Skip to main content
Log in

Computation without Representation

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The received view is that computational states are individuated at least in part by their semantic properties. I offer an alternative, according to which computational states are individuated by their functional properties. Functional properties are specified by a mechanistic explanation without appealing to any semantic properties. The primary purpose of this paper is to formulate the alternative view of computational individuation, point out that it supports a robust notion of computational explanation, and defend it on the grounds of how computational states are individuated within computability theory and computer science. A secondary purpose is to show that existing arguments for the semantic view are defective.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Bechtel W. and Richardson R.C. (1993). Discovering Complexity: Decomposition and Localization as Scientific Research Strategies. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ

    Google Scholar 

  • Bontly T. (1998). Individualism and the Nature of Syntactic States. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 49: 557–574

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burge T. (1986). Individualism and Psychology. Philosophical Review 95: 3–45

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Butler K. (1996). Content, Computation and Individuation in Vision Theory. Analysis 56: 146–154

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers D.J. (1996). Does a Rock Implement Every Finite-State Automaton?. Synthese 108: 310–333

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Copeland B.J. (1996). What is Computation?. Synthese 108: 224–359

    Google Scholar 

  • Crane T. (1990). The Language of Thought: No Syntax Without Semantics. Mind and Language 5(3): 187–212

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. (forthcoming): ‘Explaining the Brain, Oxford University Press

  • Cummins R. (1983). The Nature of Psychological Explanation. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1970): ‘Mental Events. Experience and Theory in L. Foster and J.W. Swanson’, Amherst, MA, University of Massachusetts Press. Reprinted in Davidson, Essays on Actions and Events. Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1980

  • Dean, W. (2002): What Algorithms Could Not Be. In Proceedings of the Computing and Philosophy Conference, Pittsburgh, PA

  • Dennett D.C. (1987). The Intentional Stance. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Dietrich E. (1989). Semantics and the Computational Paradigm in Cognitive Psychology. Synthese 79: 119–141

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Egan F. (1992). Individualism, Computation and Perceptual Content. Mind 101(403): 443–459

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Egan F. (1995). Computation and Content. Philosophical Review 104: 181–203

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Egan F. (1999). In Defence of Narrow Mindedness. Mind and Language 14(2): 177–194

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Egan F. (2003). ‘Naturalistic Inquiry: Where Does Mental Representation Fit in?’. In: Antony, L.M. and Hornstein, N. (eds) Chowsky and His Critics, pp 89–104. Blackwell, Malden

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor J.A. (1968). The Appeal to Tacit Knowledge in Psychological Explanation. Journal of Philosophy 65: 627–640

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor J.A. (1975). The Language of Thought. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor J.A. (1978). ‘Tom Swift and His Procedural Grandmother’. Cognition 6: 229–247

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor J.A. (1980). ‘Methodological Solipsism Considered as a Research Strategy in Cognitive Psychology’. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3(1): 63–109

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor J.A. (1981): ‘The Mind–Body Problem’, Scientific American 244 (January 1981). Reprinted in Heil, J. (ed.) (2004a). Philosophy of Mind: A Guide and Anthology, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 168–182

  • Fodor J.A. (1987). Psychosemantics. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor J.A. (1998). Concepts. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Frank R. (1994). Instruments, Nerve Action and the All-or-None Principle. Osiris 9: 208–235

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glennan S. (2002). Rethinking Mechanistic Explanation. Philosophy of Science 69: 5342–5353

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glymour C. (1991). Freud’s Androids. In: Neu, J. (eds) The Cambridge Companion to Freud, pp. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman G. (1988). ‘Wide Functionalism’. In: Schiffer, S. and Steele, S. (eds) Cognition and Representation, pp 11–20. Westview, Boulder

    Google Scholar 

  • Horst S.W. (1996). Symbols, Computation and Intentionality: A Critique of the Computational Theory of Mind. University of California Press, Berkeley, CA

    Google Scholar 

  • Horst S. (1999). Symbols and Computation. Minds and Machines 9(3): 347–381

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jacquette D. (1991). ‘The Myth of Pure Syntax’. In: Albertazzi, L. and Poli, R. (eds) Topics in Philosophy and Artificial Intelligence, pp 1–14. Istituto Mitteleuropeo di Cultura, Bozen

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher P. (1985). Narrow Taxonomy and Wide Functionalism. Philosophy of Science 52(1): 78–97

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machamer P.K., Darden L. and Craver C. (2000). Thinking About Mechanisms. Philosophy of Science 67: 1–25

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machtey M. and Young P. (1978). An Introduction to the General Theory of Algorithms. North Holland, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Markov A.A. (1960 [1951]). The Theory of Algorithms. American Mathematical Society Translations, Series 2 15: 1–14

    Google Scholar 

  • Marr D. (1982). Vision. Freeman, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • McCulloch W.S. and Pitts W.H. (1943). A Logical Calculus of the Ideas Immanent in Nervous Activity. Bulletin of Mathematical Biophysics 7: 115–133

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newell A. (1980). Physical Symbol Systems. Cognitive Science 4: 135–183

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke C. (1994a). Content, Computation and Externalism. Mind and Language 9: 303–335

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke C. (1994b). ‘Content’. In: Guttenplan, S. (eds) A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind, pp 219–225. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke C. (1999). Computation as Involving Content: A Response to Egan. Mind and Language 14(2): 195–202

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piccinini G. (2004a). Functionalism, Computationalism and Mental Contents. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 34(3): 375–410

    Google Scholar 

  • Piccinini G. (2004b). The First Computational Theory of Mind and Brain: A Close Look at McCulloch and Pitts’s ‘Logical Calculus of Ideas Immanent in Nervous Activity’. Synthese 141(2): 175–215

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piccinini, G. (forthcoming): ‘Computational Modeling vs. Computational Explanation: Is Everything a Turing Machine, and Does It Matter to the Philosophy of Mind?’ Australasian Journal of Philosophy

  • Putnam H. (1967). Psychological Predicates. Art, Philosophy and Religion. University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh, PA

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975): ‘The Meaning of “Meaning”’, in K. Gunderson (ed.), Language, Mind and Knowledge, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Reprinted in Putnam, H. (1975): Mind, Language and Reality: Philosophical Papers, Vol. 2. (pp. 215–271) Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press

  • Pylyshyn Z.W. (1984). Computation and Cognition. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Scheutz M. (1999). When Physical Systems Realize Functions. Minds and Machines 9: 161–196

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searle J.R. (1980). Minds, Brains and Programs. The Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3: 417–457

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searle J.R. (1992). The Rediscovery of the Mind. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Segal G. (1989). Seeing What is Not There. Philosophical Review 98: 189–214

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Segal G. (1991). Defence of a Reasonable Individualism. Mind 100: 485–493

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shagrir O. (1997). Two Dogmas of Computationalism. Minds and Machines 7(3): 321–344

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shagrir O. (1999). What is Computer Science About?. The Monist 82(1): 131–149

    Google Scholar 

  • Shagrir O. (2001). Content, Computation and Externalism. Mind 110(438): 369–400

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro L.A. (1994). Behavior, ISO Functionalism and Psychology. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science 25(2): 191–209

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro L. (1997). A Clearer Vision. Philosophy of Science 64: 131–153

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith B.C. (1996). On the Origin of Objects. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Stich S. (1983). From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Wells A.J. (1998). Turing’s Analysis of Computation and Theories of Cognitive Architecture. Cognitive Science 22(3): 269–294

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson R.A. (1994). Wide Computationalism. Mind 103: 351–372

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson R.A. (2004). Boundaries of the Mind: The Individual in the Fragile Sciences. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Gualtiero Piccinini.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Piccinini, G. Computation without Representation. Philos Stud 137, 205–241 (2008). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-005-5385-4

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-005-5385-4

Keywords

Navigation