Skip to main content

Understanding Social Science Simulations: Distinguishing Two Categories of Simulations

  • Conference paper
  • First Online:
The Science and Art of Simulation I

Abstract

How can we understand the results of a simulation study? In this article, I address this epistemic question for social science simulations. I argue that we can distinguish two categories of simulations: simulations STE, which possess key features that resemble the epistemology and methodology of thought experiments, and simulations SE, which resemble the epistemology and methodology of experiments. Based on Woodward’s theory of causal explanation, I put forward the hypothesis that STE provide more understanding and a different kind of knowledge than SE because they give well-founded answers to what-if-things-had-been-different questions. Epistemic opacity is a persistent problem for simulations SE, while for STE it need not necessarily be so.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    In this article, I avoid the term social simulation for the reason that this umbrella term also encompasses models employed by, for example, ecologists and computer scientists, who do not relate their work to social theory. Instead, I use the term social science simulation to indicate this difference.

  2. 2.

    Hartmann’s definition applies to non-computational simulations as well. However, they are not relevant for the argument presented here.

  3. 3.

    It is not certain that the restrictive definition of “simulation” by Hartmann (1996) still applies to all examples of current computer simulation, even in the particular domain of social sciences: e.g., there have been simulations that do not imitate a phenomenon with a temporal dimension (see e.g. Winsberg 2009). From this viewpoint, the exclusion of Monte Carlo simulations may also seem excessive and unjustified. However, for our present purposes we prefer a restrictive definition for two reasons: First, the vast majority of simulations in the social sciences are included in this restrictive definition, and it is more transparent to develop the present argument in line with this restrictive definition. Second, the argument may be transferred later to a more comprehensive definition of simulation, including, e.g., Monte Carlo simulations. Consideration of further sorts of current computer simulation would exceed the space limitations of a journal article.

  4. 4.

    I remain neutral toward two theses that have established an argument view. I do not argue that each thought experiment can be reconstructed as an argument (Norton’s thesis put forward in Norton 1996), nor do I argue that each computer simulation can be reconstructed as an argument (Beisbart’s thesis put forward in Beisbart 2012).

References

  • Axtell, R. L., J. M. Epstein, J. S. Dean, G. J. Gumerman, A. C. Swedlund, J. Harburger, S. Chakravarty, R. Hammond, J. Parker, and M. Parker. 2002. Population Growth and Collapse in a Multi-Agent Model of the Kayenta Anasazi in Long House Valley. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 99 (3): 7275–7279.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barberousse, Anouk, Sara Franceschelli, and Cyrille Imbert. 2009. Computer Simulations as Experiments. Synthese 169: 557–574.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Beisbart, Claus. 2011. A Transformation of Normal Science. Computer Simulations From a Philosophical Perspective. Unpublished Habilitation Thesis, Technical University Dortmund.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beisbart, Claus. 2012. How can Computer Simulations Produce New Knowledge? European Journal for Philosophy of Science 2: 395–434.

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Beisbart, Claus, and John D. Norton. 2012. Why Monte Carlo Simulations Are Inferences and Not Experiments. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 26: 403–422.

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Carley, Kathleen M., and Les Gasser. 1999. Computational Organization Theory. In Multiagent Systems. A Modern Approach to Distributed Artificial Intellgence, ed. Gerhard Weiss, 299–330. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conte, Rosaria, Bruce Edmonds, Scott Moss, and R. Keith Sawyer. 2001. Sociology and Social Theory in Agent Based Social Simulation. A Symposium. Computational Mathematical Organization Theory 7: 183–205.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cooper, Rachel. 2005. Thought Experiments. Metaphilosophy 36: 328–347.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dean, J. S., G. J. Gumerman, J. M. Epstein, R. L. Axtell, A. C. Swedlund, M. T. Parker, and S. McCarroll. 2000. Understanding Anasazi Culture Change Through Agent Based Modeling. In Dynamics in Human and Primate Societies: Agent Based Modeling of Social and Spatial Processes, ed. T. Kohler and G. Gumerman. SFI Working Paper 1998-10-094. New York and London: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elsenbroich, Corinna, and Nigel Gilbert. 2014. Modelling Norms. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, Joshua M. 2008. Why Model? Journal of Artificial Societies and Social Simulation 11 (4) 12. http://jasss.soc.surrey.ac.uk/11/4/12.html.

    Google Scholar 

  • Evans, Andrew, Alison Heppenstall, and Mark Birkin. 2013. Understanding Simulation Results. In Simulating Social Complexity. A Handbook, ed. Bruce Edmonds and Ruth Meyer, 173–195. Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gumerman, G. J., A. C. Swedlund, J. S. Dean, and J. M. Epstein. 2003. The Evolution of Social Behavior in the Prehistoric American Southwest. Artificial Life 9: 435–444.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, Ian. 1983. Representing and Intervening: Introductory Topics in the Philosophy of Science. New York: Free Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, Ian. 1992. The Self-Vindication of the Laboratory Sciences. In Science as Practice and Culture, ed. A. Pickering, 29–64. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hartmann, Stephan. 1996. The World as a Process: Simulation in the Natural and Social Sciences. In Modelling and Simulation in the Social Sciences From the Philosophy of Science Point of View, ed. Rainer Hegselmann, Ulrich Müller, and Klaus G. Troitzsch, 77–100. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hedström, Peter. 2005. Dissecting the Social. On the Principles of Analytic Sociology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, Carl Gustav. 1965. Aspects of Scientific Explanation and Other Essays in the Philosophy of Science. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Humphreys, Paul. 2004. Extending Ourselves. Computational Science, Empiricism, and Scientific Method. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Humphreys, Paul. 2009. The Philosophical Novelty of Computer Simulation Methods. Synthese 169: 615–626.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Izquierdo, Luis R., Segismundo S. Izquierdo, José M. Galan, and José I. Santos. 2013. Combining Mathematical and Simulation Approaches to Understand the Dynamics of Computer Models. In Simulating Social Complexity. A Handbook, ed. Bruce Edmonds and Ruth Meyer, 235–271. Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kaminski, Andreas. 2017. Der Erfolg der Modellierung und das Ende der Modelle. Epistemische Opazität in der Computersimulation. In Technik - Macht - Raum. Das Topologische Manifest im Kontext interdisziplinärer Studien, ed. Andreas Brenneis, Oliver Honer, Sina Keesser and Silke Vetter-Schultheiß, Wiesbaden: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, Philip. 1989. Explanatory Unification and the Causal Structure of the World. In Scientific Explanation, ed. Philip Kitcher and W. Salmon, 410–506. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lenhard, Johannes. 2011. Epistemologie der Iteration. Gedankenexperimente und Simulationsexperimente. Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 59: 131–145.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lenhard, Johannes, and Hans Hasse. 2017. Fluch und Segen: Die Rolle anpassbarer Parameter in Simulationsmodellen. In Technisches Nichtwissen. Jahrbuch Technikphilosophie 2017, ed. Alexander Friedrich, Petra Gehring, Christoph Hubig, Andreas Kaminski and Alfred Nordmann, 69–84. Baden-Baden: Nomos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Macy, Michael, and John Skvoretz. 1998. The Evolution of Trust and Cooperation Between Strangers: A Computational Model. American Sociological Review 63: 638–660.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marr, David. 1982. Vision. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, Mary. 2003. Experiments Without Material Intervention. Model Experiments, Virtual Experiments, and Virtually Experiments. In The Philosophy of Scientific Experimentation, ed. Hans Radder, 216–235. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morrison, Margaret. 2009. Models, Measurement, and Computer Simulation: The Changing Face of Experimentation. Philosophical Studies 143: 33–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Norton, John. 1996. Are Thought Experiments Just What You Thought? Canadian Journal of Philosophy 26: 333–366.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sawyer, R. Keith. 2004. The Mechanisms of Emergence. Philosophy of the Social Sciences 34: 260–282.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sawyer, R. Keith. 2013. Interpreting and Understanding Simulations. The Philosophy of Social Simulation. In Simulating Social Complexity. A Handbook, ed. Bruce Edmonds and Ruth Meyer, 273–289. Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Suppes, Patrick. 1968. The Desirability of Formalization in Science. Journal of Philosophy 65: 651–664.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tymoczko, Thomas. 1979. The Four-Color Problem and its Philosophical Significance. Journal of Philosophy 76: 57–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Winsberg, Eric. 2003. Simulated Experiments: Methodology for a Virtual World. Philosophy of Science 70: 105–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Winsberg, Eric. 2009. A Tale of Two Methods. Synthese 169: 575–592.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wolfram, Stephen. 1985. Undecidability and Intractability in Theoretical Physics. Physical Review Letters 54: 735–738.

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, James. 2003. Making Things Happen. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

The author would like to thank Andreas Kaminski for his valuable comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Nicole J. Saam .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this paper

Cite this paper

Saam, N.J. (2017). Understanding Social Science Simulations: Distinguishing Two Categories of Simulations. In: Resch, M., Kaminski, A., Gehring, P. (eds) The Science and Art of Simulation I . Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-55762-5_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics