Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Virtue Beyond Contract: A MacIntyrean Approach to Employee Rights

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Journal of Business Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Rights claims are ubiquitous in modernity. Often expressed when relatively weaker agents assert claims against more powerful actors, especially against states and corporations, the prominence of rights claims in organizational contexts creates a challenge for virtue-based approaches to business ethics, especially perspectives employing MacIntyre’s practices–institutions schema since MacIntyre has long been a vocal critic of the notion of human rights. In this article, I argue that employee rights can be understood at a basic level as rights conferred by the rules constitutive of practices. As such, employee rights correspond to the obligations of practitioners to treat fellow practitioners according to the standards of excellence and requirements of justice. Thus, one way that managers can ensure that their core practice is well-functioning is to recognize employee rights. One implication of this argument is that managers should adopt a more positive stance toward labor unions, insofar as they are a key way for employees to ensure that their voice is heard, and their rights respected.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Research suggests that many criminal organizations, such as the mafia, where any notion of a good purpose seems to be lacking, are actually ethically ambivalent, often fulfilling important social functions, contributing in a distorted manner to the common good, while also unjustly exploiting others (Hagedorn 2008; Kilcullen 2010, 2015). This is not to say that criminal organizations are practices but it does suggest that most organizations, especially lawful corporations, present a rather mixed picture, contributing to the common good, while also engaging in forms of injustice. Though clearly some organizations, such as concentration camps lack any sort of direction to the common good. As Moore (2017, p. 146) says, “The conclusion we have reached, therefore, is a rather nuanced one. Not everything is a practice; some activities are excluded because they do not have internal goods which serve the common good (concentration camps, for example). Some activities clearly are practices even if, sometimes, they stand in need of moral criticism (chess, medicine, architecture, for example). And some activities may have been practices in the past, or could have the potential to be practices in the future, but institutional corruption and acquisitiveness is such that there is barely any evidence of practice-like features (banking, for example). But in the latter case, it may yet be possible to redeem these activities so that they, at least, begin to exhibit practice-like features.”

References

  • Adler, P. S., & Borys, B. (1996). Two types of bureaucracy: Enabling and coercive. Administrative Science Quarterly, 41(1), 61–89.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, E. (2017). Private government: How employers rule our lives (and why we don't talk about it). Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aquinas, T. (1981). Summa theologiae. New York: Christian Classics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. (1999). The Nichomachean ethics. In T. Irwin (Ed.), Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing Company Inc.

  • Arnold, D. G., & Bowie, N. E. (2003). Sweatshops and respect for persons. Business Ethics Quarterly, 13(2), 221–242.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arnold, D. G., & Bowie, N. E. (2007). Respect for workers in global supply chains: Advancing the debate over sweatshops. Business Ethics Quarterly, 17(1), 135–145.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barnard, C. (1971). The functions of the executive: 30th (anniversary ed.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beabout, G. (2012). Management as a domain-relative practice that requires and develops practical wisdom. Business Ethics Quarterly, 22(2), 405–432.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beadle, R. (2008). Why business cannot be a practice. Analyse & Kritik, 30(1), 229–241.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beadle, R. (2013). Managerial work in a practice-embodying institution: The role of calling, the virtue of constancy. Journal of Business Ethics, 113(4), 679–690.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beadle, R. (2017). MacIntyre's influence on business ethics. In A. Sison, G. Beabout, & I. Ferrero (Eds.), Handbook of virtue ethics in business and management (pp. 1–9). New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beadle, R., & Moore, G. (2006). MacIntyre on virtue and organization. Organization Studies, 27(3), 323–340.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beadle, R., & Knight, K. (2012). Virtue and meaningful work. Business Ethics Quarterly, 22(2), 433–450.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernacchio, C. (2015). Rival versions of corporate governance as rival theories of agency. Philosophy of Management, 14(1), 67–76.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernacchio, C. (2018a). Networks of giving and receiving in an organizational context: Dependent Rational Animals and MacIntyrean business ethics. Business Ethics Quarterly, 28(4), 377–400.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernacchio, C. (2018b). Agency, desires, and changing organizational routines. Philosophy of Management, 17(3), 279–301.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackledge, P. (2012). Marxism and ethics: Freedom, desire, and revolution. Albany, NY: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bowie, N. (2015). Richard De George and the use of ethical theory in applied ethics. Journal of Business Ethics, 127(4), 699–706.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burton, B. K., & Dunn, C. P. (1996). Collaborative control and the commons: Safeguarding employee rights. Business Ethics Quarterly, 6, 277–288.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cyert, R., & March, J. (2013). A behavioral theory of the firm. Eastford, CT: Martino Fine Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Des Jardins, J. R., & McCall, J. J. (1985). A defense of employee rights. Journal of Business Ethics, 4(5), 367–376.

    Google Scholar 

  • Donaldson, T. (2015). Where the facts end: Richard De George and the rise of business ethics. Journal of Business Ethics., 127(4), 783–787.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duarte d'Almeida, L. (2016). Fundamental legal concepts: the Hohfeldian framework. Philosophy Compass, 11(10), 554–569.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, G. (1978). Taking rights seriously. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferrero, I., & Sison, A. J. G. (2014). A quantitative analysis of authors, schools and themes in virtue ethics articles in business ethics and management journals (1980–2011). Business Ethics European Review, 23, 375–400.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fontrodona, J., & Sison, A. (2006). The nature of the firm, agency theory and shareholder theory: A critique from philosophical anthropology. Journal of Business Ethics, 66(1), 33–42.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foss, N., & Lindenberg, S. (2013). Microfoundations for strategy: A goal-framing perspective on the drivers of value creation. Academy of Management Perspectives, 27(2), 85–102.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ghoshal, S. (2005). Bad management theories are destroying good management practices. Academy of Management Learning & Education, 4(1), 75–91.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ghoshal, S., & Moran, P. (1996). Bad for practice: A critique of the transaction cost theory. Academy of Management Review, 21(1), 13–47.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer, G. (2008). Rationality for mortals: How people cope with uncertainty. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greenhouse, S. (2019). The autoworkers strike is bigger than G.M. The New York Times, September 17.

  • Gregory, B. (2012). The unintended reformation how a religious revolution secularized society. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haase, M. (2014). Am i you? Philosophical Explorations, 17(3), 358–371.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hagedorn, J. (2008). A world of gangs: Armed young men and gangsta culture. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hartman, E. M. (1996). Organizational ethics and the good life. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hartman, E. M. (2013). Virtue in business: Conversations with Aristotle. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Herzog, L. (2018). Reclaiming the system: Moral responsibility, divided labour, and the role of organizations in society. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hohfeld, W. N. (1913). Some fundamental legal conceptions as applied in judicial reasoning. The Yale Law Journal, 23(1), 16–59.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hursthouse, R. (1999). On virtue ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jensen, M., & Meckling, W. (1976). Theory of the firm: Managerial behavior, agency costs and ownership structure. Journal of Financial Economics, 3(4), 305–360.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kilcullen, D. (2010). Counterinsurgency. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kilcullen, D. (2015). Out of the mountains: The coming age of the urban guerrilla. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knight, K. (2008). Goods. Philosophy of Management, 7(1), 107–122.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knight, K. (2018). A radical’s critique of rights. Politics & Poetics., 4, 1–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kogut, B., & Zander, U. (1996). What firms do? Coordination, identity, and learning. Organization Science, 7(5), 502–518.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kolodny, N., & Wallace, R. J. (2003). Promises and practices revisited. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 31(2), 119–154.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laitien, A. 2015. Practices as actual sources of goodness of action. Philosophy and Public Issues (New Series), Supplementary Volume: 57–70.

  • Lindblom, L. (2018). Consent, contestability, and unions. Business Ethics Quarterly. https://doi.org/10.1017/beq.2018.25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lindenberg, S., & Foss, N. J. (2011). Managing joint production motivation: The role of goal framing and governance mechanisms. Academy of Management Review, 36(3), 500–525.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A. (1983). Are there any natural rights?. Brunswick: Bowdoin College.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A. (1994a). How can we learn what Veritatis Splendor has to teach? The Thomist: A Speculative Quarterly Review, 58(2), 171–195.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A. (1994b). A partial response to my critics. In J. Horton & S. Mendus (Eds.), After MacIntyre (pp. 283–304). Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A. (1999). Dependent rational animals: Why human beings need the virtues. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A. (2000). The recovery of moral agency. In J. Wilson (Ed.), The best christian writing 2000 (pp. 111–136). London: HarperCollins.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A. (2004). Questions for Confucians: Reflections on the essays in comparative study of self, autonomy, and community. In K. Shun & D. B. Wong (Eds.), Confucian ethics: A comparative study of self, autonomy, and community (pp. 203–218). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A. (2007). After virtue: A study in moral theory (3rd ed.). Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A. (2016). Ethics in the conflicts of modernity: An essay on desire, practical reasoning, and narrative. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A., & Dunne, J. (2002). Alasdair MacIntyre on education: In dialogue with Joseph Dunne. Journal of Philosophy of Education, 36(1), 1–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • March, J., & Simon, H. (1997). Organizations (2nd ed.). Hoboken, NJ: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marchington, M., & Wilkinson, A. (2005). Direct participation and involvement. In S. Bach (Ed.), Managing human resources: Personnel management in transition (pp. 398–423). Hoboken, NJ: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayer, C. (2013). Firm commitment: Why the corporation is failing us and how to restore trust in it. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCall, J. J. (2001). Employee voice in corporate governance: A defense of strong participation rights. Business Ethics Quarterly, 11, 195–213.

    Google Scholar 

  • Melé, D. (2012). The firm as a “community of persons”: A pillar of humanistic business ethos. Journal of Business Ethics, 106(1), 89–101.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. (2005a). Humanizing business: A modern virtues ethics approach. Business Ethics Quarterly, 15(2), 237–255.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. (2005b). Corporate character: Modern virtue ethics and the virtuous corporation. Business Ethics Quarterly, 15(4), 659–685.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. (2008). Re-imagining the morality of management: A modern virtue ethics approach. Business Ethics Quarterly, 18(4), 483–511.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. (2012a). Virtue in business: Alliance Boots and an empirical exploration of MacIntyre’s conceptual framework. Organization Studies, 33(3), 363–387.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. (2012b). The virtue of governance, the governance of virtue. Business Ethics Quarterly, 22(2), 293–318.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. (2017). Virtue at work: Ethics for individuals, managers, and organizations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G., & Beadle, R. (2006). In search of organizational virtue in business: Agents, goods, practices, and environments. Organization Studies, 27(3), 369–389.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nozick, R. (1974). Anarchy, state, and utopia. New York, NY: Basic Books Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Otteson, J. (2019). Honorable business: A framework for business in a just and humane society. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paár, T. (2018). Whose Aristotelianism? MacIntyre, neoaristotelianism, and morality. Politics & Poetics, 4, 1–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Radin, T. J., & Werhane, P. H. (2003). Employment-at-will, employee rights, and future directions for employment. Business Ethics Quarterly, 13(2), 113–130.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1955). Two concepts of rules. The Philosophical Review, 64(1), 3–32.

    Google Scholar 

  • Retter, M. D. (2018). The road not taken: On MacIntyre’s human rights skepticism. The American Journal of Jurisprudence. https://doi.org/10.1093/ajj/auy012.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robson, A. (2015). Constancy and integrity:(un) measurable virtues? Business Ethics: A European Review, 24(S2), S115–S129.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosanas, J. M., & Velilla, M. (2003). Loyalty and trust in the ethical bases of organizations. Journal of Business Ethics, 44(1), 49–59.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sanz, P., & Fontrodona, J. (2019). Moderation as a moral competence: Integrating perspectives for a better understanding of temperance in the workplace. Journal of Business Ethics, 155(4), 981–994.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon, T. M. (1998). What we owe to each other. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Selznick, P. (2011). Leadership in administration: A sociological interpretation. New Orleans, LA: Quid Pro Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H. (1997). Administrative behavior (4th ed.). New York, NY: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sinnicks, M. (2014). Practices, governance, and politics: Applying MacIntyre's ethics to business. Business Ethics Quarterly, 24(2), 229–249.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sinnicks, M. (2018). The just world fallacy as a challenge to the business-as-community Thesis. Business & Society, 0007650318759486.

  • Sinnicks, M. (2019). Moral education at work: On the scope of MacIntyre’s concept of a practice. Journal of Business Ethics, 159(1), 105–118.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sison, A. J. G. (2018). Virtue ethics and natural law responses to human rights quandaries in business. Business and Human Rights Journal, 3(2), 211–232.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sison, A. J. G., Ferrero, I., & Guitián, G. (2016). Human dignity and the dignity of work: Insights from Catholic social teaching. Business Ethics Quarterly, 26(4), 503–528.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sison, A. J. G., & Fontrodona, J. (2012). The common good of the firm in the Aristotelian-Thomistic tradition. Business Ethics Quarterly, 22(2), 211–246.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, R. C. (1992). Corporate roles, personal virtues: An Aristotelian approach to business ethics. Business Ethics Quarterly, 2(3), 317–339.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, R. C. (1993). Ethics and excellence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, C. (1994). Justice after virtue. In J. Horton & S. Mendus (Eds.), After MacIntyre (pp. 16–43). Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Teece, D. J., Pisano, G., & Shuen, A. (1997). Dynamic capabilities and strategic management. Strategic Management Journal, 18(7), 509–533.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, M. (2004). What is it to wrong someone? A puzzle about justice. In R. J. Wallace, P. Pettit, S. Scheffler & M. Smith (Eds.), Reason and value: Themes from the moral philosophy of Joseph Raz. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, M. (2008). Life and action. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tsoukas, H. (2018a). Strategy and virtue: Developing strategy-as-practice through virtue ethics. Strategic Organization, 16(3), 323–351.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tsoukas, H. (2018b). Praxis, character, and competence: From a behavioral to a communitarian view of the firm. In M. Augier, C. Fang, & V. P. Rindova (Eds.), Behavioral strategy in perspective (pp. 181–194). Bingley, West Yorkshire, UK: Emerald Publishing Limited.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tsoukas, H., & Vladimirou, E. (2001). What is organizational knowledge? Journal of Management Studies, 38(7), 973–993.

    Google Scholar 

  • Upton, H. (2000). Right-based morality and Hohfeld's relations. The Journal of Ethics, 4(3), 237–256.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, M., 1947. The theory of economic and social organization. (A. M. Henderson & T. Parsons, Trans.. New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Werhane, P., Radin, T. J., & Bowie, N. E. (2004). Employment and employee rights. Hoboken, NJ: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • West, A. (2018). After virtue and accounting ethics. Journal of Business Ethics, 148(1), 21–36.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilkinson, A., Gollan, P. J., Marchington, M., & Lewin, D. (2010). Conceptualizing employee participation in organizations. In A. Wilkinson, P. J. Gollan, M. Marchington, & D. Lewin (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of participation in organizations (pp. 3–25). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, O. E. (1973). Markets and hierarchies: Some elementary considerations. The American Economic Review, 63(2), 316–325.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yeoman, R. (2014). Conceptualising meaningful work as a fundamental human need. Journal of Business Ethics, 125(2), 235–251.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Caleb Bernacchio.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The author declares that he has no conflict of interest.

Research Involving Human and Animal Participants

This article does not contain any studies with human participants or animals performed by any of the authors.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Bernacchio, C. Virtue Beyond Contract: A MacIntyrean Approach to Employee Rights. J Bus Ethics 171, 227–240 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-020-04435-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-020-04435-2

Keywords

Navigation