Skip to main content
Log in

Tournament solutions based on cooperative game theory

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
International Journal of Game Theory Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

A tournament can be represented as a set of candidates and the results from pairwise comparisons of the candidates. In our setting, candidates may form coalitions. The candidates can choose to fix who wins the pairwise comparisons within their coalition. A coalition is winning if it can guarantee that a candidate from this coalition will win each pairwise comparison. This approach divides all coalitions into two groups and is, hence, a simple game. We show that each minimal winning coalition consists of a certain uncovered candidate and its dominators. We then apply solution concepts developed for simple games and consider the desirability relation and the power indices which preserve this relation. The tournament solution, defined as the maximal elements of the desirability relation, is a good way to select the strongest candidates. The Shapley–Shubik index, the Penrose–Banzhaf index, and the nucleolus are used to measure the power of the candidates. We also extend this approach to the case of weak tournaments.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. About Condorcet methods, we recommend the book chapter by Zwicker (2016).

  2. A comprehensive study of simple games can be found in the books by Taylor and Zwicker (1999) and Felsenthal and Machover (1998).

  3. Alonso-Meijide et al. (2013) and Bertini et al. (2013) provide recent reviews on power indices.

  4. In the case of simple games, the Shapley value (Shapley 1953) is known as the Shapley–Shubik index.

  5. The uncovered set and the covering relation were introduced independently by Fishburn (1977) and Miller (1980).

  6. The influence (or desirability) relation was introduced by Isbell (1958).

  7. We slightly abuse the notation by denoting subtournaments as (BH) instead of \((B,H\Vert _B)\).

  8. We use \(A {\setminus } a\) for \(A {\setminus } \{a\}\), \(D(a)\cup a\) for \(D(a)\cup \{a\}\).

  9. We denote \(B'\) as the complement \(A{\setminus } B\) of B in A.

  10. We connect this definition with the concepts of \(\alpha \) and \(\beta \)-effectivity (Abdou and Keiding 1991). Consider the tournament solution that chooses a Condorcet winner, whenever it exists, or all the candidates, otherwise. For a coalition \(B\subset A\), we say that B is \(\alpha \)-effective if there is a strategy of B such that the choice set is included in B for each strategy of the countercoalition \(B'\). We say that B is \(\beta \)-effective if for each strategy of \(B'\), there is a strategy of B such that the choice set is included in B. In our setting, the following three conditions are equivalent: (1) B is winning, (2) B is \(\alpha \)-effective, (3) B is \(\beta \)-effective.

  11. We use ac and bde as abbreviations for the coalitions \(\{a,c\}\) and \(\{b,d,e\}\), respectively.

  12. Moreover, candidate a is uniquely dominant because \(a\succ b\), coalition ab is winning, and this simple game is proper; about dominant candidates, we recommend Peleg (1981).

  13. The tournament equilibrium set and the minimal extending set are rare exceptions; both do not satisfy monotonicity. See Brandt et al. (2013, 2017), respectively.

  14. Note that such well-known solutions as the Slater set, the Banks set, the minimal extending set and the tournament equilibrium set cannot be computed in polynomial time; we recommend Brandt et al. (2016a) and Hudry (2009) for surveys on the complexity of tournament solutions.

  15. Recently, Bachrach et al. (2010) suggest randomized methods to approximate the Penrose–Banzhaf index and the Shapley–Shubik index, in any simple game.

  16. Monotonicity is not a straightforward property. For instance, maximal lotteries, the most famous solution based on non-cooperative game theory, do not satisfy monotonicity if one considers the probabilities as the power of candidates. Moreover, selecting those candidates with maximal probabilities results in a non-monotonic tournament solution (Laslier 1997).

  17. This example also shows that the maximal Shapley value, the maximal Banzhaf value, and the influential set are not composition-consistent tournament solutions, see Brandt et al. (2016a) and Laffond et al. (1993) for the definitions.

  18. The nucleolus belongs to the kernel. Maschler and Peleg (1966) proved that the influence relation is preserved by each score vector belonging to the kernel.

  19. Also, this example illustrates that the support of the nucleolus can be strictly smaller than the Banks set (Banks 1985), \(\{a, b, c \}=NU(T) \subset BA(T)=\{a, b, c, d\}\).

  20. This example also illustrates that the support of the nucleolus can be strictly smaller than the minimal covering set introduced by Dutta (1988), \( A{\setminus } a10 = NU(T) \subset MC(T) = A\).

  21. A general way is the so-called conservative extension (Brandt et al. 2016a).

  22. It is known as the McKelvey uncovered set (McKelvey 1986). Bordes (1983) denotes \(\gamma \) the covering relation and \(F_g\) the uncovered set; he shows that \(F_g\) satisfies a series of positive properties in comparison with other generalizations for weak tournaments. Brandt et al. (2016b) show that the set of necessarily Pareto optimal candidates coincides with the McKelvey uncovered set. For a comprehensive overview of the theory of covering relations, we recommend Duggan (2013).

  23. In weak tournaments, v is not necessarily superadditive. For example, in the case of three candidates and an adjacency matrix such that \(H(a,b)=H(a,c)=H(b,c)=1/2\), it is clear that \(v(a)=v(b)=v(c)=1/2\) and hence \(v(a)+v(b)+v(c)>v(A)\).

References

  • Abdou J, Keiding H (1991) Effectivity functions in social choice. Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Alonso-Meijide JM, Casas-Méndez B, Fiestras-Janeiro MG (2013) A review of some recent results on power indices. In: Holler MJ, Nurmi H (eds) Power, voting, and voting power: 30 years after. Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg, pp 231–245

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Altman A, Tennenholtz M (2005) Ranking systems: the pagerank axioms. In: 6th ACM Conference on Electronic Commerce. ACM, New York, pp 1–8

  • Altman A, Procaccia AD, Tennenholtz M (2009) Nonmanipulable selections from a tournament. In: 21st international joint conference on artifical intelligence, Morgan Kaufmann Publishers Inc., San Francisco, pp 27–32

  • Amer R, Giménez JM, Magaña A (2012) Accessibility measures to nodes of directed graphs using solutions for generalized cooperative games. Math Methods Oper Res 75(1):105–134

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anesi V (2012) A new old solution for weak tournaments. Soc Choice Welf 39(4):919–930

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bachrach Y, Markakis E, Resnick E, Procaccia AD, Rosenschein JS, Saberi A (2010) Approximating power indices: theoretical and empirical analysis. Auton Agents Multi Agent Syst 20(2):105–122

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Banks JS (1985) Sophisticated voting outcomes and agenda control. Soc Choice Welf 1(4):295–306

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Banzhaf JF III (1965) Weighted voting doesn’t work: a mathematical analysis. Rutgers L Rev 19:317–343

    Google Scholar 

  • Bertini C, Freixas J, Gambarelli G, Stach I (2013) Comparing power indices. Int Game Theory Rev 15(2):1340,004

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Besley T, Coate S (1997) An economic model of representative democracy. Q J Econ 112(1):85–114

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bordes G (1983) On the possibility of reasonable consistent majoritarian choice: some positive results. J Econ Theory 31(1):122–132

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brandt F (2011) Minimal stable sets in tournaments. J Econ Theory 146(4):1481–1499

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brandt F, Fischer F (2007) Pagerank as a weak tournament solution. In: Deng X, Graham FC (eds) Internet and network economics. Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg, pp 300–305

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Brandt F, Chudnovsky M, Kim I, Liu G, Norin S, Scott A, Seymour P, Thomassé S (2013) A counterexample to a conjecture of Schwartz. Soc Choice Welf 40(3):739–743

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brandt F, Brill M, Harrenstein P (2016a) Tournament solutions. In: Brandt F, Conitzer V, Endriss U, Lang J, Procaccia AD (eds) Handbook of computational social choice. Cambridge University Press, New York, pp 57–84

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Brandt F, Geist C, Harrenstein P (2016b) A note on the McKelvey uncovered set and pareto optimality. Soc Choice Welf 46(1):81–91

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brandt F, Harrenstein P, Seedig HG (2017) Minimal extending sets in tournaments. Math Soc Sci 87:55–63

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chen X, Deng X, Liu BJ (2011) On incentive compatible competitive selection protocols. Algorithmica 61(2):447–462

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Duggan J (2013) Uncovered sets. Soc Choice Welf 41(3):489–535

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dutta B (1988) Covering sets and a new Condorcet choice correspondence. J Econ Theory 44(1):63–80

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dutta B, Jackson MO, Le Breton M (2001) Strategic candidacy and voting procedures. Econometrica 69(4):1013–1037

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Everett MG, Borgatti SP (1999) The centrality of groups and classes. J Math Soc 23(3):181–201

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Faliszewski P, Gourvès L, Lang J, Lesca J, Monnot J (2016) How hard is it for a party to nominate an election winner? In: Proceedings of the twenty-fifth international joint conference on artificial intelligence, AAAI Press, IJCAI’16, pp 257–263

  • Felsenthal DS, Machover M (1998) The measurement of voting power. Theory and practice, problems and paradoxes. Edward Elgar, Cheltenham

    Google Scholar 

  • Fishburn PC (1977) Condorcet social choice functions. SIAM J Appl Math 33(3):469–489

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fishburn PC (1984) Probabilistic social choice based on simple voting comparisons. Rev Econ Stud 51(4):683–692

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fisher DC, Ryan J (1995) Tournament games and positive tournaments. J Graph Theory 19(2):217–236

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freixas J, Pons M (2008) Circumstantial power: optimal persuadable voters. Eur J Oper Res 186(3):1114–1126

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Good IJ (1971) A note on Condorcet sets. Public Choice 10(1):97–101

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guajardo M, Jörnsten K (2015) Common mistakes in computing the nucleolus. Eur J Oper Res 241(3):931–935

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hudry O (2009) A survey on the complexity of tournament solutions. Math Soc Sci 57(3):292–303

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Isbell JR (1958) A class of simple games. Duke Math J 25(3):423–439

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirsch W, Langner J (2010) Power indices and minimal winning coalitions. Soc Choice Welf 34(1):33–46

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kondratev A, Mazalov V (2017) A ranking procedure with the Shapley value. In: Nguyen NT, Tojo S, Nguyen LM, Trawiński B (eds) Intelligent information and database systems. Springer, Cham, pp 691–700

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kreweras G (1965) Aggregation of preference orderings. In: Mathematics and Social Sciences I: Proceedings of the seminars of Menthon–Saint-Bernard, France (1–27 July 1960) and of Gösing, Austria (3–27 July 1962), pp 73–79

  • Laffond G, Laslier JF, Le Breton M (1993) The bipartisan set of a tournament game. Games Econ Behav 5(1):182–201

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lange F, Kóczy LÁ (2013) Power indices expressed in terms of minimal winning coalitions. Social Choice Welf 41(2):281–292

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laslier JF (1997) Tournament solutions and majority voting. Springer, Berlin

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Maschler M (1992) The bargaining set, kernel, and nucleolus. In: Aumann R, Hart S (eds) Handbook of game theory with economic applications, vol 1. Elsevier, New York, pp 591–667

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Maschler M, Peleg B (1966) A characterization, existence proof and dimension bounds for the kernel of a game. Pac J Math 18(2):289–328

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mazalov V (2014) Mathematical game theory and applications. Wiley, Hoboken

    Google Scholar 

  • McKelvey RD (1986) Covering, dominance, and institution-free properties of social choice. Am J Polit Sci 30(2):283–314

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michalak TP, Aadithya KV, Szczepanski PL, Ravindran B, Jennings NR (2013) Efficient computation of the Shapley value for game-theoretic network centrality. J Artif Intell Res 46:607–650

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller NR (1980) A new solution set for tournaments and majority voting: further graph-theoretical approaches to the theory of voting. Am J Polit Sci 24(1):68–96

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Montero M (2013) On the nucleolus as a power index. In: Holler MJ, Nurmi H (eds) Power, voting, and voting power: 30 years after. Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg, pp 283–299

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Osborne MJ, Slivinski A (1996) A model of political competition with citizen-candidates. Q J Econ 111(1):65–96

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peleg B (1981) Coalition formation in simple games with dominant players. Int J Game Theory 10(1):11–33

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Penrose LS (1946) The elementary statistics of majority voting. J R Stat Soc 109(1):53–57

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • del Pozo M, Manuel C, González-Arangüena E, Owen G (2011) Centrality in directed social networks. a game theoretic approach. Soc Netw 33(3):191–200

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell T, Walsh T (2009) Manipulating tournaments in cup and round robin competitions. In: Rossi F, Tsoukias A (eds) Algorithm Decis Theory. Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg, pp 26–37

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Schmeidler D (1969) The nucleolus of a characteristic function game. SIAM J Appl Math 17(6):1163–1170

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz T (1972) Rationality and the myth of the maximum. Nous 6(2):97–117

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapley LS (1953) A value for n-person games. In: Kuhn HW, Tucker AW (eds) Contributions to the Theory of Games II. Princeton University Press, Princeton, pp 307–317

    Google Scholar 

  • Subochev A, Aleskerov F, Pislyakov V (2018) Ranking journals using social choice theory methods: a novel approach in bibliometrics. J Inf 12(2):416–429

    Google Scholar 

  • Szczepański PL, Michalak TP, Rahwan T (2016) Efficient algorithms for game-theoretic betweenness centrality. Artif Intell 231:39–63

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tarkowski MK, Michalak TP, Rahwan T, Wooldridge M (2018) Game-theoretic network centrality: a review. arXiv:180100218v1

  • Taylor AD, Zwicker WS (1999) Simple games: desirability relations, trading. Princeton University Press, Pseudoweightings

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Den Brink R, Borm P (2002) Digraph competitions and cooperative games. Theory Decis 53(4):327–342

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Den Brink R, Gilles RP (2000) Measuring domination in directed networks. Soc Netw 22(2):141–157

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vartiainen H (2015) Dynamic stable set as a tournament solution. Soc Choice Welf 45(2):309–327

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wolsey LA (1976) The nucleolus and kernel for simple games or special valid inequalities for 0–1 linear integer programs. Int J Game Theory 5(4):227–238

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zwicker WS (2016) Introduction to the theory of voting. In: Brandt F, Conitzer V, Endriss U, Lang J, Procaccia AD (eds) Handbook of computational social choice. Cambridge University Press, New York, pp 23–56

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We are grateful to Jennifer Rontganger (WZB Berlin Social Science Center) and Alexander Mazurov for help with language editing. We thank Elena Yanovskaya, Alexander Nesterov, Artem Sedakov and Nadezhda Smirnova for helpful comments on the manuscript.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Aleksei Y. Kondratev.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Kondratev was supported from the Basic Research Program of the National Research University Higher School of Economics and by the Russian Foundation for Basic Research (project 18-31-00055). Mazalov was supported by the Russian Science Foundation (project 17-11-01079) and by the Shandong Province “Double-Hundred Talent Plan” (No. WST2017009)

Appendix

Appendix

Proof of Lemma 1

We demonstrate that if candidate \(a\in UC\) then \(a\cup {\overline{D}}(a)\) is a minimal winning coalition. Indeed, \(a\cup {\overline{D}}(a)\) is winning because a dominates D(a). Using the principle of contradiction, assume that there exists a coalition \(B \subset a \cup {\overline{D}}(a)\) such that \(B \ne a \cup {\overline{D}}(a)\) and B is winning. Then a certain candidate \(b\in B\) dominates the countercoalition \(B'\) such that \(D(a)\subset B'\) and \(D(a) \ne B'\). Therefore, \(b \ne a\), \(b\in {\overline{D}}(a)\) and b dominates \(a\cup D(a)\). Hence, b covers a, which contradicts \(a\in UC\).

On the other hand, consider a candidate \(a\notin B\), a minimal winning coalition \(a \cup B\) and its countercoalition \(B'{\setminus } a\) such that a dominates \(B'{\setminus } a\). Suppose that there exists a candidate \(b\in B\) dominated by a. Then, the coalition \(a \cup B {\setminus } b\) is also winning, which contradicts the minimality of \(a \cup B\). Therefore, B dominates a, and \(B={\overline{D}}(a)\). If candidate a were covered by a certain candidate \(b\in B={\overline{D}}(a)\), then b would dominate \(B'\), and B would be winning, which contradicts the minimality of \(a \cup B\). Hence, a belongs to UC. \(\square \)

Lemma 3

For a certain pair of candidates \(\{a,b\}\) and each coalition \(K\subset A{\setminus } \{a,b\}\), let characteristic functions v and \({\widehat{v}}\) satisfy the conditions

$$\begin{aligned} v(K)= & {} {\widehat{v}}(K), \quad v(K\cup b)\ge {\widehat{v}}(K\cup b), \\ v(K\cup a)\le & {} {\widehat{v}}(K\cup a), \quad v(K\cup a \cup b) = {\widehat{v}}(K\cup a \cup b). \end{aligned}$$

Then, the transition from v to \({\widehat{v}}\) does not decrease the Shapley value \(\varphi _a\) for candidate a and also does not increase the Shapley value \(\varphi _b\) for candidate b.

For every other candidate \(c\in A{\setminus } \{a,b\}\), the Shapley value increment \(\varphi _c({\widehat{v}})-\varphi _c(v)\) is not greater than the increment \(\varphi _a({\widehat{v}})-\varphi _a(v)\) and not smaller than the increment \(\varphi _b({\widehat{v}})-\varphi _b(v)\).

Hence, the transition from v to \({\widehat{v}}\) does not reduce the ordinal rank of candidate a and also does not raise the ordinal rank of candidate b.

Proof

By the hypotheses of this lemma and formula (3), the Shapley value for candidate a does not decrease while for candidate b it does not increase.

Now, demonstrate that for every other candidate \(c\in A{\setminus } \{a,b\}\), the Shapley value increment does not exceed that for a. According to the hypotheses of Lemma 3, we have the inequalities

$$\begin{aligned} v(K \cup a) \le {\widehat{v}}(K\cup a), \quad v(K \cup c) \ge {\widehat{v}}(K\cup c) \quad \text{ for } \text{ each } \quad K\subset A{\setminus } \{a,c\}. \end{aligned}$$

Therefore,

$$\begin{aligned} \varphi _a({\widehat{v}})-\varphi _c({\widehat{v}})= & {} \sum _{K\subset A{\setminus } \{a,c\}} \frac{k!(m-k-2)!}{(m-1)!} \left( {\widehat{v}}(K\cup a)-{\widehat{v}}(K\cup c)\right) \ge \\\ge & {} \sum _{K\subset A{\setminus } \{a,c\}} \frac{k!(m-k-2)!}{(m-1)!} \left( v(K\cup a)-v(K\cup c)\right) = \varphi _a(v)-\varphi _c(v), \end{aligned}$$

whence it follows that \(\varphi _a({\widehat{v}})-\varphi _a(v)\ge \varphi _c({\widehat{v}})-\varphi _c(v).\)

In a similar fashion, we receive the inequalities

$$\begin{aligned} v(K \cup c) \le {\widehat{v}}(K\cup c), \quad v(K \cup b) \ge {\widehat{v}}(K\cup b) \quad \text{ for } \text{ each } \quad K\subset A{\setminus } \{b,c\}. \end{aligned}$$

As a result,

$$\begin{aligned} \varphi _c({\widehat{v}})-\varphi _b({\widehat{v}})= & {} \sum _{K\subset A{\setminus } \{b,c\}} \frac{k!(m-k-2)!}{(m-1)!} \left( {\widehat{v}}(K\cup c)-{\widehat{v}}(K\cup b)\right) \ge \\\ge & {} \sum _{K\subset A{\setminus } \{b,c\}} \frac{k!(m-k-2)!}{(m-1)!} \left( v(K\cup c)-v(K\cup b)\right) = \varphi _c(v)-\varphi _b(v), \end{aligned}$$

which directly gives \(\varphi _c({\widehat{v}})-\varphi _c(v) \ge \varphi _b({\widehat{v}})-\varphi _b(v)\). \(\square \)

Remark 3

Lemma 3 remains in force for the Banzhaf value (5). The proof is analogous. Really, for each candidate \(c\in A{\setminus } \{a,b\}\),

$$\begin{aligned} {\widetilde{\beta }}_a({\widehat{v}})-{\widetilde{\beta }}_c({\widehat{v}})= & {} 2 \sum _{K\subset A{\setminus } \{a,c\}} \left( {\widehat{v}}(K\cup a)-{\widehat{v}}(K\cup c)\right) \ge \\\ge & {} 2 \sum _{K\subset A{\setminus } \{a,c\}} \left( v(K\cup a)-v(K\cup c)\right) = {\widetilde{\beta }}_a(v)-{\widetilde{\beta }}_c(v), \end{aligned}$$

By analogy, \({\widetilde{\beta }}_a({\widehat{v}})-{\widetilde{\beta }}_b({\widehat{v}})\ge {\widetilde{\beta }}_a(v)-{\widetilde{\beta }}_b(v) \).

Lemma 4

For each weak tournament \(T=(A,H)\), the Shapley value \(\varphi (A,H)\) satisfies the following properties:

  1. (1)

    For any candidate a, the Shapley value is \(\varphi _a=1\) if and only if \(a\in CW(A,H)\) is the Condorcet winner in A;

  2. (2)

    For each candidate \(b\in A{\setminus } TC\), the Shapley value is \(\varphi _b=0\) and hence \(\varphi _{+}\subset TC\);

  3. (3)

    The Shapley value remains the same after removing any candidate that receives zero Shapley value, that is, \(\varphi _a(A,H)=\varphi _a(A{\setminus } b, H)\) for each pair \(\{a, b\}\), whenever \(\varphi _b (A,H) =0\) and \(a\in A{\setminus } b\);

  4. (4)

    The support of the Shapley value is \(\varphi _{+} = MNL\).

Proof

(1) Let candidate \(a\in CW(A,H)\) be the Condorcet winner in A. As is easily seen, the optimal strategy of the coalition that contains a is to nominate him. Therefore, \(v(B)=1\) if \(a\in B\), and \(v(B)=0\) if \(a\notin B\). Subsequently, the contribution of candidate a to each coalition is 1, and \(\varphi _a=1\).

We prove the converse result by contradiction. Suppose that, in a certain weak tournament, \(a\notin CW(A,H)\). Then, \(v(A{\setminus } a)\ge 1/2\) and \(v(A)-v(A{\setminus } a) = 1 -v(A{\setminus } a) \le 1/2\). This inequality implies \(\varphi _a < 1\).

(2) Consider the game of an arbitrary coalition \(B \subset A\) against the countercoalition \(B'=A{\setminus } B\); in the payoff matrix of this game, the rows and columns for players \(a\in TC\) dominate the rows and columns for players \(b\in A{\setminus } TC\). Take arbitrary \(b\in A{\setminus } TC, B\subset A{\setminus } b, K=B'{\setminus } b\), the payoff matrix in the game of the coalition \(B\cup b\) against the countercoalition K that is defined by

and also the payoff matrix in the game of the coalition B against the countercoalition \(K\cup b\) that is defined by

Introduce the notation \(B_1=B\cap TC=\{b^1_1,\ldots ,b^1_l\}\), \(B_2=B\cap (A{\setminus } TC)=\{b^2_1,\ldots ,b^2_p\}\), \(K_1=K\cap TC=\{k^1_1,\ldots ,k^1_r\}\), and \(K_2=K\cap (A{\setminus }{\setminus } TC)=\{k^2_1,\ldots ,k^2_t\}\). If \(B_1=\emptyset \), then \(v(B)=v(B\cup b)=0\). If \(B_1 \ne \emptyset \) and \(K_1=\emptyset \), then \(v(B)=v(B\cup b)=1\). If \(B_1 \ne \emptyset \) and \(K_1 \ne \emptyset \), then in both games the dominating strategies are from the sets \(B_1\) and \(K_1\), which means that \(v(B)=v(B\cup b)\).

(3) Consider any candidate b with zero Shapley value, \(\varphi _b =0\). Thus, for each coalition \(K\subset A{\setminus } b\) we have \(v(K\cup b) - v(K) =0\). Let \({\widehat{v}}\) be the characteristic function of the weak tournament \((A{\setminus } b, H)\). Then, we have the following inequalities

$$\begin{aligned} v(K\cup b)= & {} \max _{c\in K \cup b}{\min _{d\in A{\setminus } b \setminus K}{H(c,d)}} \ge {\widehat{v}}(K) = \max _{c\in K}{\min _{d\in A{\setminus } b \setminus K}{H(c,d)}} \ge \\\ge & {} v(K) = \max _{c\in K}{\min _{d\in A {\setminus } K}{H(c,d)}}, \end{aligned}$$

and so \({\widehat{v}}(K) = v(K) = v(K\cup b)\).

For each candidate \(a\in A{\setminus } b\), the Shapley value takes the form

$$\begin{aligned} \varphi _a= & {} \sum _{K\subset A{\setminus } a} \frac{k!(m-k-1)!}{m!} \left( v(K\cup a)-v(K)\right) \\= & {} \sum _{K\subset A{\setminus } \{a,b\}} \frac{k!(m-k-1)!}{m!} \left( v(K\cup a)-v(K)\right) \\&+ \sum _{K\subset A{\setminus } \{a,b\}} \frac{(k+1)!(m-k-2)!}{m!} \left( v(K\cup a\cup b)-v(K\cup b)\right) \\= & {} \sum _{K\subset A{\setminus } \{a,b\}} \left( \frac{k!(m-k-1)!}{m!}+\frac{(k+1)!(m-k-2)!}{m!}\right) \left( {\widehat{v}}(K\cup a)-{\widehat{v}}(K)\right) \\= & {} \sum _{K\subset A{\setminus } \{a,b\}} \frac{k!(m-k-2)!}{(m-1)!} \left( {\widehat{v}}(K\cup a)-{\widehat{v}}(K)\right) =\widehat{\varphi _a}. \end{aligned}$$

(4) We have to show that \(\varphi _{+} \supset MNL\). Each candidate \(a\in MNL(A,H)\) belongs at least to one minimal nonlosing coalition \(a\in B\in M_1 \cup M_{1/2}\); hence, \(v(B)-v(B{\setminus } a)>0\) and \(\varphi _a>0\).

To prove \(\varphi _{+} \subset MNL\), we use the principle of contradiction. Assume that \(a\in \varphi _{+}(T)\), \(a\notin MNL(T)\), in a certain tournament \(T=(A,H)\). Since \(a\in \varphi _{+}(T)\), then there exists a set \(K\cup a\) such that \(v(K\cup a)>v(K)\). On the strength of \(a\notin MNL(T)\), for each \(B\in M_1(T)\cup M_{1/2}(T)\) we have \(a\notin B\). If \(v(K\cup a)=i\in \{1, 1/2\}\), then there exists \(B\subset K\cup a\), where \(B\in M_i\) and \(a\notin B\). As a result, \(B\subset K\) and the conclusion follows from the contradiction \(v(B)=i=v(K\cup a)\le v(K)\). \(\square \)

Remark 4

Lemma 4 remains in force for the Banzhaf value (5). The only difference in the proof concerns Item 3. To argue this result, it suffices to observe that

$$\begin{aligned} {\widetilde{\beta }}_a(A,H)= & {} \sum _{K\subset A{\setminus } a} \left( v(K\cup a)-v(K)\right) \\= & {} 2 \sum _{K\subset A{\setminus } \{a,b\}} \left( v(K\cup a)-v(K)\right) =2 {\widetilde{\beta }}_a(A{{\setminus }} b,H) \end{aligned}$$

for each b, whenever \(\varphi _b(A,H)=0\) and \(a\in A{\setminus } b\).

Lemma 5

For each weak tournament \(T=(A,H)\) and each pair of candidates \(\{a,b\}\) such that a covers b, we have the following properties:

  1. (1)

    For each coalition \(B\subset A{\setminus } \{a,b\}\), the payoffs satisfy the inequalities \(v(B\cup a)\)\(\ge \)\(v(B\cup b)=v(B)\);

  2. (2)

    Candidate a is at least as influential as candidate b: \(a\succeq b\);

  3. (3)

    The Shapley value satisfies the inequality \(\varphi _a\ge \varphi _b\).

    Moreover, if the tournament T allows no ties, then also:

  4. (4)

    If \(a\in UC\) is uncovered, then a is more influential than b: \(a\succ b\);

  5. (5)

    If \(a\in UC\), then \(\varphi _a>\varphi _b\).

Proof

(1) Using the principle of contradiction, assume that \(v(B\cup b)>v(B)\) for a certain coalition \(B\subset A{\setminus } \{a,b\}\). Consider the game of the coalition \(B\cup b\) against the coalition \(K\cup a\), where \(K=A{\setminus } B\setminus \{a,b\}\). Candidate b cannot be a nominated candidate from the coalition \(B\cup b\), as long as \(H(b,a)=0\). Denote by \(c\in B\) a nominated candidate from the coalition \(B\cup b\) that guarantees the payoff \(v(B\cup b)\). Therefore, \(H(c,a)\ge v(B\cup b)\) and \(H(c,d)\ge v(B\cup b)\) for each \(d\in K\). In the case of \(H(c,b)\ge v(B\cup b)\), candidate \(c\in B\) would guarantee the payoff \(v(B)=v(B\cup b)\) for the coalition B. Hence, \(H(c,b) < v(B\cup b)\le H(c,a)\), which obviously contradicts the covering relation a over b.

Thus, we have demonstrated that \(v(B\cup b)=v(B)\). The inequality \(v(B\cup a)\)\(\ge \)v(B) holds by monotonicity of v.

(2) The desired relation follows from Item 1 and the influence relation definition.

(3) The desired inequality follows from Item 1 and formula (6).

(4,5) Under items 2 and 3 we have \(a\succeq b\) and \(\varphi _a\ge \varphi _b\). Under Lemma 1 coalition \(a\cup {\overline{D}}(a) \in M\) is minimal winning; thus, \(v(a\cup {\overline{D}}(a)) = 1\) and \(v({\overline{D}}(a))=0\). According to Item 1 we have \(v(b\cup {\overline{D}}(a)) = v({\overline{D}}(a)) =0\). The inequality \(v(a\cup {\overline{D}}(a)) > v(b\cup {\overline{D}}(a))\) implies \(a\succ b\) and \(\varphi _a>\varphi _b\).

\(\square \)

Remark 5

Lemma 5 remains in force for the Banzhaf value (5). The only difference in the proof is that it uses formula (7).

Proof of Theorem 1

(1) Suppose that the adjacency matrices \({\widehat{H}}\) and H satisfy \({\widehat{H}}(a,b) > H(a,b)\) and \({\widehat{H}}(b,a) < H(b,a)\) for a certain pair of candidates \(\{a, b\}\) and the other elements of the matrices coincide. Let \({\widehat{v}}\) and v be the characteristic functions for the tournaments \((A,{\widehat{H}})\) and (AH), respectively. The definition of the characteristic function under formula (1) directly implies that

$$\begin{aligned} {\widehat{v}}(B\cup a) \ge v(B\cup a), \quad {\widehat{v}}(B) \le v(B) \quad \text{ for } \text{ each } \quad B\subset A{\setminus } a. \end{aligned}$$
(10)

To prove that \(a\in IN(A,{\widehat{H}})\), whenever \(a\in IN(A,H)\), we use the principle of contradiction. Assume that a certain candidate c is more influential than candidate a in the tournament \((A,{\widehat{H}})\), that is,

$$\begin{aligned} {\widehat{v}}(B\cup c) \ge {\widehat{v}}(B\cup a) \quad \text{ for } \text{ each } \quad B\subset A{\setminus } \{a,c\}, \end{aligned}$$

and the inequality is strict for some B. These inequalities and the inequalities (10) imply that c is more influential than a in (AH), which contradicts \(a\in IN(A,H)\).

(2) The desired inclusion follows from Item 4 of Lemma 5.

(3) Under Lemma 1 the set of minimal winning coalitions can be computed in polynomial time. Hence, for each pair of candidates, under Lemma 2 we can check the influence relation in polynomial time. \(\square \)

Proof of Theorem 4

Items 1 and 2 have been proved in Lemmas 5 and 4, respectively.

(3) If we change an adjacency matrix H for \({\widehat{H}}\) so that \({\widehat{H}}(a,b)>H(a,b)\) and \({\widehat{H}}(b,a)<H(b,a)\) for a certain pair of candidates \(\{a,b\}\) (the other values remain the same), then the hypotheses of Lemma 3 hold and the rank of candidate a is not decreased.

(4) The desired inclusion \(\varphi _{+} = MNL \subset TC\) has been proved in Lemma 4.

(5) Suppose candidate b covered by candidate \(a\in A\) is added to a tournament (AH), that is, \({\widehat{H}}(a,b)=1\), \({\widehat{H}}(a,c)\ge {\widehat{H}}(b,c)\) for each candidate \(c\in A{\setminus } a\), and \({\widehat{H}}=H\) in the other cases.

Let \({\widehat{v}}\) be the characteristic function for the tournament \((A\cup b, {\widehat{H}})\). As is easily observed, for each coalition \(B\subset A{\setminus } a\) not containing candidate a, we have

$$\begin{aligned} v(B)={\widehat{v}}(B), \quad v(B\cup a)={\widehat{v}}(B\cup a \cup b),\quad B\subset A{\setminus } a. \end{aligned}$$
(11)

Under Item 1 of Lemma 5, for each coalition \(B\subset A{\setminus } a\) the contribution is \({\widehat{\varDelta }}_b(B) = {\widehat{v}}(B\cup b) -{\widehat{v}}(B)=0\).

Consider an arbitrary permutation of length m in which a certain candidate \(c\in A{\setminus } \{a,b\}\) stands after candidate a, and \(\sigma =b_1\), \(\ldots ,b_l,a,k_1\), \(\ldots \), \(k_r,c,t_1\), \(\ldots ,t_p\). Construct the sets \(B=\{b_1,\ldots ,b_l\}\) and \(K=\{k_1,\ldots ,k_r\}\). There exist \(m+1\) ways to place candidate b, among which \(l+1\) ways to place it before a and \(m-l\) ways after a. Taking into account (11), averaging over all the \(m+1\) ways yields

$$\begin{aligned} {\widehat{\varDelta }}_{a}(\sigma +b)= & {} \frac{(l+1){\widehat{\varDelta }}_a(B\cup b)+(m-l){\widehat{\varDelta }}_a(B)}{m+1}\\= & {} \frac{(l+1)(\varDelta _a(B) - {\widehat{\varDelta }}_{b}(B))+(m-l)(\varDelta _a(B)- {\widehat{\varDelta }}_{b}(B\cup a)) }{m+1}\\= & {} \varDelta _a(B)-\frac{(l+1) {\widehat{\varDelta }}_{b}(B)+(m-l){\widehat{\varDelta }}_{b}(B\cup a) }{m+1} \\= & {} \varDelta _a(B)-\frac{(m-l){\widehat{\varDelta }}_{b}(B\cup a) }{m+1}. \end{aligned}$$

Let us associate each permutation \(\sigma \) considered with a permutation \(\sigma '=b_1,\ldots ,b_l, c, k_1,\ldots ,k_r, a, t_1,\ldots ,t_p\) of length m, where candidate a stands after candidate c. The averaged contribution of candidate c over all the \(m+1\) ways to permute candidate b makes up

$$\begin{aligned} {\widehat{\varDelta }}_{c}(\sigma '+b)= & {} \frac{(l+1){\widehat{\varDelta }}_c(B\cup b)+(m-l){\widehat{\varDelta }}_c(B)}{m+1}\\= & {} \frac{(l+1)(\varDelta _c(B) - {\widehat{\varDelta }}_{b}(B)+{\widehat{\varDelta }}_{b}(B\cup c))+(m-l)\varDelta _c(B)}{m+1}\\= & {} \varDelta _c(B)+\frac{(l+1)({\widehat{\varDelta }}_{b}(B\cup c) -{\widehat{\varDelta }}_{b}(B)) }{m+1} = \varDelta _c(B). \end{aligned}$$

Hence, candidate c loses in \(\sigma '\) no more than candidate a in \(\sigma \).

By analogy, one may obtain the formulas

$$\begin{aligned} {\widehat{\varDelta }}_{a}(\sigma '+b)= & {} \varDelta _a(B\cup c\cup K)- \frac{(m-l-r-1){\widehat{\varDelta }}_{b}(B\cup c \cup K \cup a) }{m+1}, \\ {\widehat{\varDelta }}_{c}(\sigma +b)= & {} \varDelta _c(B\cup a\cup K)\\&+\frac{(m-l-r-1)( {\widehat{\varDelta }}_{b}(B\cup a \cup K)- {\widehat{\varDelta }}_{b}(B\cup a \cup K \cup c)) }{m+1}. \end{aligned}$$

Thus, candidate c loses in \(\sigma \) no more than candidate a in \(\sigma '\). Since the Shapley value for an arbitrary candidate is calculated as its average score over all permutations, adding candidate b does not increase the ordinal rank and the score of candidate a. \(\square \)

Proof of Theorem 2

Items 1 and 2 have been proved in Lemmas 5 and 4, respectively. Items 3 and 5 have been proved in Theorem 4.

(4) The inclusion \(\varphi _{max} \subset IN\) follows from formula (6) and the definition of the influence relation. The inclusion \(IN \subset UC\) has been proved in Theorem 1.

The formula for \(\varphi _{+}\) follows from Lemmas 1 and  4. The inclusion \(\varphi _{+} \subset TC\) has been proved in Lemma 4. \(\square \)

Proof of Theorem 3

(1) Consider a certain candidate \(a\in UC(T)\) that covers candidate b. For each coalition \(B\subset A{\setminus } \{a,b\}\), we have \(v(B\cup b)=v(B)\) according to Item 1 of Lemma 5 in Appendix. Therefore, each minimal winning coalition \(K\in M(A,H)\) containing candidate b always includes candidate a that covers the former. However, candidate b is not a member of the coalition \(a\cup {\overline{D}}(a)\in M(A,H)\) by Lemma 1. The largest excesses belong to the coalitions \(K\in M(A,H)\),

$$\begin{aligned} e(x,K)=1-\sum _{a_i\in K}{x_i}\ge 0. \end{aligned}$$

The excesses of losing coalitions do not exceed zero. Hence, to minimize the excess vector, the whole imputation \(x_b\) is transferred from candidate b to candidate a, and \(N_b=0\).

Now show that removing candidate \(b\notin UC\) does not affect the nucleolus. Let the imputation be \(x=N(A,H)\), \(x_b=0\). Denote by \({\widehat{v}}\) the corresponding characteristic function and by \({\widehat{e}}\) the excesses for \({\widehat{A}}=A{\setminus } b\).

Consider an arbitrary coalition \(B\subset A{\setminus } \{a,b\}\). As is easily seen,

$$\begin{aligned} v(B)=v(B\cup b)={\widehat{v}}(B), \quad v(B\cup a)\le v(B\cup a \cup b)={\widehat{v}}(B\cup a). \end{aligned}$$

For each imputation \({\widehat{x}}\), the excesses are

$$\begin{aligned} {\widehat{e}}({\widehat{x}},B)= & {} {\widehat{v}}(B)-\sum \limits _{k\in B} {{\widehat{x}}_k}=e({\widehat{x}},B)=e({\widehat{x}},B\cup b), \\ {\widehat{e}}({\widehat{x}},B\cup a)= & {} {\widehat{v}}(B\cup a)-\sum \limits _{k\in B\cup a} {{\widehat{x}}_k} =e({\widehat{x}},B\cup a \cup b) \ge e({\widehat{x}}, B\cup a). \end{aligned}$$

Consequently, the lexicographic minimum of the excesses \({\widehat{e}}({\widehat{x}})\) is achieved at the imputation \({\widehat{x}} : {\widehat{x}}_c=x_c, c\ne b\).

(2) Item 1 directly implies that \(NU\subset UC^{\infty }\). \(\square \)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Kondratev, A.Y., Mazalov, V.V. Tournament solutions based on cooperative game theory. Int J Game Theory 49, 119–145 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00182-019-00681-5

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00182-019-00681-5

Keywords

Mathematics Subject Classification

JEL Classification

Navigation