Skip to main content

William James and the “Theatre” of Consciousness

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Brain, Mind and Consciousness in the History of Neuroscience

Part of the book series: History, Philosophy and Theory of the Life Sciences ((HPTL,volume 6))

  • 2460 Accesses

Abstract

This essay examines the relationship of philosopher and psychologist William James (1842–1910) to the history of the hard problem of consciousness and to contemporary neuroscience. From the outset, James’s psychological writings fused Darwinian evolutionary theory, physics, and phenomenology in order to address the relation of our felt sense of possessing an autonomous, conscious “self” to a broader environment and social community. For James, the “hard problem” of how the physiological brain gives rise to will, habit, and attention – the essential components of volition – also involved a social component. This essay first traces how James’s earliest writings describe consciousness as a selective agency that works in consort with natural selection to contribute to human evolutionary advancement. Second, it demonstrates how James grafted Darwinian evolutionary thought onto the new physics in ways that anticipate contemporary neuroscientific attempts to resolve the hard problem by identifying the structures in the brain responsible for our phenomenological experience. Finally, it addresses the broader sociological aspects of the hard problem in James’s later writings. Through the lens of James’s writings on the transmission theory and compounding of consciousness we can understand the hard problem as encompassing the biosocial: the experience of individual and collective minds in the process of shaping complex networks of social interaction.

To clear up the immediate relation of minds and brains is the big problem.

–William James

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    “Notebook 19.” bMSAm1092.9 (4513). William James Papers (MSAm1092.9–1092.12). Houghton Library, Harvard University.

  2. 2.

    Skrupskelis 1995, p. 75.

  3. 3.

    Hawkins 2011.

  4. 4.

    James 1922, p. 34.

  5. 5.

    Chalmers 2010. Throughout this essay I will use the term, the “mind sciences” to refer collectively to philosophers of mind, neuroscientists, and psychologists and physicists invested in exploring the relationship of consciousness to that of brain physiology.

  6. 6.

    Thompson 2007; Revonsuo 2009; Fingelkurts et al. 2010.

  7. 7.

    Cotkin 1990; Bordogna 2008.

  8. 8.

    Feinstein 1999; Leary 2002.

  9. 9.

    Taylor 1996, p. 73.

  10. 10.

    Crippen 2010.

  11. 11.

    James 1879/1983, pp. 51–52.

  12. 12.

    James 1981, p. 51.

  13. 13.

    James, of course, anticipates Gerald Edelman’s theory of “neural Darwinism.” However, Edelman parts ways with James by insisting that consciousness itself has no impact on neuronal firing. See Edelman 2004, p. 84. See also, Schwartz and Begley The Mind and the Brain (2003), which cites James on the adaptive “plasticity” of the brain in his chapter on “Habit” in Principles.

  14. 14.

    See Revonsuo 2009, Fingelkurts et al. 2010, and Barnard 1997.

  15. 15.

    James 1879/1983, pp. 229–230.

  16. 16.

    These ideas are expanded in his chapter on “Habit” in The Principles of Psychology. In 1887, the chapter appeared as an essay in Popular Science Monthly.

  17. 17.

    Bjork 1983, pp. 81–83.

  18. 18.

    Marshall 1982, p. 80. See also, Marshall 1974.

  19. 19.

    qtd. in Marshall 1982.

  20. 20.

    James 1990, p. 21.

  21. 21.

    Ibid., p. 21.

  22. 22.

    James 1981, p. 379.

  23. 23.

    Ibid., p. 379.

  24. 24.

    Ibid., p. 379.

  25. 25.

    McGinn’s 2011 book on the philosophy of physics makes a similar argument about consciousness as a form of matter. As the new physics probed ever deeper into the hidden structures of material reality, “More and more types of physical reality had to be recognized, such as radio waves and X-rays, and the sheer versatility of matter became increasingly evident.” Such discoveries gave rise to new “species of energy,” such as “kinetic energy, chemical energy, gravitational energy, electro-magnetic energy, nuclear energy” p. 176

  26. 26.

    James 1986, p. 369.

  27. 27.

    Hawkins 2005, 2011.

  28. 28.

    Coon 2002, p. 129.

  29. 29.

    Fuchs 2002, pp. 79–84; Taylor 1992, 1996, p. 182, 2002, 2003.

  30. 30.

    Albanese 2007.

  31. 31.

    Marshall 1982; Heidelberger 2004.

  32. 32.

    Marshall 1982; Heidelberger 2004.

  33. 33.

    Heidelberger 2004, pp. 103–104.

  34. 34.

    James 1992, p. 1104.

  35. 35.

    Ibid., pp. 1109–1110; Kelly et al. 2007, p. 29.

  36. 36.

    James 1992, p. 1111.

  37. 37.

    Ibid.

  38. 38.

    As James himself acknowledged, philosophers Immanuel Kant and F.C.S. Schiller made similar arguments. Kant, for example, maintained that the body restricts the intellectual function of the brain, which only comes into full flower after death. Schiller similarly argued that matter restricts “the consciousness which it encases.” Ibid., p. 1119, n9.

  39. 39.

    Kelly et al. 2007, p. 606.

  40. 40.

    James 1986, p. 357; for accounts of the experiences leading up to James’s report, see Richardson 2007, pp. 478–479; for Hodgson’s reputed vow, see Simon 1998, pp. 319–320.

  41. 41.

    Ibid., p. 358, emphasis in original.

  42. 42.

    Ibid., p. 359.

  43. 43.

    Nuñez 2010, p. 11.

  44. 44.

    Ibid., p. 274.

  45. 45.

    Filk and Müller 2008, p. 63; See Stapp 1995/1997, 2007.

  46. 46.

    Filk and Müller 2008, p. 63.

  47. 47.

    Kern 1983, p. 41.

  48. 48.

    Edelman 2004, p. 133.

  49. 49.

    Trehub 2007, p. 310.

  50. 50.

    Ibid., 329.

  51. 51.

    Ibid.

  52. 52.

    James 1977, p. 130.

  53. 53.

    James 1904, p. xv.

  54. 54.

    Thompson 2007, p. 39.

  55. 55.

    James 1977, pp. 115–116.

  56. 56.

    James 1977, p. 73, 1909, 1910.

  57. 57.

    Thompson 2007, p. 67.

  58. 58.

    Ibid., p. 82.

  59. 59.

    Ibid., p. 87.

  60. 60.

    Chalmers 2010, p. 5.

  61. 61.

    Ibid.

  62. 62.

    Ibid., p. 6.

  63. 63.

    Revonsuo 2009, p. 3; Fingelkurts et al. 2010; Kelly et al. 2007.

  64. 64.

    Pauli 1994, p. 260; Fingelkurts et al. 2010.

  65. 65.

    See McGinn on consciousness as a form of matter: He writes, “An electromagnetic field is a type of material reality, and so is consciousness. Alternatively, consciousness is one form of energy, along with kinetic energy or electrical energy. If this hypothesis is true, then consciousness is material after all – though not in the Cartesian sense. The general conception I am working with is that matter/energy is the underlying substance of the universe, and it may ultimately be unitary, but it can take widely different forms – with consciousness as just one of them” 2011, p.178

  66. 66.

    Taylor 2010, p. 411; Wallace 2007, p. 105.

  67. 67.

    Varela 1997; Taylor 2010, pp. 421–422.

  68. 68.

    Edelman 2004, p. 76; Trehub 2007; Fingelkurts et al. 2010, 2011, 2012.

  69. 69.

    Freeman 2007, p. 1022.

  70. 70.

    Ibid.

  71. 71.

    Shear 1997.

  72. 72.

    Between 1899 and 1904 James published anti-imperialist essays against U.S. occupation of the Philippines. His anti-lynching essays appear in 1903, on the heels of James’s many reviews of books dealing with crowd psychology and mental hygiene. James 1987.

References

  • Albanese CL (2007) A republic of mind and spirit: a cultural history of American metaphysical religion. Yale University Press, New Haven/London

    Google Scholar 

  • Barnard GW (1997) Exploring unseen worlds: William James and the philosophy of mysticism. State University of New York Press, Albany

    Google Scholar 

  • Bjork DW (1983) The compromised scientist: William James in the development of American psychology. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Bordogna F (2008) William James at the boundaries: philosophy, science, and the geography of knowledge. University of Chicago Press, Chicago/London

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers DJ (2010) The character of consciousness. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Coon DJ (2002) Testing the limits of sense and science: American experimental psychologists combat spiritualism, 1880–1920. In: Pickren WE, Dewsbury DA (eds) Evolving perspectives on the history of psychology. American Psychological Association, Washington, DC, pp 121–139

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Cotkin G (1990) William James: public philosopher. Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore

    Google Scholar 

  • Crippen M (2010) William James on belief: turning Darwinism against Empiricistic Skepticism. Trans Charles Peirce Soc 46(3):477–502

    Google Scholar 

  • Edelman G (2004) Wider than the sky: the phenomenal gift of consciousness. Yale University Press, New Haven/London

    Google Scholar 

  • Feinstein HM (1999) Becoming William James. Cornell University Press, Ithaca/London

    Google Scholar 

  • Filk T, von Müller A (2008) Quantum physics and consciousness: the quest for a common conceptual foundation. Mind Matter 7(1):59–79

    Google Scholar 

  • Fingelkurts AA, Fingelkurts AA, Neves CFH (2010) Natural world physical, brain operational, and mind phenomenal space-time. Phys Life Rev 7(2010):195–249

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fingelkurts AA et al (2011) Persistent operational synchrony within brain default-mode network and self-processing operations in healthy subjects. Brain Cogn 75:79–90

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fingelkurts AA, Fingelkurts AA, Bagnato S, Boccagni C, Galardi G (2012) Toward operational architectonics of consciousness: basic evidence from patients with severe cerebral injuries. Cogn Process 13:111–131

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freeman WJ (2007) Indirect biological measures of consciousness from field studies of brains as dynamical systems. Neural Netw 20:1021–1031

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fuchs AH (2002) Contributions of American mental philosophers to psychology in the United States. In: Pickren WE, Dewsbury DA (eds) Evolving perspectives on the history of psychology. American Psychological Association, Washington, DC, pp 79–99

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hawkins SL (2005) The science of superstition: Gertrude Stein, William James, and the formation of belief. Mod Fict Stud 51(1):60–87

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hawkins SL (2011) William James, Gustav Fechner, and early psychophysics. Front Fractal Physiol 2:1–10

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidelberger M (2004) Gustav Theodor Fechner and his psychophysical worldview (trans: Klohr C). University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh

    Google Scholar 

  • Jack AI, Roepstorff A (2002) Introspection and cognitive brain mapping: from stimulus-response to script-report. Trends Cogn Sci 6(8):333–339

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • James W (1879/1983) Are we automata? Mind 4(January 1879):1–22. In: Burkhardt FH, Bowers F, Skrupskelis IK (eds) Essays in psychology. The works of William James. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA/London, pp 38–61

    Google Scholar 

  • James W (1888/1983) What the will effects. Scribner’s Magazine 3(February 1888):240–250. In: Burkhardt FH, Bowers F, Skrupskelis IK (eds) Essays in psychology. The works of William James. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA/London, pp 216–234

    Google Scholar 

  • James W (1904) Introduction. In: Fechner G (ed) The little book of life after death (trans: Wadsworth MC). Little, Brown, and Company, Boston, pp vii–xix

    Google Scholar 

  • James W (1909) The doctrine of the earth-soul and of beings intermediate between man and God; an account of the philosophy of G.T. Fechner. Hibbert J: A Q Rev Relig Theol Philos 7(2):278–291

    Google Scholar 

  • James W (1910) A suggestion about mysticism. J Philos Psychol Sci Method 7(4):85–92

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • James W (1922) Essays in radical empiricism. Longmans, Green and Co., New York (Original 1904)

    Google Scholar 

  • James W (1977) A pluralistic universe, vol 4, The works of William James. Burkhardt F, Bowers F (eds). Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA (Original 1909)

    Google Scholar 

  • James W (1981) The principles of psychology. The works of William James. Burkhardt F, Bowers F, Skrupskelis I (eds). Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA/London (Original 1890)

    Google Scholar 

  • James W (1986) Essays in psychical research. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • James W (1987) Essays, comments, and reviews. Burkhardt FH, Bowers F, Skrupskelis IK (eds). Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA/London

    Google Scholar 

  • James W (1990) The varieties of religious experience. Kuklick B (ed). The Library of America, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • James W (1992) On human immortality. In William James: writings 1878–1899. The Library of America, New York, pp 1100–1127 (Original 1898)

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelly EF et al (2007) Irreducible mind: toward a psychology for the 21st century. Rowman and Littlefield, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Kern S (1983) The culture of time and space: 1880–1918. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Lamberth DC (1997) Interpreting the universe after a social analogy: intimacy, panpsychism, and a finite God in a pluralistic universe. In: Putnam RA (ed) The Cambridge companion to William James. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 237–259

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Leary DE (2002) William James and the art of human understanding. In: Pickren WE, Dewsbury DA (eds) Evolving perspectives on the history of psychology. American Psychological Association, Washington, DC, pp 101–120

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Marshall M (1974) William James, Gustav Fechner, and the question of dogs and cats in the library. J Hist Behav Sci 10:304–312

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marshall M (1982) Physics, metaphysics, and Fechner’s psychophysics. In: Woodward WR, Ash MG (eds) The problematic science: psychology in nineteenth-century thought. Praeger, New York, pp 65–87

    Google Scholar 

  • McGinn C (2011) Basic structures of reality: essays in metaphysics. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Nuñez PL (2010) Brain, mind, and the structure of reality. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pauli W (1994) Writings on physics and philosophy, Enz CP, von Meyenn K (eds). Springer, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • Revonsuo A (2009) Inner presence: consciousness as a biological phenomenon. The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA/London

    Google Scholar 

  • Richardson RD (2007) William James: in the maelstrom of American modernism. Mariner, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz JM, Begley S (2003) The mind and the brain: neuroplasticity and the power of mental force. Harper Perennial, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Shear J (1997) The hard problem: closing the empirical gap. In: Explaining consciousness: the ‘Hard Problem’. The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA/London, pp 359–375

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon L (1998) Genuine reality: a life of William James. Harcourt Brace, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Skrupskelis IK (1995) James’s conception of psychology as a natural science. Hist Hum Sci 8(1):73–89

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stapp HP (1995/1997) The hard problem: a quantum approach. In: Shear J (ed) Explaining consciousness: the ‘hard problem’. The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA/London, pp 197–215

    Google Scholar 

  • Stapp HP (2007) Mindful universe: quantum mechanics and the participating observer. Springer, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson G (2008) Real materialism and other essays. Oxford University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor E (1992) The case for a uniquely American Jamesian tradition in psychology. In: Donnelly ME (ed) Reinterpreting the legacy of William James. American Psychological Association, Washington, DC, pp 3–28

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor E (1996) William James on consciousness beyond the margin. Princeton University Press., Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor E (2002) William James and depth psychology. In: Michel F (ed) The varieties of religious experience: centenary essays. Imprint Academic, Charlottesville, pp 11–36

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor E (2003) A perfect correlation between mind and brain: William James’s Varieties and the contemporary field of mind/body medicine. J Specul Philos New Ser 17(1):40–52

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor E (2010) William James and the humanistic implications of the neuroscience revolution: an outrageous hypothesis. J Humanist Psychol 50:410–429

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson E (2007) Mind in life: biology, phenomenology, and the sciences of mind. The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA/London

    Google Scholar 

  • Trehub A (2007) Space, self, and the theater of consciousness. Conscious Cogn 16:310–330

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varela FJ (1997) Neurophenomenology: a methodological remedy for the hard problem. In: Jonathan S (ed) Explaining consciousness: the ‘hard problem’. The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA/London, pp 337–357

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallace BA (2007) Hidden dimensions: the unification of physics and consciousness. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgment

I am grateful to Andrew and Alexander Fingelkurts for commenting on an earlier draft of this essay.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Stephanie L. Hawkins .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Hawkins, S.L. (2014). William James and the “Theatre” of Consciousness. In: Smith, C., Whitaker, H. (eds) Brain, Mind and Consciousness in the History of Neuroscience. History, Philosophy and Theory of the Life Sciences, vol 6. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-8774-1_11

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics