Skip to main content

On Split Negation, Strong Negation, Information, Falsification, and Verification

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
J. Michael Dunn on Information Based Logics

Part of the book series: Outstanding Contributions to Logic ((OCTR,volume 8))

Abstract

This paper deals with some criticism that has been put forward against strong, constructive negation in comparison to a certain example of Galois connected negations. The general background to this discussion is the informational interpretation of substructural logics, and the key issue is whether there exists an asymmetry or not between positive and negative information and between verification and falsification. The present paper confirms the view that a symmetrical conception is adequate for both direct and indirect variants of verification and falsification.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The association with Fregean thoughts may prompt further discussion. In his famous paper on sense and reference (Frege 1892), Frege considers an example of a fictional sentence that has no truth value but nevertheless expresses a thought. In the later paper “Compound Thoughts” (Frege 1923), however, he characterizes a thought as “something which must be either true or false, tertium non datur.”

  2. 2.

    Sequoiah-Grayson uses ‘\(\lnot \)’ instead of ‘\(\lnot ^r\)’ and ‘\(\sim \)’ instead of ‘\(\lnot ^l\)’. The superscripts have the advantage of reminding one of the directionality of the implication that is involved.

  3. 3.

    We may assume that there is a typing error in the versions of (3) and (4) in Sequoiah-Grayson (2009). With these versions:  

    (3)\(_{SG}\) :

    \(x\Vdash A\rightarrow B\text { iff for all }y,z\in S,\text { if }x \bullet y\sqsubseteq z\text { and }y\Vdash A,\text { then }z\Vdash B\)

    (4)\(_{SG}\) :

    \(x\Vdash A\leftarrow B\text { iff for all }y,z\in S, \text { if }y\bullet x\sqsubseteq z\text { and }y\Vdash A,\text { then }z\Vdash B\)

        \(x \Vdash (A\rightarrow B)\otimes A\) implies \(x\Vdash B\) and \(x\Vdash A\otimes (A \leftarrow B)\) implies \(x\Vdash B\), and, as a result, we do not obtain (6) and (7).

  4. 4.

    He writes (Sequoiah-Grayson 2009, p. 236):

    One might wish to understand ‘supports’ as ‘makes true’ if one holds to a dialethic paraconsistentism whereby at least some contradictions are taken to be true. However, we will sidestep this particular debate and stay with the interpretation of ‘supports’ that takes it to be the subtler relative of ‘makes true’ in a manner aligned with Mares’ informational interpretation.

    .

  5. 5.

    Note that in this paper I do not pay close attention to the mention/use distinction when there is no risk of confusion.

  6. 6.

    An anonymous reviewer raised the question whether there are other ways of defining a semantics in order to obtain a formal reconstruction of the presentation in (Sequoiah-Grayson 2009). I have nothing else to offer than the preservation of support-of-information-that, which captures derivability in NL\(\mathbf{0 }\).

  7. 7.

    Assuming sequent rules that capture Sequoiah-Grayson’s (3)\(_{SG}\) and (4)\(_{SG}\) instead of (3) and (4) would not help.

  8. 8.

    Analogous remarks apply to the inference pattern (21) and the “prohibited procedure” (22). Also the endorsed inference patterns

    1. (23)

      \(A\rightarrow \lnot B\vdash {\sim }A\leftarrow B\), and

    2. (24)

      \(A\rightarrow {\sim }B\vdash \lnot A\leftarrow B\)

    are not provable, so that they are not underpinned by the formulas numbered (25) and (26) in (Sequoiah-Grayson 2009).

  9. 9.

    It is complicated in the constructive setting of intuitionistic logic and N3 already, cf. (Wansing 2006).

  10. 10.

    Note that the strong negation \({\sim }\) is different from Sequoiah-Grayson’s \({\sim }\), i.e., \(A\rightarrow \mathbf{0 }\).

  11. 11.

    Since in ordinary natural deduction a formula A is a proof of A from \(\{\,A\,\}\), the cancellation of formulas amounts to the cancellation of proofs.

  12. 12.

    In these tables, Ep stands for “elimination from proofs,” Ip for “introduction into proofs,” Edp for “elimination from dual proofs,” and Idp for “introduction into dual proofs.”

  13. 13.

    Another translation presented in (Wansing 2013) gives one a faithful embedding of 2Int into dual intuitionistic logic with respect to dual entailment.

  14. 14.

    Cf. (Wansing 2010), where I consider extensions of Heyting–Brouwer logic (Rauszer 1980) by strong negation and refer to reductions to non-truth as dual proofs.

  15. 15.

    In (Kapsner 2014), a detailed analysis is presented of Michael Dummett’s views on the interaction between verification and falsification in an inferentialist theory of meaning. In that context Kapsner argues for “the superiority of the Nelson account over the intuitionistic one,” (Kapsner 2014, p. 198).

References

  • Adriaans, P. (2013). Information. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, fall 2013 ed. http://www.plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2013/entries/information/.

  • Belnap, N. D. (1977a). How a computer should think. In G. Ryle (Ed.), Contemporary aspects of philosophy (pp. 30–56). Stocksfield: Oriel Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Belnap, N. D. (1977b). A useful four-valued logic. In J. M. Dunn & G. Epstein (Eds.), Modern uses of multiple-valued logic (pp. 8–37). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berto, F. (2015). A modality called ‘negation’. Mind, 124, 761–793.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bimbó, K. & Dunn, J. M. (2008). Generalized Galois logics. Relational semantics of nonclassical logical calculi, Volume 188 of CSLI Lecture Notes. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Birkhoff, G., & von Neumann, J. (1936). The logic of quantum mechanics. Annals of Mathematics, 37, 823–843.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Došen, K. (1984). Negative modal operators in intuitionistic logic. Publications de l’Institut Mathématique. Nouvelle Série, 35(49), 3–14. See also at www.emis.de/journals/PIMB/049/n049p003.pdf.

  • Došen, K. (1986). Negation as a modal operator. Reports on Mathematical Logic, 20, 15–27.

    Google Scholar 

  • Došen, K. (1999). Negation in the light of modal logic. In D. Gabbay & H. Wansing (Eds.), What is negation? (pp. 77–86). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dunn, J. M. (1966). The algebra of intensional logics, PhD thesis. Ann Arbor (UMI): University of Pittsburgh.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dunn, J. M. (1976). Intuitive semantics for first-degree entailments and ‘coupled trees’. Philosophical Studies, 29, 149–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dunn, J. M. (1986). Relevance logic and entailment. In D. Gabbay & F. Guenthner (Eds.), Handbook of philosophical logic (1st ed., Vol. 3, pp. 117–224). Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Dunn, J. M. (1991). Gaggle theory: An abstraction of Galois connections and residuation with applications to negation, implication, and various logical operators. In van Eijck, J. (Ed.), Logics in AI: European Workshop JELIA’90, Volume 478 of Lecture Notes in Computer Science (pp. 31–51). Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dunn, J. M. (1993). Star and perp: Two treatments of negation. In Tomberlin, J. (Ed.), Philosophical perspectives, language and logic, (Vol. 7, pp. 331–357)

    Google Scholar 

  • Dunn, J. M. (1995). Gaggle theory applied to intuitionistic, modal and relevance logic. In: I. Max & W. Stelzner (Eds.), Logik und Mathematik. Frege-Kolloquim Jena (pp. 335–368). Berlin: W. de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dunn, J. M. (1996). Generalised ortho negation. In H. Wansing (Ed.), Negation: A notion in focus (pp. 3–26). Berlin: W. de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dunn, J. M. (1999). A comparative study of various model-theoretic treatments of negation: A history of formal negation. In D. M. Gabbay & H. Wansing (Eds.), What is negation? (pp. 23–51). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Dunn, J. M. (2000). Partiality and its dual. Studia Logica, 65, 5–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dunn, J. M. (2001). The concept of information and the development of modern logic. In W. Stelzner & M. Stöckler (Eds.), Zwischen traditioneller und moderner Logik: Nichtklassische Ansätze (pp. 423–447). Paderborn: Mentis-Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dunn, J. M. (2008). Information in computer science. In: P. Adriaans & J. van Benthem (Eds.), Philosophy of information. Handbook of the philosophy of science, (D. M. Gabbay, P. Thagard, J. Woods (Eds.)) (Vol.8, pp. 581–608). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dunn, J. M. (2010). Contradictory information: too much of a good thing. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 39, 425–452.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dunn, J. M. & Hardegree, G. M. (2001). Algebraic methods in philosophical logic, Vol. 41 of Oxford Logic Guides. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dunn, J. M., & Zhou, C. (2005). Negation in the context of gaggle theory. Studia Logica, 80, 235–264.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Floridi, L. (2015). Semantic conceptions of information. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (spring 2015 ed.). http://www.plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2015/entries/information-semantic/.

  • Frege, G. (1892). Über Sinn und Bedeutung. Zeitschrift für Philosophie und Philosophische Kritik NF, 100, 25–50.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1923). Gedankengefüge. Beiträge zur Philosophie des Deutschen Idealismus, 3, 36–51.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gabbay, D., & Wansing, H. (Eds.). (1999). What is negation?. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldblatt, R. (1974). Semantic analysis of orthologic. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 3, 19–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldblatt, R. (1975). The Stone space of an ortholattice. Bulletin of the London Mathematical Society, 7, 45–48.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grzegorczyk, A. (1964). A philosophically plausible formal interpretation of intuitionistic logic. Indagationes Mathematicae, 26, 596–601.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gurevich, Y. (1977). Intuitionistic logic with strong negation. Studia Logica, 36, 49–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hartonas, C. & Dunn, J. M. (1993). Duality theorems for partial orders, semilattices, Galois connections and lattices, Technical Report Preprint No. IULG-93-26, Indiana University Logic Preprint Series.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horn, L. R. & Wansing, H. (2015). Negation. In: E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (spring 2015 ed.). http://www.plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2015/entries/negation/.

  • Kamide, N. & Wansing, H. (2011). Connexive modal logic based on positive S4. In J.-Y. Béziau & M. Coniglio (Eds.), Logic without Frontiers. Festschrift for Walter Alexandre Carnielli on the occasion of his 60th birthday (pp. 389–409). London: College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kamide, N., & Wansing, H. (2012). Proof theory of Nelson’s paraconsistent logic: A uniform perspective. Theoretical Computer Science, 415, 1–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kamide, N., & Wansing, H. (2015). Proof theory of N4-related paraconsistent logics. London: College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kapsner, A. (2014). Logics and falsifications, A new perspective on constructivist semantics. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lambek, J. (1958). The mathematics of sentence structure. American Mathematical Monthly, 65, 154–169.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lambek, J. (1961). On the calculus of syntactic types. In R. Jacobson (Ed.), Structure of language and its mathematical aspects (pp. 166–178). RI: American Mathematical Society, Providence.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Mares, E. D. (2009). General information in relevant logic. Synthese, 167, 343–362.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nelson, D. (1959). Negation and separation of concepts in constructive systems. In A. Heyting (Ed.), Constructivity in mathematics (pp. 208–225). Amsterdam: North-Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Odintsov, S. (2008). Constructive negations and paraconsistency, Vol. 26. of Trends in Logic. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Odintsov, S. P. (2005). The class of extensions of Nelson’s paraconsistent logic. Studia Logica, 80, 291–320.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Odintsov, S. P., & Wansing, H. (2015). The logic of generalized truth values and the logic of bilattices. Studia Logica, 103, 91–112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Onishi, T. (2015). Substructural negations. Australasian Journal of Logic, 12, 177–203.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paoli, F. (2002). Substructural logics: A primer. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Paoli, F., & Tsinakis, C. (2012). On Birkhoff’s common abstraction problem. Studia Logica, 100, 1079–1105.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rauszer, C. (1980). An algebraic and Kripke-style approach to a certain extension of intuitionistic logic, Dissertationes Mathematicae 167. Polish Academy of Sciences, Warsaw: Institute of Mathematics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Restall, G. (1999). Negation in relevant logics (How I stopped worrying and learned to love the Routley star). In D. Gabbay & H. Wansing (Eds.), What is negation? (pp. 53–76). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Restall, G. (2000). An introduction to substructural logics. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Routley, R. & Meyer, R. K. (1972). The semantics of entailment, II-III. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 1, 53–73 and 192–208.

    Google Scholar 

  • Routley, R. & Meyer, R. K. (1973). The semantics of entailment. In: H. Leblanc (Ed.), Truth, syntax and modality, Proceedings of the Temple University Conference on Alternative Semantics (pp. 199–243). North-Holland, Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sequoiah-Grayson, S. (2009). Dynamic negation and negative information. Review of Symbolic Logic, 2(1), 233–248.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shramko, Y. (2005). Dual intuitionistic logic and a variety of negations: The logic of scientific research. Studia Logica, 80, 347–367.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shramko, Y., & Wansing, H. (2005). Some useful 16-valued logics: How a computer network should think. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 34, 121–153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shramko, Y., & Wansing, H. (2011). Truth and falsehood: An inquiry into generalized logical values. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vakarelov, D. (1977). Theory of negation in certain logical systems: Algebraic and semantic approach, PhD thesis, University of Warsaw.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vakarelov, D. (1989). Consistency, completeness and negations. In G. Priest, R. Routley, & J. Norman (Eds.), Paraconsistent logic: Essays on the inconsistent (pp. 328–368). Munich: Philosophia Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wansing, H. (1993a). Informational interpretation of substructural propositional logics. Journal of Logic, Language and Information, 2, 285–308.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wansing, H. (1993b). The logic of information structures. Vol. 681 of Lecture Notes in AI. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wansing, H. (2001). Negation. In L. Goble (Ed.), The Blackwell guide to philosophical logic (pp. 415–436). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wansing, H. (2005). Connexive modal logic. In R. Schmidt, I. Pratt-Hartmann, M. Reynolds, & H. Wansing (Eds.), Advances in modal logic (Vol. 5, pp. 367–383). London: College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wansing, H. (2006). Contradiction and contrariety. Priest on negation. In J. Malinowski & A. Pietruszczak (Eds.), Essays in logic and ontology (pp. 81–93). Amsterdam: Rodopi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wansing, H. (2008). Constructive negation, implication, and co-implication. Journal of Non-Classical Logics, 18, 341–364.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wansing, H. (2010). Proofs, disproofs, and their duals. In V. Goranko, L. Beklemishev, & V. Shehtman (Eds.), Advances in modal logic (Vol. 8, pp. 483–505). London: College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wansing, H. (2013). Falsification, natural deduction and bi-intuitionistic logic. Journal of Logic and Computation. Published as “first online” on July 17th, 2013. doi:10.1093/logcom/ext035.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wansing, H. (2014). Connexive logic. In: E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, fall 2014 ed. http://www.plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2014/entries/logic-connexive/.

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank Katalin Bimbó, Yaroslav Shramko, Stanislav Speranski and two anonymous referees for their very helpful comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Heinrich Wansing .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Wansing, H. (2016). On Split Negation, Strong Negation, Information, Falsification, and Verification. In: Bimbó, K. (eds) J. Michael Dunn on Information Based Logics. Outstanding Contributions to Logic, vol 8. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-29300-4_10

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics