Skip to main content
Log in

On the terminology of economic design: a critical assessment and some proposals

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Review of Economic Design Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The purpose of this paper is to provide a critical examination of some of the terminology that is common in economic design and to suggest ways in which it can be improved.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. It is also confusing to refer to an object allocation problem in which there is only one copy of each object as a school choice problem.

  2. It is important to realize that the benefit comes from the fact that it is the same good that plays that special role for all agents. Having good 1 as the special good for agent and good 2 as the special good for agent 2 would not help. This is why it is preferable to speak of quasi-linear economies, not of quasi-linear preferences.

  3. The fact that the allocation obtained by applying Gale’s algorithm can also be obtained as an equilibrium of something that looks like a market is a mathematical coincidence that has no bearing to the issue at hand, especially because the price-taking behavior would hardly be justified given the unique character of each of the objects owned by the various agents.

  4. The fact that the rule that is arguably most central to handle object-reallocation problem, the so-called top-trading-cycle rule, can be given a market interpretation is irrelevant. There is no reason why a class of problems should be named after a rule that is particular relevance to it.

  5. In “Consistency in generalized economies” (Thomson 1992, 2012), I used the expression “generalized economies” to refer to what I am here proposing to call “mixed-ownership economies”. The term “generalized” is not enough, as it provides no clue as to the type of generalization that is involved.

  6. This is the earliest reference that I could find.

  7. Admittedly, the term “rule” has other meanings. For instance, in the description of an algorithm, it can legitimately be used to designate what is to be done in each of several possible cases that are enumerated. This usage is also common in implementation theory; different cases are distinguished in describing strategy profiles and in each case, a “rule” is applied to determine the outcome.

  8. We noted earlier than the research program associated with Hurwicz’s name has to do with more than the identification of processes that lead to good outcomes, but also with the identification of desirable mappings from economic environments to outcome spaces. However a primary concern of Hurwicz’s as well as of the writers in the so-called socialist controversy indeed was processes. This concern was reflected in the focus of that literature on planning procedures.

  9. By this expression, I mean the problem of either ranking the alternatives in a set or selecting one of them as a function of the list of the preferences of a group of agents, this set not being endowed with any particular structure.

  10. I have had a number of conversations about the school choice problem and a very frequent response when the Boston mechanism was brought up has been “I have attended many presentations where it was discussed but I don’t remember the definition”. All of these conversations were with people who would state the definition of the deferred acceptance rule with no hesitation and I have no doubt that any of them would immediately guess what the expression immediate acceptance could refer to, or at least would easily remember it if presented with the definition.

  11. By definition, the last stage is defined to be the one at which all students are accepted.

  12. It does happen and the possibility underlies the proofs of some characterizations. For example, it is an important step in Schummer’s (1997, 1999) characterizations of the strategy-proof selections from the efficiency correspondence on domains of private good economies (or domains of public good economies) with strictly monotonic and linear preferences. (Indeed, a monotonic transformation at an efficient point is a monotonic transformation at each other efficient point.)

  13. Perhaps we could distinguish between “local” invariance, and “global” invariance. For the property under discussion here, we could say that a rule is “locally invariant” if the following holds: at each point that it selects for a profile, if preferences are subjected to monotonic transformations at this point, then the point is still selected for the new profile. By contrast, a rule would satisfy a “global invariance” property if the entire set of allocations selected for a profile would still be chosen after preferences have been subjected to some transformation: the transformation would be defined in relation to that entire set.

  14. In the context of classical demand theory, the expression “the law of demand” does not seem well justified either since preference relations that violate it are certainly not thought to be pathological.

References

  • Abdulkadiroğlu A, Sönmez T (1999) House allocation with existing tenants. J Econ Theory 88:233–260

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Abdulkadiroğlu A, Sönmez T (2003) Ordinal efficiency and dominated sets of assignments. J Econ Theory 112:157–172

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Adachi H (2000) On a characterization of stable matchings. Econ Lett 68:43–49

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Adachi T (2010) The uniform rule with several commodities: a generalization of Sprumont’s characterization. J Math Econ 46:952–964

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alcalde J (1996) Implementation of stable solutions to marriage problems. J Econ Theory 69:240–254

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alkan A (2002) A class of multipartner matching markets with a strong lattice structure. Econ Theory 19:737–746

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alkan A, Demange G, Gale D (1991) Fair allocation of indivisible goods and criteria of justice. Econometrica 59:1023–1039

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Amorós P (2002) Single-peaked preferences with several commodities. Soc Choice Welf 19:57–67

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Balinski M, Sönmez T (1999) A tale of two mechanisms: student placement. J Econ Theory 84:73–94

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barberà S, Sonnenschein H, Zhou L (1991) Voting by committees. Econometrica 59:595–609

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barberà S, Jackson M, Neme A (1997) Strategy-proof allotment rules. Games Econ Behav 18:1–21

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bénassy JP (1982) The economics of market disequilibrium. Academic Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Bogomolnaia A, Moulin H (2001) A new solution to the random assignment problem. J Econ Theory 100:295–328

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Border K, Jordan J (1983) Straightforward elections, unanimity and phantom voters. Rev Econ Stud 50:153–170

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Camus A (1944) Sur une philosophie de l’expression. Poésie

  • Chen Y, Kesten O (2017) Chinese college admissions and school choice reforms: a theoretical analysis. J Polit Econ 125:99–139

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cho J (2018) Probabilistic assignment: an extension approach. Soc Choice Welf (forthcoming)

  • Cho J, Thomson W (2011) On the existence of the uniform rule to more than one commodity: existence and maximality results. Mimeo, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Dasgupta P, Hammond P, Maskin E (1979) The implementation of social choice rules. Rev Econ Stud 46:153–170

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Doğan B, Doğan S, Yıldız K (2018) A new ex-ante efficiency criterion and implications for the probabilistic serial mechanism. J Econ Theory 175:178–200

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dur U (2015) The modified Boston mechanism. Mimeo, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Ehlers L, Peters H, Storcken T (2002) Strategy-proof probabilistic decision schemes for one-dimensional single-peaked preferences. J Econ Theory 105:408–434

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Farquharson R (1956) Straightforwardness in voting procedures. Oxf Econ Pap 8:80–89

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feldman A (1979) Manipulation and the Pareto rule. J Econ Theory 21:473–482

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gärdenfors P (1977) A concise proof of theorem on manipulation of social choice functions. Pub Choice 32:137–142

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harless P (2015) A school choice compromise: between immediate and deferred acceptance. Mimeo, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurwicz L (1972) On informationally decentralized systems. In: McGuire CB, Radner R (eds) Chapter 14 in decision and organisation. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, pp 297–336

    Google Scholar 

  • Ju B-G (2005) A characterization of plurality-like rules based on non-manipulability, restricted efficiency, and anonymity. Int J Game Theory 33:335–354

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kasajima Y (2013) Probabilistic assignment of indivisible goods with single-peaked preferences. Soc Choice Welf 41:203–215

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klaus B (2008) The coordinate-wise core for multiple-type housing markets is second-best incentive compatible. J Math Econ 44:919–924

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Manea M (2008) Random serial dictatorship and ordinally efficient contracts. Int J Game Theory 36:489–496

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Manjunath V (2014) Efficient and strategy-proof social choice when preferences are single-dipped. Int J Game Theory 43:579–597

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maskin E (1999) Nash equilibrium and welfare optimality. Rev Econ Stud 66:83–114 (first circulated in 1977)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McLennan A (2002) Ordinal efficiency and the polyhedral separating hyperplane theorem. J Econ Theory 105:29–54

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mennle T, Seuken S (2014) The naive versus the adaptive Boston mechanism. Mimeo, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Miyagawa E (2004) Strategy-proofness for the reallocation of multiple types of indivisible goods. Mimeo, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Monte D, Tumennasan N (2013) Matching with quorums. Econ Lett 120:14–17

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morimoto S, Serizawa S, Ching S (2013) A characterization of the uniform rule with several commodities and agents. Soc Choice Welf 40:871–911

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moulin H (1980) On strategy-proofness and single peakedness. Pub Choice 35:437–455

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moulin H (1984) Generalized Condorcet-winners for single-peaked and single-plateau preferences. Soc Choice Welf 1:127–147

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Muller E, Satterthwaite M (1977) The equivalence of strong positive association and strategy-proofness. J Econ Theory 14:412–418

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Murakami S (1968) Logic and social choice. Routledge & Kegan Paul, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Nash JF (1950) The bargaining problem. Econometrica 28:155–162

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pazner E, Wesley E (1977) Stability of social choices in infinitely large societies. J Econ Theory 14:252–262

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pinker S (2014) The sense of style: the thinking person’s guide to writing in the 21st century. Penguin, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Schummer J (1997) Strategy-proofness versus efficiency on restricted domains of exchange economies. Soc Choice Welf 14:47–56

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schummer J (1999) Strategy-proofness versus efficiency for small domains of preferences over public goods. Econ Theory 13:709–722

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapley L, Scarf H (1974) On cores and indivisibility. J Math Econ 1:23–28

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapley LS, Shubik M (1972) The assignment game I: the core. Int J Game Theory 1:111–130

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Su F (1999) Rental harmony: Sperner’s lemma in fair division. Am Math Mon 106:930–942

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tadenuma K, Thomson W (1993) The fair allocation of an indivisible good when monetary compensations are possible. Math Soc Sci 25:117–132

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomson W (1992) Consistency in exchange economies. Mimeo, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomson W (2006) Airport problems and cost allocation. Mimeo, New York (revised May 2017)

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomson W (2012) On the axiomatics of resource allocation: interpreting the consistency principle. Econ Philos 28:385–421

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomson W, Myerson RB (1980) Monotonicity and independence axioms. Int J Game Theory 9:37–49

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Velez R (2016) Fairness and externalities. Theor Econ 11:381–410

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yılmaz Ö (2010) The probabilistic serial mechanism with private endowments. Games Econ Behav 69:475–491

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to William Thomson.

Additional information

Thanks to Battal Doğan, Eun Jeong Heo, Alexander Nichifor, Szilvia Pápai, and Utku Ünver for their comments.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Thomson, W. On the terminology of economic design: a critical assessment and some proposals. Rev Econ Design 22, 67–99 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10058-018-0210-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10058-018-0210-7

Keywords

JEL Classifications

Navigation