Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

A contextualist approach to functional localization in the brain

  • Published:
Biology & Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Functional localization has historically been one of the primary goals of neuroscience. There is still debate, however, about whether it is possible, and if so what kind of theories succeed at localization. I argue for a contextualist approach to localization. Most theorists assume that widespread contextual variability in function is fundamentally incompatible with functional decomposition in the brain, because contextualist accounts will fail to be generalizable and projectable. I argue that this assumption is misplaced. A properly articulated contextualism can ground successful theories of localization even without positing completely generalizable accounts. Via a case study from perceptual neuroscience, I suggest that there is strong evidence for contextual variation in the function of perceptual brain areas. I then outline a version of contextualism that is empirically adequate with respect to this data, and claim that it can still distinguish brain areas from each other according to their functional properties. Finally, I claim that the view does not fail the norms for good theory in the way that anticontextualists suppose. It is true that, on a contextualist view, we will not have theories that are completely generalizable and predictive. We can, however, have successful partial generalizations that structure ongoing investigation and lead to novel functional insight, and this success is sufficient to ground the project of functional localization.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Since I only discuss one brain area, it is of course possible that other parts of the brain will be less amenable to contextualist analysis. McCaffrey (2015) suggests such a view in his “functional heterogeneity hypothesis.” My goal here is to articulate contextualism for perceptual brain areas, which are important test cases for functional localization. How far the view extends is an empirical question, as McCaffrey notes.

  2. Out of the extant philosophical options, this characterization most resembles “systems” accounts of functions (Cummins 1975). As Craver (2007) notes, systems accounts normally must be supplemented with an account of causal relevance, to show which properties of the parts are actual components of the causal organization that produces the explanandum. In systems neuroscience, it is assumed that the electrical signaling activity of a part of the brain is its relevant causal contribution, and I will adopt this assumption.

  3. Functional decomposition is not the only explanatory goal for which we might discuss the parts of a system. We might, for instance, want to explain the evolutionary history of a brain area, or its morphological properties. But this kind of explanation is at least a primary goal of neuroscientists involved in pursuing localization.

  4. I take it that these are three core desiderata for theories of functional localization. I don’t claim that they are exhaustive, but they seem to capture relatively accurately the concerns that theorists have expressed.

  5. To be fair, Rathkopf is concerned with a particular form of functional explanation, namely descriptions that explain why a certain anatomical structure is present. He admits that context-sensitive descriptions might be useful for other purposes.

  6. Establishing a privileged correlation is by no means an easy matter. Perceptual neuroscientists have developed a variety of sophisticated strategies for arguing that one unique type of information is represented by a brain area in all cases, often despite seeming influence of other types on its responses. I present below the data for contextual variation that I take to best avoid the strategies, but I will not make the full argument here. I discuss the strategies in detail, and give arguments against them for these cases, in (Burnston 2015).

  7. Some areas are sub-divided into functionally specified parts. For instance, V1 is a single anatomical area, but comprises different parts specialized for representing wavelength, displacement, and oriented edges. V2 has a parallel internal organization. The hierarchy proposed by the MFH theory is posited to then separate these features into distinct areas corresponding to our standard perceptual attributives of motion, color, shape, etc. This sort of subdivision is entirely compatible with absolutism, so long as the distinct parts within the areas represent only one feature. Below I will explain that subdivision is not appropriate in the case of MT.

  8. For a review of these results, see (Dobkins and Albright 2004).

  9. This is based on the attendant assumption that motion perception follows the border with the smallest displacement at each time step, which is independently well-established (Dobkins and Albright 1994).

  10. One can compare this with non-categorical shifts, such as those posited by “gain-increase” mechanisms of attention, which suggest that top-down attention does not change what is represented, but simply heightens the response to a particular represented property (Treue and Trujillo 1999).

  11. This would occur in a circumstance where the moving stimulus was precisely at the plane of fixation. See Fig. 3.

  12. There have yet to be detailed studies, along the lines of Britten et al. (1996) or Dodd et al. (2001), establishing the functional use of this information. Given the progression of the field, however, and MT’s detailed responses to tilt and slant, it is reasonable to expect that such studies will discover the functional usefulness of these responses.

  13. Thanks to Nancy Cartwright for pushing me on the disposition objection. There is in fact, a third strategy, which attempts to save absolutism by searching for a deeper functional principle that explains all of the specific functions that an area like MT performs. Several absolutists (including some of those cited in the “Introduction” section) have argued that, rather than representing a specific type of information or contributing to a particular type of task, each neural area performs a particular type of computation in any context in which it functions. These views are still absolutist, in that they still posit univocal functions that are intended to account for all cases. I argue against this alternative form of absolutism in (Burnston 2016).

  14. To actually establish that V4 is not a feature-specific area would require a thorough analysis of the evidence, along the lines of what I gave above for MT. I won’t do so here; while I believe such an argument can be made, my primary interest in this section is to analyze the consequences for decomposition if both MT and V4 are genuinely context sensitive in their functioning.

  15. Importantly, this does not mean that contextualism is “unfalsifiable” in any interesting sense. Posits about particular conjuncts and how they differentiate between areas are highly falsifiable. See the discussion below.

  16. Strictly speaking, a contextualist view needn’t be unbounded. Functional properties could be context-sensitive and conjunctive even if it were possible to give a complete list of the conjuncts. There are two reasons for embracing unboundedness. First, since it is the strongest form of contextualism, avoiding the epistemic worries evinced by absolutists for this kind of view should heavily lessen the motivations for denying contextualism writ large. Second, I agree with Rathkopf that once we open our function ascriptions to contextual variation, it will be hard to know that we have a complete theory. At several times during investigation of MT, consensus views of its function have been overturned, and it is part of the appeal of contextualism that it has the epistemic modesty not to rule out this possibility a priori. Thanks to Gary Ebbs for pushing me to clarify this point.

  17. Thanks to Olivier Morin and Ben Sheredos for pressing the ecological validity objection.

References

  • Anderson ML (2010) Neural reuse: a fundamental organizational principle of the brain. Behav Brain Sci 33(4):245–266 (discussion 266-313)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anzai A, DeAngelis GC (2010) Neural computations underlying depth perception. Curr Opin Neurobiol 20(3):367–375

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel W, Richardson RC (1993) Discovering complexity: decomposition and localization as scientific research strategies. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Bergeron V (2007) Anatomical and functional modularity in cognitive science: shifting the focus. Philos Psychol 20(2):175–195

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Britten KH, Newsome WT, Shadlen MN, Celebrini S, Movshon JA (1996) A relationship between behavioral choice and the visual responses of neurons in macaque MT. Vis Neurosci 13:87–100

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burnston DC (2015) Perceptual Context and the Nature of Neural Function. Doctoral dissertation, University of California, San Diego

  • Burnston DC (2016) Computational neuroscience and localized neural function. Synthese. doi:10.1007/s11229-016-1099-8

  • Canolty RT, Ganguly K, Carmena JM (2012) Task-dependent changes in cross-level coupling between single neurons and oscillatory activity in multiscale networks. PLoS Comput Biol 8(12):e1002809

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cappelen H, Lepore E (2005) Insensitive semantics: a defense of semantic minimalism and speech act pluralism. Wiley, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Connor CE, Brincat SL, Pasupathy A (2007) Transformation of shape information in the ventral pathway. Curr Opin Neurobiol 17(2):140–147

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver CF (2007) Explaining the brain. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Craver CF, Darden L (2013) In search of mechanisms: discoveries across the life sciences. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cummins RC (1975) Functional analysis. J Philos 72(20):741–765

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeAngelis GC, Newsome WT (2004) Perceptual “read-out” of conjoined direction and disparity maps in extrastriate area MT. PLoS Biol 2:e77

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeAngelis GC, Cumming BG, Newsome WT (1998) Cortical area MT and the perception of stereoscopic depth. Nature 394(6694):677–680

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DeRose K (1992) Contextualism and knowledge attributions. Philos Phenomenol Res 52(4):913–929

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dobkins KR, Albright TD (1994) What happens if it changes color when it moves?: the nature of chromatic input to macaque visual area MT. J Neurosci 14(8):4854–4870

    Google Scholar 

  • Dobkins KR, Albright TD (2004) Merging processing streams: color cues for motion detection and interpretation. In: Chalupa LM, Werner JS (eds) The visual neurosciences. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 1217–1228

    Google Scholar 

  • Dobkins KR, Stoner GR, Albright TD (1998) Perceptual, oculomotor, and neural responses to moving color plaids. Perception 27:681–709

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dodd JV, Krug K, Cumming BG, Parker AJ (2001) Perceptually bistable three-dimensional figures evoke high choice probabilities in cortical area MT. J Neurosci 21(13):4809–4821

    Google Scholar 

  • Felleman DJ, Van Essen DC (1991) Distributed hierarchical processing in the primate cerebral cortex. Cereb Cortex 1(1):1–47

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klein C (2012) Cognitive ontology and region-versus network-oriented analyses. Philos Sci 79(5):952–960

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Livingstone M, Hubel D (1988) Segregation of form, color, movement, and depth: anatomy, physiology, and perception. Science 240(4853):740–749

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacFarlane J (2009) Nonindexical contextualism. Synthese 166(2):231–250

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maunsell JH, Van Essen DC (1983a) Functional properties of neurons in middle temporal visual area of the macaque monkey. I. Selectivity for stimulus direction, speed, and orientation. J Neurophysiol 49(5):1127–1147

    Google Scholar 

  • Maunsell JH, Van Essen DC (1983b) Functional properties of neurons in middle temporal visual area of the macaque monkey. II. Binocular interactions and sensitivity to binocular disparity. J Neurophysiol 49(5):1148–1167

    Google Scholar 

  • McCaffrey JB (2015) The brain’s heterogeneous functional landscape. Philos Sci 82(5):1010–1022

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McIntosh AR (2004) Contexts and catalysts: a resolution of the localization and integration of function in the brain. Neuroinformatics 2(2):175–182

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mishkin M, Ungerleider LG, Macko KA (1983) Object vision and spatial vision: two cortical pathways. Trends Neurosci 6:414–417

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Palanca BJA, DeAngelis GC (2003) Macaque middle temporal neurons signal depth in the absence of motion. J Neurosci 23(20):7647–7658

    Google Scholar 

  • Pessoa L (2014) Understanding brain networks and brain organization. Phys Life Rev 11(3):400–435

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Poldrack RA (2006) Can cognitive processes be inferred from neuroimaging data? Trends Cognit Sci 10(2):59–63

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Preyer G, Peter G (2005) Contextualism in philosophy: knowledge, meaning, and truth. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Price CJ, Friston KJ (2005) Functional ontologies for cognition: the systematic definition of structure and function. Cognit Neuropsychol 22(3):262–275

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rathkopf CA (2013) Localization and intrinsic function. Philos Sci 80(1):1–21

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rentzeperis I, Nikolaev AR, Kiper DC, van Leeuwen C (2014) Distributed processing of color and form in the visual cortex. Front Psychol 5:1–14

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roe AW, Chelazzi L, Connor CE, Conway BR, Fujita I, Gallant JL, Vanduffel W (2012) Toward a unified theory of visual area V4. Neuron 74(1):12–29

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sanada TM, Nguyenkim JD, DeAngelis GC (2012) Representation of 3-D surface orientation by velocity and disparity gradient cues in area MT. J Neurophysiol 107(8):2109–2122

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simon HA (1962) The architecture of complexity. In: Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society, pp 467–482

  • Stanley J (2005) Semantics in context. In: Preyer G, Peter G (eds) Contextualism in philosophy: knowledge, meaning, and truth. Clarendon Press, Oxford, pp 221–253

    Google Scholar 

  • Stein BE, Stanford TR (2008) Multisensory integration: current issues from the perspective of the single neuron. Nat Rev Neurosci 9(4):255–266

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Treue S, Trujillo JCM (1999) Feature-based attention influences motion processing gain in macaque visual cortex. Nature 399(6736):575–579

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Uka T, DeAngelis GC (2003) Contribution of middle temporal area to coarse depth discrimination: comparison of neuronal and psychophysical sensitivity. J Neurosci 23(8):3515–3530

    Google Scholar 

  • Watrous AJ, Fell J, Ekstrom AD, Axmacher N (2015) More than spikes: common oscillatory mechanisms for content specific neural representations during perception and memory. Curr Opin Neurobiol 31:33–39

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zeki SM (1974) Functional organization of a visual area in the posterior bank of the superior temporal sulcus of the rhesus monkey. J Physiol 236(3):549–573

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zeki SM (1978) Functional specialisation in the visual cortex of the rhesus monkey. Nature 274(5670):423–428

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zeki S, Watson J, Lueck C, Friston KJ, Kennard C, Frackowiak R (1991) A direct demonstration of functional specialization in human visual cortex. J Neurosci 11(3):641–649

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank William Bechtel, Jonathan Cohen, Rick Grush, Thomas Albright, and John Serences for invaluable advice during the development of this project. Thanks also to Ann-Sophie Barwich, Olivier Morin, Isabella Sarto-Jackson, and Ben Sheredos for extremely helpful comments on an earlier version of the manuscript. This material was presented to colloquia audiences at Tulane University and Indiana University, Bloomington, and I am grateful to both for helpful discussion.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Daniel C. Burnston.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Burnston, D.C. A contextualist approach to functional localization in the brain. Biol Philos 31, 527–550 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-016-9526-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-016-9526-2

Keywords

Navigation