997). Path Integration and cognitive mapping in a continuous attractor neural network model. Journal of Neuroscience, 17(15), 5900–5920.Google Scholar
  80. Searle, J. (1983). Intentionality: An essay in the philosophy of mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  81. Sellars, W. (1954). Some reflections on language games. Philosophy of Science, 21, 204–228.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  82. Sellars, W. (1956). Empiricism and the philosophy of mind. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 1(19), 253–329.Google Scholar
  83. Seung, S. (1998). Continuous attractors and oculomotor control. Neural Networks, 11(7–8), 1253–1258.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  84. Shagrir, O. (2012). Structural representations and the brain. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 63(3), 519–545.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  85. Shannon, C. (1948). A mathematical theory of communication. The Bell System Technical Journal, 27(7), 379–423.MathSciNetCrossRefMATHGoogle Scholar
  86. Shepard, R., & Chipman, S. (1970). Second-order isomorphism of internal representations: Shapes of states. Cognitive Psychology, 1(1), 1–17.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  87. Sprevak, M. (2011). Review of Representation Reconsidered by William Ramsey. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62, 669–675.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  88. Sterelny, K. (1995). Basic minds. Philosophical Perspectives, 9, 251–270.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  89. Stich, S. (1983). From folk psychology to cognitive science: The case against belief. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  90. Swoyer, C. (1991). Structural representation and surrogative reasoning. Synthese, 87(3), 449.MathSciNetCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  91. Turing, A. (1936). On computable numbers, with an application to the Entscheidungsproblem. Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society, 42(2), 230–265.MathSciNetMATHGoogle Scholar
  92. Tye, M. (1995). Ten problems of consciousness: A representational theory of the phenomenal mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  93. van Gelder, T. (1995). What might cognition be, if not computation. The Journal of Philosophy, 92(7), 345–381.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  94. Wang, X. (2001). Synaptic reverberation underlying mnemonic persistent activity. Trends in Neurosciences, 24(8), 455–463.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  95. Watson, J. (1913). Psychology as the behaviorist views it. Psychological Review, 20(2), 158.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  96. Wolpert, D., et al. (2003). A unifying computational framework for motor control and social interaction. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 358(1431), 593–602.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2017

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Rice UniversityHoustonUSA
  2. 2.University of Missouri–St. LouisSt. LouisUSA

Personalised recommendations