1 Introduction

Modern societies in the West are under strain. Populist politicians and parties are becoming more successful in campaigning against government policies that tended to appear self-evident in the past decades. Past policies were based on efficiency-enhancing values such as international integration and globalization, individual freedom and meritocracy (Sandel, 2020). Nowadays, a political divide opens up between those social groups that have internalized these values and continue supporting the respective policies and those other social groups that oppose these policies. To better understand these developments, it can be helpful to consider different facets of the social divide: differences in economic opportunities, differences in access to relevant (economic) information, as well as different levels of inclusiveness characterizing public debates. A sound analysis of how these differences interact is essential for a better understanding of some of the current tensions in modern democracies.

To this purpose, we develop an experimental model (Mäki, 2005) that represents in a simplified way the situation of modern societies in the West. Although we do not frame our experiment, its main application is to a situation in which societies have to choose between alternative policies, facing a potential conflict between two social groups. The state of the economy is uncertain, and while the members of one of the groups (the whites) have some information about it, the members of the other group (the blues) are uninformed.Footnote 1 In both states of the economy the same set of policies can be implemented, which lead to different distributions of material payoffs between the groups. In one state of the world the two groups have conflicting material interests, in the other state their material interests are aligned. Hence, only the whites have some information on whether interests are conflicting. The collective choice of policy is determined through a vote in which all individuals from both groups can participate. Before the vote, the groups may communicate.

This simple setting captures modern democratic societies’ critical issue of dealing with potential economic conflicts between social groups. In most of these societies there is arguably a social class with little wealth, whose incomes are highly dependent on the thriving of the national industrial sector (the “dependent class”). In contrast, leading politicians and opinion leaders in the media, cultural and educational professions are mainly recruited from another social class that is less dependent on the national industries and more entrenched in the multi-national economic sectors (the “entrenched class”). Individuals in the entrenched class have higher education and somewhat more reliable information on economic conditions than those in the dependent class. Hence, they have an informed idea about whether their material interests align or clash with those of the dependent class, depending on the current state of the economy. By contrast, the dependent class only knows that their interests may or may not clash with the entrenched class’ interests, depending on the unknown state. How much can such a society turn their collective choice toward efficient policies? And how do truthfulness, trust, and cooperativeness between these classes develop, depending on the degree of inclusiveness that the communication channels in the society provide, e.g., the degree to which discussion panels and media are representative of both classes?

Across experimental treatments, we exogenously vary inclusiveness as follows. Pre-vote communication is determined by three distinct protocols or deliberative structures that differ in how the communication between the whites and the blues is designed. In the FullyPublic deliberative structure, we implement a stylized ideal of deliberation that is inspired by the normative deliberation literature (Dawes et al., 1990, Orbell et al., 1988, Dryzek & List, 2003): All individuals, regardless of their group affiliation, have the same possibilities of sending to and receiving messages from all other individuals. This ideal deliberative structure is the most inclusive.Footnote 2 We then decrease inclusiveness stepwise: In the deliberative structure that we refer to as TopDown, only the whites have the possibility of sending messages; the blues are reduced to being receivers. However, at least in their role as receivers, whites and blues are on the same footing since each message sent is simultaneously received by all. We further reduce inclusiveness in the deliberative structure that we refer to as TopDownClosed. There, the whites first communicate among each other (“behind closed doors”) before sending messages to all.Footnote 3 For completeness, we compare these three deliberative structures to the benchmark voting game without any communication (NoChat).

Our main interest is in comparing the three implemented deliberative structures with respect to how they contribute to solving a potential economic conflict. For this to happen, in the experimental model at hand, the whites need to truthfully reveal their information to which the blues need to respond with a cooperative vote for the efficient policy, even if this is against their material interest. Building on the deliberation literature cited above, which posits that inclusiveness is essential for truthfulness and a sense of cooperation in society, we propose that different deliberative structures trigger distinct preferences in the spirit of Bowles and Polanía-Reyes (2012). Our assumption is that a deliberative structure’s inclusiveness triggers efficiency preferences, translating into increased truthfulness and cooperativeness.Footnote 4 In a nutshell, we hypothesize that truthfulness and cooperativeness will be lowest in the setting without communication and increase with increasing inclusiveness of the deliberative structures.

Compared with the setting without any communication, we find that communication in all three deliberation treatments leads to more frequent choices of the efficient policies. Comparing our three deliberative structures with each other, we find that the blues are more trustful and more cooperative in FullyPublic than in TopDownClosed, which is reflected in their higher propensity to vote for the efficient policies in the former than in the latter treatment. Hence, when comparing those two extreme degrees of inclusiveness, we do find that more inclusiveness contributes to solving the economic conflict between the two groups. However, this is less clear when we compare FullyPublic and TopDown as well as TopDown and TopDownClosed. And although the whites are more truthful in TopDown than in TopDownClosed, their truthfulness does not differ significantly between FullyPublic and TopDownClosed. We then study the dynamics of the chat and voting behavior in the three deliberation treatments. We find that the dynamics of communication and behavior exhibit a general deterioration of blues’ cooperativeness and trust and whites’ truthfulness in all deliberation treatments. Moreover, in FullyPublic there is an additional factor that enforces deterioration, namely disrespectful language of the whites and uncooperative talk of the blues.

2 Related literature

Pre-vote communication has already been studied in the extensive literature on voting, recently surveyed in Palfrey (2016). For instance, the results in Guarnaschelli et al. (2000) and Goeree and Yariv (2011) document that pre-play communication in the form of either a straw-vote or unrestricted chat leads to an increase in the efficiency of the voting outcome. By contrast, Buechel and Mechtenberg (2019) show that pre-vote communication in social networks that is restricted to information aggregation can lower efficiency even in a common-interest setting.

Andreoni and Rao (2011) study how pre-distribution communication affects distribution. They find that when pairs of individuals play a dictator game the distribution of the endowment varies depending on whether the allocator can send a message to the receiver or the receiver can send a message to the allocator. The receiver obtains a smaller share in the first case than in the second.

Moreover, previous experimental work has found evidence in favor of communication affecting group identity (see Akerlof & Kranton, 2000, 2010), and hence preferences. Chen and Li (2009) report on an experiment in which they study the effects of induced group identity in an environment with an ingroup and an outgroup. They find that participants are more altruistic towards members of an ingroup and that chat communication within the ingroup leads to stronger ingroup favoritism. In the related experiment of Chen and Chen (2011) participants play a coordination game with either an ingroup or an outgroup. In one of the treatments the coordination game is preceded by a chat. They find that stronger communication—more words, more content—has a positive effect on the ingroup and a negative effect on the outgroup. Robalo et al. (2017) also induce ingroup bias in an experiment related to political issues without using communication. They group people according to the results of a personality questionnaire and find that political participation is higher when ingroup bias is stronger. In our case, groups are distinguished by asymmetric payoffs and access to information.

Like in our study, Palfrey and Pogorelskiy (2017) investigate the effects of two different communication structures on voting: public communication (all voters exchange messages through a computer chat) and party communication (messages are only exchanged within each party). However, they focus on voter turnout in an experiment with costly voting. The issue of voter turnout is quite different from the research question that we address. In our environment voting is costless and, hence, is it not suited to studying turnout; indeed, we observe very little abstention in all our treatments.

Pronin and Woon (2017) study how the economic benefits of deliberation can be robust to the existence of private communication between parts of the society, prior to a public discussion. In a setting in which a group of players has to allocate a fixed budget between themselves and a public good they find that allowing for private messages before the public discussion leads to the under-provision of the public good. Again, the particular issue they study is very different from ours, but the communication structure they study is related to our TopDownClosed treatment.

Although our main interest is in communication on the societal level, our analysis can also be related to the effects of institutionalized communication structures in organizational economics (Ambrus et al., 2013). For example, Brandts and Cooper (2007) compare the effects on coordination of various communication structures between a manager and workers.

Our novel contribution to the literature reviewed above is that we simultaneously study (1) how two groups solve a state-dependent conflict of interest, (2) how efficiently they aggregate information on that state held by one of the groups, and (3) how the conflict solution is affected by communication structures.

3 Experimental design

We consider the following voting game: Six players form a voting group, consisting of three white players and three blue players. These players vote on a policy from a set of three alternatives (A, B, and C). The implemented policy determines state-dependent payoffs that may differ by the players’ colors, see Table 1. At the beginning of the game, nature draws the state of the world, which is either X or Y with equal probability. Then, nature randomly draws an informative private signal on the state of the world for each white player. These signals are conditionally independent and true with probability \(p=0.7\). Blue players do not receive any signal.

Next, a communication stage starts. We consider three deliberative structures that vary in their inclusiveness. In particular, they gradually differ in the extent of the whites’ control over the communication process. In treatment FullyPublic, whites and blues can publicly communicate with each other. In TopDown the whites, but not the blues can send (public) messages and in TopDownClosed the whites can first communicate with each other unobserved by the blues and then send public messages that are also received by the blues. Messages are sent simultaneously, and remaining silent is possible for all senders.

Communication is implemented as computerized free-form chat.Footnote 5 In FullyPublic and TopDown, the chat lasted for two minutes. In TopDownClosed, both the first (private) chat among the whites and the second (public) chat lasted for one minute each.Footnote 6 Benchmark treatment NoChat implements our game without any communication stage. After the information stage, subjects in NoChat have the opportunity to take private notes in a computer window that looks exactly like the chat window in the other treatments. We decided to exogenously restrict the duration of the chat (note taking) stage in order to keep the total duration of the experimental sessions comparable within and across treatments. We thus tightly control the task- and time-structure of all treatments. We asked our subjects to focus their communication (in NoChat their notes) on the voting decision at hand. Apart from that, we did not impose any restrictions on their writing.Footnote 7

Table 1 Blue and white players’ payoffs, conditional on the state of the world and implemented policies

In the following voting stage, each individual chooses whether to vote for one of the three policies A, B, and C, or to abstain. Voting is costless. The final policy is elected according to the plurality rule (i.e., the final policy is the one that got most votes); and ties are resolved randomly, with equal probabilities.

The state of the world interacts with the implemented policy in generating final payoffs, as displayed in Table 1. In state X, whites and blues would agree on the most preferred policy: Both would like to implement policy A. This is, however, not true in state Y: While the whites would prefer B to be chosen, selfish blues would prefer C instead. Hence, the two groups have a state-dependent conflict. This conflict in state Y is particularly sharp since, for selfish whites, C is the worst of all options. The state-dependent efficient policy choice is A in state X and B in state Y. It is hence in line with the preferences of the whites.Footnote 8

The state-dependent conflict gives the white players an incentive to lie about the state of the world in the communication stage, if, given their signals, they expect state Y. In this case, truthfully reporting the majority signal (i.e., the signal received by the majority of whites) would lead selfish blue players to vote for C. The whites would vote for B, which ultimately generates a tie between policies B and C yielding each white player an expected payoff of \(\frac{1}{2} \times 20 + \frac{1}{2} \times 0=10\) if state Y prevails. If, however, the whites successfully lied about the state of the world such that the blues expected state X and hence voted for A, the whites would expect to earn \(\frac{1}{2} \times 10 + \frac{1}{2}\times 20=15\) if they themselves chose policy B. Obviously, and as shown in Appendix A in the Electronic Supplementary Material, successful lies cannot be part of an equilibrium here – instead, communication would become meaningless (“babbling”).

Our main underlying assumption is that deliberation works in a sense consistent with normative deliberation theory (e.g., Dawes et al., 1990, Orbell et al., 1988, Dryzek & List, 2003). Central to this theory is the idea that the more inclusive the deliberation protocol, the more inclusive become the preferences of those participating in it.Footnote 9 Interpreting deliberation theory, we predict that a player has selfish preferences, unless the structure of the deliberative process leads him or her to internalize the interests of others. For the blues, preferences only impact their voting. For the whites they affect both their voting and the revelation of the information they have. Based on this, we can characterize the white and blue players’ optimal behavior in our four treatments.

First, in the benchmark treatment without deliberation, NoChat, players from both groups have selfish preferences. The blues vote for C, which is the policy that benefits them most in expectation if information about the true state is absent. The whites vote for A or B.Footnote 10

Consider next the deliberation treatments, starting with the one with the lowest degree of inclusiveness, TopDownClosed, which gives the blues a passive role in the communication process and allows the whites to communicate exclusively with the other whites in the first (private) chat stage, like in the party communication treatment of Palfrey and Pogorelskiy (2017). Supposedly, the exclusion of the blues and the in-group bias of the whites triggered by the private chat lead both groups to have selfish preferences. Then the interaction between them involves the state-dependent conflict described above, and the whites will lie to the blues if they receive majority signal Y (i.e. only babbling equilibria exist). Therefore, the blues will always vote for C, which maximizes their expected payoffs. The whites, on the other hand, will vote according to their shared information, i.e., for A in case the majority signal is X, and for B in case the majority signal is Y.Footnote 11 Hence, voting behavior in TopDownClosed can be outcome-equivalent to what we predict for NoChat.

Consider next TopDown. In this treatment’s deliberation protocol, the blues have a passive role in the communication process as in TopDownClosed and, hence, only care for their own interests. However, the whites now address the society as a whole in public, without their in-group bias being triggered by the private chat as in TopDownClosed. Thus, the hypothesis based on deliberation theory is that the whites become empathetic with the blues and hence develop efficiency preferences. This makes them truthful toward both colors. As a consequence, the conflict described above is, in total, ameliorated. The whites do no longer lie to the blues about the signals they have received. Hence, in equilibrium the blues now obtain information about the true state. Following their material interests, they vote for A along with the whites when they are told that the state is X, but for C (rather than B along with the whites) when they are told that the state is Y.

Finally, consider FullyPublic. Here, both whites and blues are senders as well as receivers, as required by normative deliberation theory for an ideal deliberative structure. Our main underlying assumption implies that now both whites and blues care for both colors; i.e., they all have efficiency preferences. Therefore, the equilibrium strategies of the two colors are the following: The whites truthfully report their signals to all other players, and players vote in such a way that a plurality of votes is for A if the majority of signals indicate that the state is X and for B if the majority of signals indicate that the state is Y. Such strategy profiles implement a compromise: If state Y is more likely than X, the blues refrain from voting for their best choice C and support their second-best choice B instead, which is efficient. Given this behavior of the blues, not even selfish whites would have an incentive to lie to them about the state.

Table 2 Preferences for efficiency and their impact on information aggregation and voting decisions in equilibrium

Table  2 summarizes for each of the four treatments (1) if players may read and/or write messages and (2) how the different treatments affect their efficiency preferences, (3) the incentive of the whites to lie to the blues and (4) the predicted voting decisions. In the analysis of the results we will mainly focus on the comparative statics of behavior (see Schotter, 2015), given by the last five columns of Table 2.

We conducted 20 sessions with 468 subjects from various study backgrounds at the WISO-laboratory of Hamburg University.Footnote 12 Subjects kept their roles throughout the 20 periods of the experiment. Half of them randomly assumed the roles of white, the other half the roles of blue players. Groups were randomly re-composed and subjects’ chat IDs were randomly reassigned in the beginning of every period such that subjects were not able to track individuals throughout the different periods (stranger matching).

We used hroot (Bock et al., 2014) to recruit subjects and coded the experiment in z-tree (Fischbacher, 2007). During the sessions payments were expressed in experimental currency units (points) which were exchanged to Euros at a rate of 1 Euro = 3 points at the end of the experiment. Average earnings for the 120 minutes sessions amounted to 23.28 Euro (s.d. 4.73), including a 10 Euro show-up fee (minimum earnings = 10 Euro, maximum earnings = 30 Euro).

4 Results

4.1 Whites’ truth-telling and blues’ trustfulness

We first investigate how the inclusiveness of the deliberative structure affects truth-telling – or conversely, lying – of the whites. We define lying as white players reporting majority message X, that is, at least two of the three whites report message X, if, in fact, the majority signal was Y. That means that we consider only pivotal lies. Analogously, we define truth-telling as the white players reporting majority message Y if their majority signal was Y. Since the whites have no incentive to lie if they receive majority signal X, we restrict the analysis of lying/truth-telling to periods in which the whites receive majority signal Y. Comparing across treatments, 22.16% of the white subgroups lie in FullyPublic, 11.44% of the white subgroups lie in TopDown and 35.08% in TopDownClosed.Footnote 13

To econometrically test for the treatment differences in truth-telling, we run a linear probability model, in which we regress the dummy variable for a white subgroup reporting majority message Y if in fact the majority signal is Y (truth-telling) on treatment dummies FullyPublic and TopDownClosed. We hence treat TopDown as baseline treatment which differs from each of the other two deliberation treatments by only one design feature.Footnote 14 Additionally, we control for the period of play.

Table 3 Truth-telling if the majority signal is Y

Other then expected, whites lying does not (weakly) increase with decreasing inclusiveness across the three deliberation treatments. Although the respective treatment coefficient in Table 3, specification (1), reveals that the whites are less truthful in TopDownClosed than in TopDown, truth-telling is significantly less prevalent in FullyPublic than in TopDown, too. Also, truth-telling does not differ significantly between FullyPublic and TopDownClosed, see the respective Wald test result reported in the lower part of the table. We summarize our findings as follows:

Finding 1

(Whites’ truth-telling) Increasing inclusiveness of deliberation does not lead to more truthfulness across the three deliberation treatments. The whites are more truthful in TopDown than in FullyPublic and TopDownClosed.

Moreover, the significant Period coefficient in specification (1) of Table 3 shows that the whites frequently report majority signal Y truthfully in the first periods, but lie increasingly more often in later periods. In the extended specification (2) we add interaction terms between treatments and period. There is no evidence that the period of play has a significant effect on the observed treatment differences.

Next we turn to the question of how the inclusiveness of the deliberative structure affects the blue players’ trustfulness; the analysis is presented in specifications (3) and (4) in Table 4. We quantify trustfulness as the blues’ propensity to vote for the efficient policy A after having received majority message X. In a linear probability model we regress the individual blues’ votes for the respective expected efficient policy A on treatment dummies FullyPublic and TopDownClosed, using TopDown as baseline treatment, and control for the period of play. We restrict the sample of analysis to periods in which the whites report majority message X. Table 4, specification (3), reveals that the blues are significantly more trustful in the most inclusive treatment FullyPublic than in the least inclusive treatment TopDownClosed, see the reported Wald test result in the lower part of the table. There is neither a significant difference in the blues’ trustfulness between FullyPublic and TopDown nor between TopDown and TopDownClosed.

Finding 2

(Blues’ trustfulness) The blues’ trustfulness (weakly) decreases with decreasing inclusiveness of the deliberative structure, though not all differences turn out significant. Blue players are more trustful in FullyPublic than in TopDownClosed.

Considering the two extremes of the implemented deliberative structures, treatments FullyPublic and TopDownClosed, the blue players’ greater beliefs in the white players’ truth-telling in the former compared to the latter treatment seem justified to some extent. The actual difference in truth-telling between these treatments is insignificant, though (\(p=0.110\)). Interestingly, however, the blues seem unaware of the whites’ greater truthfulness in TopDown compared to FullyPublic.

Finally, the significantly negative Period coefficient in specification (3) of Table 4 suggests that the blues’ trustfulness in the whites’ reported majority message X decreases significantly by on average 2.3 percentage points per period, independently of treatment. Adding interaction terms between treatments and period of play in specification (4) does not reveal significant changes in treatment differences over periods. Except for the significant treatment difference between FullyPublic and TopDownClosed, the blues mistrust the whites’ reported majority signal to similar extents in all three deliberation treatments and in all periods of play.

4.2 Whites’ voting decisions

We now investigate how voting behavior of the whites varies with the inclusiveness of the deliberative structure. Note that we do not expect any variation here: At the voting stage, the material interests of the informed whites overlap with efficiency preferences. Hence, even if whites’ efficiency preferences were triggered by inclusive deliberation, we would not able to observe this in the whites’ votes.

Figure 1 displays the white players’ voting decisions over periods. If the majority signal is X, whites predominantly vote for policy A in all four treatments, see the four graphs on the left. If the majority signal is Y, the majority of whites vote for policy B in all three deliberation treatments, in particular in the first periods and for A in NoChat, see the four graphs on the right.

Fig. 1
figure 1

Whites’ individual voting decisions

The linear probability models in Table 7, specifications (1) and (5), complement this graphical presentation and confirm that the varying inclusiveness does not significantly change the whites’ voting behavior across the deliberation treatments (see Appendix).Footnote 15

Finding 3

(Whites’ voting decisions) Given majority signal X (Y), the whites’ propensity to vote for the respective efficient policy A (B) does not differ across FullyPublic, TopDown and TopDownClosed. However, implementation of the efficient policy is more likely in those deliberation treatments than in NoChat.

4.3 Blues’ voting decisions

4.3.1 Blues’ votes for the efficient policy

We now move on to investigating how the inclusiveness of the deliberative structure affects the voting behavior of the blues. Note that here, we do expect effects, namely that, with increasing inclusiveness, the blues vote weakly more often for the state-dependent efficient policy (and weakly less often for C).

Figure 2 displays the blue players’ voting decisions over periods for the cases of majority signal X (see the four graphs on the left) and majority signal Y (see the four graphs on the right). As evident, the blues predominantly vote for policy C in treatment NoChat. In all other treatments, a non-negligible fraction of blues votes for the respective efficient policy at least in the beginning of the experiment. This is particularly true if the majority signal is X. However, the choice of C increases over time. For majority signal X, the choice of C becomes as frequent as that of A in FullyPublic and TopDown and more frequent than A in TopDownClosed. For majority signal Y, C quickly becomes the most frequent choice in all treatments.

Fig. 2
figure 2

Blues’ individual voting decisions

In the linear probability models presented in Table 4 we study the blue players’ voting decisions in more detail. Given majority signal X (see specification (1)), the blues vote significantly more often for the efficient policy A in FullyPublic than in TopDown, TopDownClosed and NoChat, and more often in TopDown than in NoChat, see the treatment coefficients and corresponding Wald test results which are at least significant at the 10% level. However, the blues’ propensity to vote for A is not significantly higher in TopDown than in TopDownClosed. Focusing on those periods in which the majority signal is Y (see specification (5)), the blues’ propensity to vote for the efficient policy B is significantly higher in FullyPublic than in TopDown, TopDownClosed and NoChat (at least at the 10% significance level). This specification also reveals significant treatment differences between TopDown, TopDownClosed and NoChat. In sum, increasing inclusiveness of the deliberative structure does indeed direct the blues’ votes more toward efficiency.

Table 4 Blues’ votes for the efficient policies

Finding 4

(Blues’ voting decisions: efficiency) Given both majority signals, the blues’ propensity to vote for the respective efficient policy is higher in all deliberation treatments than in NoChat and their propensity to vote for the efficient policy is highest in FullyPublic compared to the other deliberation treatments. Given majority signal Y, the respective difference between TopDown and TopDownClosed is significant, too.

At the same time, Fig. 2 as well as the significantly negative Period coefficients in regression specifications (1) and (5) in Table 4 reveal a general, treatment-independent decline in the blues’ propensity to vote for the efficient policy over periods, for both majority signals X and Y. It amounts to on average 1.7 percentage points per period in case of majority signal X and 1.1 percentage points per period in case of majority signal Y. Furthermore, the extended specifications (2) and (6) reveal that all treatment differences between NoChat and the deliberation treatments are particularly large in the beginning of the session and then decrease significantly over the 20 periods of play, given both majority signals.

4.3.2 Blues’ cooperativeness

We define blues’ cooperativeness as voting for B rather than C after receiving majority message Y. Given the material incentives, the whites would prefer the blues to believe that the state is X when it is Y. Hence, the whites sending majority message Y is believable and the blues then voting B is consistent with them rewarding whites’ truthfulness. Considering specifications (7) and (8) of Table 4, blues’ response to the whites sending majority message Y leads to significantly more B votes in FullyPublic than in the other two deliberation treatments, with no difference between the latter two.

Moreover, we observe a general, but small negative period effect on voting for the efficient policy.Footnote 16 Overall, we conclude that the blues’ cooperativeness improves with full inclusiveness.

4.4 The dynamics reveal deterioration of deliberation

Reconsidering our previous analyses, the significant Period coefficients in the regressions from Tables 3 and  4 show that the incidences of conflict, manifested by lying, low degrees of trust and not voting for the state-specific efficient policies, increase in all treatments over periods. After an initial phase of high cooperation and low conflict, the opportunity to deliberate does not lead to sustainable coordination on the efficient outcomes in the deliberation treatments. In particular, the results for FullyPublic suggest that the effectiveness of deliberative democracy deteriorates over periods.

To better understand the changes in behavior over periods, we study the interactions between blues’ voting decisions, whites’ lying behavior and the content of the chat conversations. We hired two research assistants to code the chat messages independently from each other (we refer to them as Coder #1 and Coder #2). We provided them with a list of chat dimensions that we considered potentially relevant a priori to classify the individual statements made by whites and blues.Footnote 17 In a second step, we then aggregated these individual classifications to chat message indicator variables at the color group level.

In the regressions presented in Table 5 we analyze the interactions between blues’ voting decisions in the deliberation treatments. In our analysis, we focus on chat classifications that we observed in more than 15% of all chat messages. Consider first specification (1), in which we focus on those periods in which the whites report majority message X. These are the periods in which the whites either truthfully reveal their majority signal or lie to make the blues believe that situation X prevails. Like in Sect. 4.1 above, we take the blues’ propensity to vote for the efficient policy A as a measure of trust. In a linear probability model we regress the blues’ propensity to vote for policy A on a dummy variable that indicates if the reported majority message in the previous period was inconsistent with the actual state of the world (“Potential lie”), and two further dummies that capture the tone of the whites’ messages (respectful language, that is, rather appreciating statements and disrespectful language, that is, rather impolite statements).Footnote 18 Moreover, we include four additional dummy variables that control for whether the whites mention the experimental environment as justification of their behavior (“our signals are not 100% correct” and similar statements) and attempt to appeal to the blues’ public spirit. Lastly, we control for treatment by including dummies for FullyPublic and TopDownClosed (TopDown serves as baseline treatment) and the period of play.

Table 5 Deliberation treatments: Blues’ votes for the efficient policies
Table 6 Deliberation treatments: Whites’ decision to lie

Voting for A after majority message X is significantly less likely if the reported majority message in the previous period was inconsistent with the actual state of the world (“Potential lie”) and if the whites treated the blues disrespectfully.Footnote 19

Next we turn to those periods in which the whites report majority message Y. Since the whites have no incentive to make the blues believe that Y prevails if in fact they believe that it is X, what we study here is not the effects on the blues’ trustfulness, but rather their cooperative response to having received a truthful message. For this, we consider their votes for the efficient policy B, given majority message Y. Specification (2) regresses the blues’ propensity to vote for B on the same explanatory variables that we used in specification (1). We find that voting for B again is more likely in FullyPublic than in TopDown and less likely if the whites treat the blues disrespectfully. Moreover, treating the blues respectfully now has a significantly positive effect, potentially reinforcing the general positive effect of telling the truth.Footnote 20

And lastly, similar to what we found in Table 4, the Period coefficient is significantly negative in both specifications in Table 5, too, indicating a general, treatment-unspecific tendency of the blues to vote for policy C increasingly often over periods.

Considering the found negative long-term consequences of whites’ lies on blues’ cooperativeness, the question arises why the whites lie to the blues and—considering that they do so also in the public chat in FullyPublic and TopDown—why they do so even at the expense of lying to their fellow whites. The regression specifications in Table 6 attempt to shed light on this question. In the reported linear probability models we regress the individual white players’ decisions to lie (to report X instead of Y) on all chat content categories that were recorded in at least 15% of the blues’ chat messages in FullyPublic. Moreover, we include a dummy that takes value 1 if all blue players that a white player was matched to in the previous period voted for C in that period. We also include a variable capturing the number of convinced blues (that is, the number of blue players who voted for A following a lie) in the previous period. Lastly, we control for the period of play and, in column (2), for treatment.

Specification (1) considers only the FullyPublic treatment. As evident, the whites’ propensity to report a wrong state of the world increases if they encountered at least one blue player who recommended voting for C and if all blue players voted for C in the previous period. Also, the more successful a lie was in the previous period (measured as number of convinced blues), the higher is a whites’ propensity to lie again.

When considering all deliberation treatments (see specification (2)), we can only condition on blue players’ voting decisions in previous periods since they have no opportunity to participate in the chat in TopDown and TopDownClosed. Again, the whites’ propensity to lie increases if all blue players voted for C in the previous period and in the number of blue players who voted for A following a lie in the previous period. Similar to what we found in Table 3, the whites lie increasingly often in later periods of play. Also the general treatment differences reported in Table 3 remain significant after including the chat content categories.

Finding 5

(Deterioration of deliberation) The dynamics of communication reveal a general deterioration of blues’ cooperativeness and trust and whites’ truthfulness in all deliberation treatments. Moreover, in FullyPublic there is an additional factor that enforces deterioration, namely disrespectful language of the whites’ and blues’ recommendation and choice of policy C.

5 Discussion

We use a laboratory experiment to shed light on an important socio-economic issue: the difficulty of reaching an efficient collective policy choice in a democratic environment in which two social groups with different material interests have also different information and different access to communication channels. In our setting, one group has more information than the other on whether their material interests align or clash. In three deliberation treatments, we vary the inclusiveness of the deliberative structure that shapes the pre-vote communication of the two groups.

Compared with a benchmark setting without any communication, we find that communication leads to a higher propensity to vote for the efficient policies. More interestingly, we learn from our experiment that fully inclusive deliberation, as modelled in FullyPublic, has both advantages and disadvantages. The main advantage is that with full inclusiveness, the blues are more cooperative in their voting behavior: they reward truthfulness of the whites (i.e. revelation of majority message Y) more than in less inclusive settings. The main disadvantage, however, is that over time the whites become less truthful in the fully inclusive setting. The reason is the existence of a vicious circle: The more whites lie, the less blues vote for efficiency; the more blues recommend voting for C, the more whites lie. In addition, the emotional connotation of communication content is also relevant. In particular, whites’ use of disrespectful language increases conflict. Our results here point to a phenomenon that we may call the curse of unrestricted communication: In an adversarial situation, the unrestricted back and forth of communication that is possible in the FullyPublic treatment may lead to an escalation in animosity. Our findings challenge the conception that fully inclusive deliberative environments will lead to the highest level of truthfulness. The reality of what is actually said in the communication can go against what a priori may appear to be an environment conducive to truth-telling.

Naturally, the particular deliberative structures we focus on are not the only interesting ones. In particular, it would be interesting to study a deliberative structure in which both whites and blues could separately communicate among each other before communicating with both groups. Such a structure would reflect the fact that in democratic societies the dependent classes also have access to restricted communication channels. It is not easy to gauge what the results would be in such an environment, but one may conjecture that conflict would be higher than in FullyPublic.

We believe that the phenomena we observe are relevant beyond our experiment. First, in modern democracies the advice pertaining to policy options given by experts and the more educated to the society at large is increasingly often ignored by the less informed members of society. This occurs out of a combination of distrust vis-à-vis those who are seen as privileged and the experience that expert knowledge is often less than perfect, so that expert advice that is ex post incorrect is not infrequent. Second, the immediacy and anonymity of inclusive communication that is now possible through digital media often leads to aggressiveness and disrespect between groups, which can make it difficult to reach a large societal consensus on important issues. If, instead, the informed group controls the communication process things can be even worse, because a group with a purely passive role in public communication loses sight of society’s general interests and becomes particularistic.