Skip to main content

Biology and Subjectivity: Philosophical Contributions to a Non-reductive Neuroscience

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Biology and Subjectivity

Abstract

In the middle of the twentieth century, Wittgenstein warned that “the method of reducing the explanation of natural phenomena to the smallest possible number of primitive natural laws…leads…into complete darkness” (1958, p. 18). At the time, few philosophers and even fewer scientists were prepared to heed his warning. A half-century later, however, the reductive method of science—the method famously defined by Descartes, brilliantly exemplified by Newtonian physics, and long upheld as the gold standard of scientific explanation—seems to have finally lost its luster. While reduction is still widely defended, in the last decades alternative views have gained credibility, to the extent that a “non-reductive science” is no longer dismissed as an oxymoron.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

References

  • Barlow, H.B. 1972. Single units and sensation: A neuron doctrine for perceptual psychology? Perception 1: 371–394.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, M.R., and P.M.S. Hacker. 2003. Philosophical foundations of neuroscience. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bickle, J. 2003. Philosophy and neuroscience: A ruthlessly reductive account. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bullock, T.H., M.V.L. Bennett, D. Johnston, R. Josephson, E. Marder, and R.D. Fields. 2005. The neuron doctrine, redux. Science 310: 791–793.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chirimuuta, M., and I. Gold. 2009. The embedded neuron, the enactive field? In The Oxford handbook of philosophy and neuroscience, ed. J. Bickle. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Choudhury, S., and J. Slaby. 2012. Critical neuroscience: A handbook for the social and cultural contexts of neuroscience. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. 1972. The reflex arc concept in psychology. In The early works of John Dewey 1882–1898, Volume 5: 1895–1898, ed. J. Boydston. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press (Original work published 1896).

    Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, W.J. 1999. How brains make up their minds. New York: Colombia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. 2006. How the body shapes the mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guillery, R.W. 2005. Observations of synaptic structures: Origins of the neuron doctrine and its current status. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B 360: 1281–1307.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hubel, D.H., and T.N. Wiesel. 1959. Receptive fields of single neurons in the cat’s striate cortex. Journal of Physiology 148: 574–591.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Juarrero, A. 1999. Dynamics in action: Intentional behavior as a complex system. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kauffman, S.A. 2000. Investigations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keeley, B.L. 2009. The role of neurobiology in differentiating the senses. In The Oxford handbook of philosophy and neuroscience, ed. J. Bickle. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelso, J.A.S. 1995. Dynamic patterns: The self-organization of brain and behavior. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuffler, S.W. 1953. Discharge patterns and functional organization of mammalian retina. Journal of Neurophysiology 16: 37–68.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos, I. 1970. Falsification and the methodology of scientific research programmes. In Criticism and the growth of knowledge, ed. I. Lakatos and A. Musgrave. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Langton, R. 2000. The musical, the magical, and the mathematical soul. In History of the mind-body problem, ed. T. Crane and S. Patterson. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laughlin, R.B. 2005. A different universe: Reinventing physics from the bottom down. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murphy, N. 2006. Bodies and souls, or spirited bodies? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. 2009. Out of our heads: Why you are not your brain, and other lessons from the biology of consciousness. New York: Hill and Wang.

    Google Scholar 

  • Northoff, R. 2013. Unlocking the brain: Volume 1: Coding. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Northoff, R. 2014. Minding the brain: A guide to philosophy and neuroscience. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M.C., and A.O. Rorty. 1992. Essays on Aristotle’s ‘De Anima’. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. 1994. Putnam, Hilary. In A Companion to the Philosophy of Mind, ed. S. Guttenplan, 507–513. Cambridge: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, D.N. 1976. An intellectual history of psychology. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, R. 1991. Life itself: A comprehensive inquiry into the nature, origin, and fabrication of life. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sheets-Johnstone, M. 2011. The primacy of movement, expanded, 2nd ed. Amsterdam: John Benjamins Publishing.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Smolin, L. 2006. The trouble with physics: The rise of string theory, the fall of a science, and what comes next. New York: Mariner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, E. 2007. Mind in life: Biology, phenomenology, and the sciences of mind. Cambridge: Belknap.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F. 2000. El fenómeno de la vida. Santiago de Chile: Editorial Dolmen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weiss, P.A. 1973. The science of life: The system of living—A system for life. New York: Futura.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. 1958. The blue and brown books. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolfram, S. 2002. A new kind of science. Champaign: Wolfram Media.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. 2005. Subjectivity and selfhood: investigating the first-person perspective. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Miguel García-Valdecasas .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Murillo, J.I., García-Valdecasas, M., Barrett, N.F. (2016). Biology and Subjectivity: Philosophical Contributions to a Non-reductive Neuroscience. In: García-Valdecasas, M., Murillo, J., Barrett, N. (eds) Biology and Subjectivity. Historical-Analytical Studies on Nature, Mind and Action, vol 2. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-30502-8_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics