Skip to main content
Log in

Why Be Cautious with Advocating Private Environmental Duties? Towards a Cooperative Ethos and Expressive Reasons

  • Articles
  • Published:
Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This article start from two opposing intuitions in the environmental duties debate. On the one hand, if our lifestyle causes environmental harm, then we have a duty to reduce that impact through lifestyle changes (lifestyle-matters intuition). On the other hand, many people share the intuition that environmental duties cannot demand to alter our lifestyle radically for environmental reasons. These two intuitions underlie the current dualism in the environmental duties debate: those arguing for lifestyle changes (private duties) and those arguing that our duties are limited to promoting just environmental institutions (promotional duties). The paper has two goals: first, to grasp the underlying reasons for the two intuitions, and, second, to provide a proposal that integrates both intuitions. The paper consists of two main parts. The first part examines the ‘our-duties-should-be-limited’ intuition. Two interpretations are discussed, one under the title ‘what I do make no difference’, dealing with causality and collective action, and one under the title ‘my duty cannot be to change my lifestyle completely’, which discusses demandingness, fairness and value conflict. The second part shows how the ‘lifestyle-matters’ intuition can still play an important role. This part consists of two sections, one on ‘how to make a difference’, which deals with the idea of a cooperative ethos, and the other with ‘why lifestyle matters’, discussing expressive rationality and integrity. These ideas allow giving an important place to lifestyle duties, while avoiding the possible counterproductive effect of a private duties account.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See also Neuteleers (2014: 503).

  2. In this number everyone is given an equal share (cf. ‘equal per capital view’) (Singer 2010), which is an intuitively plausible way of distributing individual emission shares, but not the only way.

  3. Cf. Rawls’ primary goods: ‘things that every rational man is presumed to want’ (Rawls 1999, p. 54).

  4. For a detailed discussion, see Neuteleers (2010). There, it was argued that even a liberal and strict promotional duty account can include a significant category of lifestyle actions.

  5. For a good application of Rawls’ account to environmental duties, see Bell (2002, 2005).

  6. For example, one time joyguzzling (a ride for fun in gas guzzling SUV) increases CO2 concentration by one part per quintillion (1/1018) (Kingston and Sinnott-Armstrong 2018, p. 174).

  7. Broome argues that our emissions do ‘expected harm’.

  8. Rawls’ principle of fairness (Rawls 1999, pp. 108–114) can be defined as follows: ‘those who have submitted to these restrictions [of just institutions] have a right to similar acquiescence on the part of those who have benefited from their submission’ (Nozick 1974, p. 90).

  9. Of course, fairness or justice does not only refer to the distribution of contributions. Another aspect concerns the relation with the victims. Here, however, the focus is on explaining the intuition or experience people have. The broader debate is to which extent one should contribute in a situation of partial compliance (‘tacking up the slack’) (Hohl and Roser 2011; Miller 2011).

  10. This is also the view of, for instance, Miller (2011), on the condition that non-compliance is reversible.

  11. Wolf (2007) and Frankfurt (1982, 2009) talk about ‘reasons of love’ both for particular people, as for other subjects, as in the phrase of loving music, flowers or philosophy, but the label love might be confusing because of its connotation with interpersonal love. Frankfurt also talks about the category of importance (versus moral) (Frankfurt 2009) or ‘reasons to care about’ (Frankfurt 1982).

  12. See also Frankfurt (2009, pp. 6–7).

  13. See also Williams (1981, pp. 1–19).

  14. For a detailed discussion, see Neuteleers (2010).

  15. Figures from using WWF’s carbon footprint calculator (https://footprint.wwf.org.uk/carbon/footprint).

  16. This is the expensive option (including ‘radiative forcing’), else the offset would be €23 (www.greentripper.org, used by e.g. Brussels Airlines).

  17. Average Belgian carbon footprint is 8.3 tCO2/y and carbon price in the European Emission Trading System (EU-ETS) is around €25/tCO2 (spring 2019, https://markets.businessinsider.com/commodities/co2-emissionsrechte). This price is relatively high compared to past EU-ETS prices and prices used for offsetting flights (example above: €11/tCO2)—of course, this does not imply the price is high enough.

  18. There are many criticisms of offsetting, both regarding effectiveness (e.g Anderson 2012) and morality (e.g. Goodin 1994). Many offsetting problems (additionality, measurement, control, carbon leakage, etc.) relate to implementating carbon projects in developing countries (e.g. CDM, REDD+). For this reason, I used EU-ETS prices (which do not allow external compensation anymore); there reductions only follow from decreasing emissions.

  19. See, for instance: ‘Young, smart and want to save lives? Become a banker, says philosopher’, https://www.reuters.com/article/us-global-charities-altruism-idUSKCN0Q10M220150727.

References

  • Anderson, K. (2012). The inconvenient truth of carbon offsets. Nature, 484(5 April), 7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baatz, C. (2014). Climate change and individual duties to reduce GHG emissions. Ethics; Policy & Environment, 17(1), 1–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baatz, C., & Voget-Kleschin, L. (2019). Individual duties regarding global environmental problems the example of climate change. Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics, 32(this issue).

  • Bell, D. (2002). How can political liberals be environmentalists? Political Studies, 50(4), 703–724.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bell, D. (2005). Liberal environmental citizenship. Environmental Politics, 14(2), 179–194.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bell, D., Swaffield, J., & Peeters, W. (2019). Climate ethics with an ethnographic sensibility. Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10806-019-09794-z.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bowles, S. (2016). The moral economy. Why good incentives are no substitute for good citizens. New Have: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bowles, S., & Gintis, H. (2013). A cooperative species: Human reciprocity and its evolution. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Broome, J. (2018). Against denialism. The Monist, 102(1), 110–129.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Caney, S. (2014). Two kinds of climate justice: Avoiding harm and sharing burdens. Journal of Political Philosophy, 22(2), 125–149.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, G. A. (2000). If you’re an egalitarian, how come you’re so rich?. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, G. A. (2008). Rescuing justice and equality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cripps, E. (2013). Climate change and the moral agent: Individual duties in an interdependent world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dobson, A. (2003). Citizenship and the environment. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dobson, A. (2006). Citizenship. In A. Dobson & R. Eckersley (Eds.), Political theory and the ecological challenge (pp. 216–231). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. (1977). Taking rights seriously. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elster, J. (1992). Local justice. How institutions allocate scarce goods and necessary burdens. New York: Russell Sage Foundation.

    Google Scholar 

  • Engelen, B. (2006). Solving the paradox: The expressive rationality of the decision to vote. Rationality and Society, 18(4), 419–441.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fehr, E., & Gachter, S. (2002). Altruistic punishment in humans. Nature, 415(6868), 137–140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fragnière, A. (2016). Climate change and individual duties. Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Climate Change, 7(6), 798–814.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, H. (1982). The importance of what we care about. Synthese, 53(2), 257–272.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frankfurt, H. (2009). The reasons of love. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gardiner, S. (2011). Is no one responsible for global environmental tragedy? Climate change as a challenge to our ethical concepts. In D. Arnold (Ed.), The ethics of global climate change. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodin, R. E. (1994). Selling environmental indulgences. Kyklos, 47(4), 573–596.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hohl, S., & Roser, D. (2011). Stepping in for the polluters? Climate justice under partial compliance. Analyse & Kritik, 33(2), 477–500.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hourdequin, M. (2010). Climate, collective action and individual ethical obligations. Environmental Values, 19, 443–464.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hwang, S.-H., & Bowles, S. (2012). Is altruism bad for cooperation? Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 83(3), 330–341.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jamieson, D. (2007). When utilitarians should be virtue theorists. Utilitas, 19(2), 160–183.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kingston, E., & Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2018). What’s wrong with joyguzzling? Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 21(1), 169–186.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klain, S. C., Olmsted, P., Chan, K. M. A., & Satterfield, T. (2017). Relational values resonate broadly and differently than intrinsic or instrumental values, or the New Ecological Paradigm. PLoS ONE, 12(8), 1–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knights, P. (2019). A virtue ethics account of the obligation to unilaterally reduce consumption. Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics, 32(this issue).

  • MacLean, D. (2018). Climate complicity and individual accountability. The Monist, 102(1), 1–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maltais, A. (2013). Radically non-ideal climate politics and the obligation to at least vote green. Environmental Values, 22(5), 589–608.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, D. (2001). Distributing responsibilities. The Journal of Political Philosophy, 9(4), 453–471.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, D. (2011). Taking up the Slack? Responsibility and justice in situations of partial compliance. In C. Knight & Z. Stemplowska (Eds.), Responsibility and distributive justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (2005). The problem of global justice. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 33(2), 113–147.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neuteleers, S. (2010). Institutions versus lifestyle: Do citizens have environmental duties in their private sphere? Environmental Politics, 19(4), 501–517.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neuteleers, S. (2014). Individual environmental duties: Questions from an institution-oriented perspective. Ethics, Policy & Environment, 17(1), 20–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nozick, R. (1974). Anarchy, state, and utopia. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Neill, J. (1993). Ecology, policy and politics. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ostrom, E., Gardner, R., & Walker, J. (1994). Rules, games & common-pool resources. Ann Arbor: The University of Michigan Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pascual, U., Balvanera, P., Díaz, S., Pataki, G., Roth, E., Stenseke, M., et al. (2017). Valuing nature’s contributions to people: The IPBES approach. Current Opinion in Environmental Sustainability, 26, 7–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peeters, W., De Smet, A., Diependaele, L., Sterckx, S., McNeal, R. H., & De Smet, A. (2015). Climate change and individual responsibility: Agency, moral disengagement and the motivational gap. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1999). A theory of justice (Revised ed.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sandel, M. J. (2005). Public philosophy. Essays on morality in politics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. K. (1967). Isolation, assurance and the social rate of discount. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 81(1), 112–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P. (1972). Famine, affluence, and morality. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 1(3), 229–243.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P. (2002). One world. The ethics of globalization. New York: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P. (2009). The life you can save. London: Picador.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P. (2010). One atmosphere. In S. Gardiner, S. Caney, D. Jamieson, & H. Shue (Eds.), Climate ethics. Essential readings (pp. 181–199). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2005). It’s not my fault: Global warming and individual moral obligations. In W. Sinnott-Armstrong & R. Howarth (Eds.), Perspectives on climate change: Science, economics, politics, ethics (pp. 293–314). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • van den Born, R. J. G., Arts, B., Admiraal, J., Beringer, A., Knights, P., Molinario, E., et al. (2017). The missing pillar: Eudemonic values in the justification of nature conservation. Journal of Environmental Planning and Management, 61, 1–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vanderheiden, S. (2007). Climate change and the challenge of moral responsibility. Journal of Philosophical Research, 32(Supplement), 85–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walzer, M. (1983). Spheres of justice. A defense of pluralism and equality. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, B. (1973). A critique of utilitarianism. In J. J. C. Smart & B. Williams (Eds.), Utilitarianism: For & against (pp. 77–150). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, B. (1981). Moral luck: Philosophical papers 1973–1980. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wolf, S. (1982). Moral saints. The Journal of Philosophy, 79(8), 419–439.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wolf, S. (2007). Meaning in life and why it matters. In G. B. Peterson (Ed.), The tanner lectures on human values (Vol. 28, pp. 71–116). Salt Lake City: University of Utah Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolf, S. (2014). The variety of values: Essays on morality, meaning, and love. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This research was funded by the F.R.S.-FNRS (mandat chargé de recherches). This paper benefitted from the interesting discussions during the MANCEPT workshop on environmental duties. I would like to thank especially Lieske Voget-Kleschin and Paul Knights for the many insightful and helpful comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Stijn Neuteleers.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Neuteleers, S. Why Be Cautious with Advocating Private Environmental Duties? Towards a Cooperative Ethos and Expressive Reasons. J Agric Environ Ethics 32, 547–568 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10806-019-09790-3

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10806-019-09790-3

Keywords

Navigation