Skip to main content

Making the Case for Political Anthropology: Understanding and Addressing the Backlash Against Liberalism

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Identity and Difference

Abstract

This chapter outlines the concept and contemporary importance of political anthropology, attempting to understand and address the backlash against inclusive liberal values on this basis. “Political anthropology” refers to an understanding of political activities and notions belonging to the political sphere—such as “justice,” “rights,” etc.—on the basis of philosophical anthropology, classically conceived in terms of conceptions of human nature. Although classic and modern thought has traditionally grounded its analyses of the political with reference to human nature, the mainstream of contemporary thought has—for good reasons—largely abandoned this approach. Abandoning this strategy has itself often been understood as a precondition for justice, a line of thought associated with liberalism.

This chapter is based on the conceptual framework developed and materials included in R. Clancy, Towards a Political Anthropology in the Work of Gilles Deleuze: Psychoanalysis and Anglo-American Literature, Leuven, Leuven University Press, 2015 and “Civil religion as an antidote to political conservatism and religious fundamentalism? Navigating the course between inclusive universalism and exclusive particularism,” Europeana, forthcoming.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Although this perspective is evident throughout, see especially Book 1, Chapter 7.

  2. 2.

    Again, although this perspective is evident throughout, see especially, Book 1, Part Two. For a discussion of these points and their contemporary significance, see Hadley Arkes First things: An inquiry into the first principles of morals and justice, Princeton, Princeton University Press, 1986. 12.

  3. 3.

    This perspective is also, of course, evident in the thought of Rousseau—especially the Social Contract—although in a much different form from thinkers in the liberal tradition. For a discussion of these themes in Rousseau’s thought, see R. Clancy “Civil religion as an antidote to political conservatism and religious fundamentalism? Navigating the course between inclusive universalism and exclusive particularism,” Europeana, forthcoming.

  4. 4.

    Living in the End Times. New York: Verso, 2010. 34.

  5. 5.

    Disagreement: Politics and Philosophy. Trans. Julie Rose. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1999. 76.

  6. 6.

    Michael J. Sandel’s Democracy’s Discontent: America in Search of a Public Philosophy. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1996. 4.

  7. 7.

    On this, see Isaiah Berlin’s classic formulation and defense of negative rights and freedom in “Two Concepts of Freedom.” Four Essays on Liberty. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1969. 118-172.

  8. 8.

    “The Priority of Right and Ideas of the Good.” Collected Papers. Ed. Samuel Freeman. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1999. 450.

  9. 9.

    “Liberalism and Public Morality.” Liberals on Liberalism. Ed. Alfonso J. Damico. Totowa: Rowman and Littlefield, 1986. 143.

  10. 10.

    Making Men Moral: Civil Liberties and Public Morality. New York: Oxford University Press, 2002. 159.

  11. 11.

    A Theory of Justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1971. 13.

  12. 12.

    Additionally, see his subsequent discussions of education, which further bring out Rawls’ paternalism (Theory of Justice, 469-70).

  13. 13.

    Again, the neutrality at the heart of a liberal conception of justice thus implies a conception of human nature as rational, disinterested, and risk avert, where the integration of individuals into community is based on mutual aims and shared interests, where people naturally tend toward agreement through discussion. Although dialogue and communication are less pronounced in Rawls’ earlier work, they seem to figure more prominently by the time of Political Liberalism. Of course, dialogue and communication lie at the heart of Habermas’ political and ethical work, much of which is indicative of and has contributed to recent liberal thought. See especially Habermas 1984 and Habermas 1998.

  14. 14.

    “What’s Wrong with Negative Liberty?” Philosophy and the Human Sciences: Philosophical Papers vol. 2. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985.

  15. 15.

    The Islamic State of Iraq and Syria (ISIS), for example, is often explained in terms of its attempts at establishing an older, more traditional form of Islam, insofar as it attempts to strictly enforce Sharia law. G. Wood, “What ISIS really wants” The Atlantic, March 2015 http://www.theatlantic.com/magazine/archive/2015/03/what-isis-really-wants/384980/

  16. 16.

    For an understanding of religious fundamentalism along these lines, see K. Armstrong, The battle for god, New York, Ballantine books, 2001.

  17. 17.

    See S. Amin and S. Hossain, “Women’s reproductive rights and the politics of fundamentalism: A view from Bangladesh”, in The American University law review 44 Spring 1995 and R. Feldman and K. Clark, “Women, religious fundamentalism and reproductive rights”, in Reproductive health matters, Volume 4, Issue 8 November 1996.

  18. 18.

    In the case of Rorty, this program could be characterized as one where people engage politically, recognizing these engagements as ultimately groundless. In the case of Derrida, such a program could be characterized as “let’s wait and see,” recognizing that one’s political commitments are tentative and always in need of further revision. See, for example, Rorty’s Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1989 and Derrida’s Specters of Marx: The State of the Debt, the Work of Mourning, and the New International. Trans. Peggy Kamuf. New York: Routledge, 1994, respectively.

  19. 19.

    For a discussion of these issues in a philosophical context, see Rudi Visker’s “In Praise of Visibility.” Levinas Studies vol. 3, 2008. 171-191. Much of the work of Visker and Paul Moyaert explores precisely these issues in the context of Levinas’ philosophy and Lacanian theory.

  20. 20.

    “State multiculturalism has failed, says David Cameron.” BBC News: UK Politics. 5 February 2011. http://www.bbc.co.uk/news/uk-politics-12371994

  21. 21.

    See Badiou’s relatively accessible—albeit incomplete—account in Ethics. Trans. Peter Hallward. New York: Verso, 2002. 40-44. In that work, Badiou explains his own “hostility to contemporary consensus on questions of democratic-liberal procedures, human rights, and our much-vaunted respect for cultural difference” (107). Describing the “political act,” Žižek says, “the unity and law of a civil society is imposed onto the people by an act of violence whose agent is not motivated by any moral considerations” (Žižek 2010, 32). This perspective fuels his endorsement of Leninism: “With Lenin…the point is that revolution ne s’autorise que d’elle-même: one should take responsibility for the revolutionary act” (Žižek 2010, 33).

  22. 22.

    See, for example, Richard Dawkins’ The God Delusion. New York: Mariner Books, 2008 and Daniel Dennett’s Darwin’s Dangerous Idea: Evolution and the Meanings of Life. New York: Simon and Shuster, 1995.

  23. 23.

    Finding Darwin’s God: A Scientist’s Search for Common Ground Between God and Evolution. New York: Harper Perennial 2007. 169 ff. See my comments on this in “Review of A.C. Grayling’s Ideas that Matter: The Concepts that Shape the 21 st Century.” Metapsychology Online Reviews vol. 15 issue 13 March 29, 2011. http://metapsychology.mentalhelp.net/poc/view_doc.php?type=book&id=6008&cn=394.

  24. 24.

    See Žižek’s discussions of multiculturalism in The Ticklish Subject: The Absent Centre of Political Ontology. New York: Verso, 2002, as well as the New Americanists on their critique of liberal humanism and its complicity with a conservative ontology.

  25. 25.

    “Dasein is an entity which does not just occur among other entities. Rather it is ontically distinguished by the fact that, in its very Being, that Being is an issue for it. But in that case, this is a constitutive state of Dasein’s Being, and this implies that Dasein, in its Being, has a relationship towards that Being – a relationship which is itself one of Being.” Being and Time. Trans. John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing, 2004. 32.

  26. 26.

    This is already apparent in Being and Time when he writes, “Dasein has grown up both in and into a traditional way of interpreting itself…Its own past – and this always means the past of its ‘generation’ – is not something which follows along after Dasein, but something which already goes ahead of it” (41). This perspective becomes much more explicit in his later works such as “The Origin of the Work of Art” and “The Question Concerning Technology.” Included in Basic Writings. Ed. David Farrell Krell. New York: Harper Perennial, 2008.

  27. 27.

    See, for example, E. Beardsley, “After Paris Attacks, Voltaire’s ‘Tolerance’ Is Back In Vogue”, www.npr.com, February 15, 2015 http://www.npr.org/sections/parallels/2015/02/15/385422239/after-paris-attacks-voltaires-tolerance-is-back-in-vogue

  28. 28.

    Again, for a much fuller discussion of this point, see Clancy 2015.

  29. 29.

    For empirical, social scientific findings regarding these dynamics in social identity theory, see N. Ellemers, R. Spears & B. Doosje “Self and social identity”, Annual review of psychology, 53, 2002, 161-186 and R.J. Fisher The social psychology of intergroup and international conflict resolution, New York, Springer-Verlag, 1990. With regard to the way this dynamic plays out in Chinese studying and working abroad, see H.C. Hail, “Patriotism abroad: Overseas Chinese students’ encounters with criticisms of China”, Journal of studies in international education, January 12, 2015, 1–16, and Tajfel 1978.

  30. 30.

    See Freud 2001 and Lawrence 2005 for an understanding of social identity and group membership along these lines, as well as my commentaries in Clancy 2015.

  31. 31.

    Given its specific conceptual history, the term “essence” here is probably inappropriate, although Sartre never himself ceases to use it. Hence, his dictum that “If God does not exist, there is at least one being in whom existence precedes essence, a being who exists before he can be defined by any concept.” Existentialism and Human Emotions. Trans. Bernard Frechtman. New York: Citadel, 2000. 35.

  32. 32.

    Describing the role of nothingness, the way nothingness acts as a condition of human existence, see Being and Nothingness. Trans. Hazel Barnes. New York: Washington Square Press, 1978. 138.

  33. 33.

    See Deleuze 1991.

  34. 34.

    For a similar understanding of human life with regard to the distinction between work (werk) and labor (arbeiten), see Arendt 1998.

  35. 35.

    “We do not here acknowledge any difference between mankind and other individual natural entities.” A Theologico-Political Treatise in A Theologico-Political Treatise and A Political Treatise. Trans. R.H.M. Elwes. New York: Dover, 2004. 201. “[M]an…is part of nature, and…ought to be referred to the power of nature” (Political Treatise, 292). On this point, Deleuze writes that man “thus loses in Spinozism all the privileges owed to a quality supposed proper to him, which belonged to him only from the viewpoint of imitative participation” in God (Expressionism in Philosophy: Spinoza, 183). In the case of Deleuze, the political consequences of these commitments only become clear from a certain perspective, only after Difference and Repetition and the Logic of Sense and at the beginning of his collaborations with Guattari, in terms of his critique of psychoanalysis and praise for Anglo-American literature. Again, for extended commentaries on these points, see Clancy 2015.

  36. 36.

    Deleuze writes that the “difficult part is making all the elements of non-homogeneous sets converge, making them function together” (Dialogues, 39).

  37. 37.

    Rancière writes that the “foundation of politics is not in fact more a matter of convention than of nature: it is the lack of foundation, the sheer contingency of any social order. Politics exists simply because no social order is based on nature, no divine law regulates human society” (Rancière 16). “This means that politics doesn’t always happen – it actually happens very little or rarely” (Rancière 17).

  38. 38.

    See Lawrence 1995 for an understanding of social identity and group membership along these lines, as well as my commentaries in Clancy 2015.

  39. 39.

    On these points, see the work of geographer Jared Diamond, especially Diamond 1997, as well as anthropologist and environmental scientist Peter Richerson and Robert Boyd, especially Richerson and Boyd 2006.

  40. 40.

    See especially Trying Not to Try: The Art and Science of Spontaneity. Generally translated into English as either non- or effortless action, Slingerland examines descriptions of wu wei in Confucian, Daoist, and Zen texts—similarities in and differences between uses and understandings of this term in these traditions.

  41. 41.

    With reference to the thought of Deleuze, much of Rosi Braidotti’s work focuses on cultivating a similar embodied perspective on ethics. See especially Braidotti, 2011 and Braidotti, 2012.

  42. 42.

    This thesis was first put forward in Clark and Chalmers 1998. See Nöe 2009, 81-82 for a discussion of its relation to theories of embodiment and consciousness. See Aydin 2013 for an excellent discussion of the relation between the extended mind thesis and technology, as well as Hansell and Grassie 2011 regarding the relation between technology and human nature from a variety of perspectives.

  43. 43.

    See Latour 1986 and Latour 1988 regarding ANT in general, and Latour 2004 with regard ANT’s relation to politics.

Bibliography

  • Arendt, H. 1998, The Human Condition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle 1995a, “Nicomachean Ethics”, in Jonathan Barnes (ed.), The Complete Works of Aristotle, Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle, 1995b, “Politics”, in Jonathan Barnes (ed.), The Complete Works of Aristotle, Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arkes, H. 1986, First Things: An Inquiry into the First Principles of Morals and Justice, Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Armstrong, K. 2001, The Battle for God, New York: Ballantine Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aydin, C. 2013 “The artifactual mind: overcoming the ‘inside–outside’ dualism in the extended mind thesis and recognizing the technological dimension of cognition,” Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 14 (1). 73–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beardsley, E. 2015, “After Paris attacks, Voltaire’s ‘tolerance’ is back in vogue,” www.npr.com, February 15,http://www.npr.org/sections/parallels/2015/02/15/385422239/after-paris-attacks-voltaires-tolerance-is-back-in-vogue

  • Berlin, I. 1969, “Two concepts of freedom,” in: Berlin, I. (ed.) Four Essays on Liberty, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Braidotti, R. 2011. Nomadic Subjects: Embodiment and Sexual Difference in Contemporary Feminist Theory, Second Edition. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Braidotti, R. 2012. Nomadic Theory: The Portable Rosi Braidotti. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clancy, R. 2011, “Review of A.C. Grayling’s Ideas that matter: The concepts that shape the 21 st century,” Metapsychology Online Reviews, 15, 13 March 29, http://metapsychology.mentalhelp.net/poc/view_doc.php?type=book&id=6008&cn=394.

  • Clancy, R. 2015, Towards a Political Anthropology in the Work of Gilles Deleuze: Psychoanalysis and Anglo-American Literature, Leuven: Leuven University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark A., & D. Chalmers, “The Extended Mind,” Analysis, 58 (1998), 10–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deleuze, G. 1988, Spinoza: Practical Philosophy, transl. R. Hurley, San Francisco: City Light Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deleuze, G. 1991, Empiricism and Subjectivity: An Essay on Hume’s Theory of Human Nature, transl. C. Boundas, New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deleuze, G. 1998, Essays Critical and Clinical, transl. D. Smith and M. Greco, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deleuze, G. 2005, Expressionism in Philosophy: Spinoza, transl. M. Joughin, New York: Zone.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deleuze, G. & Guattari, F 2005, A Thousand Plateaus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia vol. II, transl. B. Massumi, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Derrida, J. 1994, Specters of Marx: The State of the Debt, the Work of Mourning, and the New International, transl. P. Kamuf, New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diamond, J., Guns, germs and steel, New York, W.W. Norton, 1997.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. 1983, “A Reply by Ronald Dworkin,” in M. Cohen (ed.), Ronald Dworkin and Contemporary Jurisprudence, Totowa, NJ: Rowan and Allanheld. pp. 245–6.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. 1985, A Matter of Principle, Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellemers, N., Spears, R., & Doosje, B. 2002, “Self and social identity,” Annual Review of Psychology, 53, 161–186.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fisher, R. J. 1990, The Social Psychology of Intergroup and International Conflict Resolution, New York, Springer-Verlag.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Freud, S. 2001, “Civilization and its discontents”, in James Strachey (ed.), The Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud, vol. 21, London: Vintage Books. pp. 59–148.

    Google Scholar 

  • Galston, W. 1986, “Liberalism and Public Morality,” in A. Damico (ed.), Liberals on Liberalism, Totowa: Rowman and Littlefield. pp. 129–147.

    Google Scholar 

  • George, R. 2002, Making Men Moral: Civil Liberties and Public Morality, New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. 1984, Theory of Communicative Action vol. 1 Reason and the Rationalization of Society, transl. T. McCarthy, Boston: Beacon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. 1998, On the Pragmatics of Communication, M. Cooke (ed.), Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hansell, G. and W. Grassie (eds.) 2011, H± Transhumanism and its Critics. Philadelphia: Metanexus Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. 2004, Being and Time, transl. J. Macquarrie & E. Robinson, Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobbes, T. 1985, Leviathan, London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huntington, S. 2011, The Clash of Civilizations and the Remaking of World Order, New York: Simon and Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Latour, B. 1986, Laboratory Life: The Construction of Scientific Facts. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Latour, B. 1988, Science in Action: How to Follow Scientists and Engineers Through Society. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Latour, B. 2004, Politics of Nature: How to Bring the Sciences into Democracy, transl. C. Porter, Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawrence, D.H. 1995, Apocalypse and Other Writings on Revelation, M. Kalnins (ed.), London: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawrence, D.H. 2005, Psychoanalysis and the Unconscious and Fantasia of the Unconscious, New York: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, K. 2007, Finding Darwin’s God: A Scientist’s Search for Common Ground Between God and Evolution, New York: Harper Perennial.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. Out of Our Heads: Why You Are Not Your Brain, and Other Lessons from the Biology of Consciousness. New York: Hill and Wang, 2010.

    Google Scholar 

  • Plato 1999, “Republic”, in E. Hamilton & H. Cairns (eds.), The Collected Dialogues of Plato, Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rancière, J. 1999, Disagreement: Politics and Philosophy, transl. J. Rose, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1999.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. 1971, A Theory of Justice, Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. 1999, “The Priority of Right and Ideas of the Good,” in S. Freeman (ed.), Collected Papers, Cambridge: Harvard University Press. pp. 449–472.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. 2005, Political Liberalism, expanded edition, New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. 1988, The Morality of Freedom, Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Richerson, P. & R. Boyd 2006, Not by Genes Alone: How Culture Transformed Human Evolution. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, R. 1989, Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity, New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rousseau, J.J. 1974, The Social Contract, in: The Essential Rousseau, transl. L. Bair, New York: Signet Classics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sandel, M. 1996, Democracy’s Discontent: America in Search of a Public Philosophy, Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, J.P. 1978, Being and Nothingness, transl. H. Barnes, New York: Washington Square Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, J.P. 2000, Existentialism and Human Emotions, transl. B. Frechtman, New York: Citadel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spinoza 2004, A Theologico-Political Treatise and A Political Treatise, transl. R.H.M. Elwes, New York: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spinoza 2005, Ethics, transl. E. Curley, New York: Penguin Classics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slingerland, E. (2014). Trying Not to Try: The Art and Science of Spontaneity. New York: Crown Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, D. 2014, Deleuze, Technology, and Thought, paper presented at Shanghai Jiao Tong University on July 29.

    Google Scholar 

  • “State multiculturalism has failed, says David Cameron” 2011, BBC News: UK Politics, 5 February, http://www.bbc.co.uk/news/uk-politics-12371994.

  • Tajfel, H. 1978, “Social categorization, social identity and social comparison,” in H. Tajfel (ed.), Differentiation between Social Groups: Studies in the Social Psychology of Intergroup Relations, London, England: Academic Press. pp. 61–83

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, C. 1985, “What’s Wrong with Negative Liberty?,” in Taylor, C. (ed.), Philosophy and the Human Sciences: Philosophical Papers vol. 2, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 211–229.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Visker, R. 2008, “In praise of visibility,” Levinas Studies 3, 171–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Žižek, S. 2002, The Ticklish Subject: The Absent Centre of Political Ontology, New York: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Žižek, S. 2010, Living in the End Times, New York: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Clancy, R.F. (2016). Making the Case for Political Anthropology: Understanding and Addressing the Backlash Against Liberalism. In: Winkler, R. (eds) Identity and Difference. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-40427-1_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics