Skip to main content
Log in

Missing systems and the face value practice

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Call a bit of scientific discourse a description of a missing system when (i) it has the surface appearance of an accurate description of an actual, concrete system (or kind of system) from the domain of inquiry, but (ii) there are no actual, concrete systems in the world around us fitting the description it contains, and (iii) that fact is recognised from the outset by competent practitioners of the scientific discipline in question. Scientific textbooks, classroom lectures, and journal articles abound with such passages; and there is a widespread practice of talking and thinking as though there are systems which fit the descriptions they contain perfectly, despite the recognition that no actual, concrete systems do so—call this the face value practice. There are, furthermore, many instances in which philosophers engage in the face value practice whilst offering answers to epistemological and methodological questions about the sciences. Three questions, then: (1) How should we interpret descriptions of missing systems? (2) How should we make sense of the face value practice? (3) Is there a set of plausible answers to (1) and (2) which legitimates reliance on the face value practice in our philosophical work, and can support the weight of the accounts which are entangled with that practice? In this paper I address these questions by considering three answers to the first: that descriptions of missing systems are straightforward descriptions of abstract objects, that they are indirect descriptions of “property-containing” abstracta, and that they are (in a different way) indirect descriptions of mathematical structures. All three proposals are present in the literature, but I find them wanting. The result is to highlight the importance of developing a satisfactory understanding of descriptions of missing systems and the face value practice, to put pressure on philosophical accounts which rely on the practice, and to help us assess the viability of certain approaches to thinking about models, theory structure, and scientific representation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Cartwright N. (1983) How the laws of physics lie. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Downes, S. M. (1992). The importance of models in theorizing: A deflationary semantic view. In D. Hull, M. Forbes, & K. Okruhlik, (Eds.), PSA 1992: Proceedings of the 1992 biennial meeting of the philosophy of science association (Vol. 1, pp. 142–153). East Lansing: Philosophy of Science Association.

  • Gánti T., Griesemer J., Szathmáry E. (2003) The principles of life. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere R.N. (1988) Explaining science: A cognitive approach. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere R.N. (2004) How models are used to represent reality. Philosophy of Science 71: 742–752

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P. (2006) The strategy of model-based science. Biology and Philosophy 21: 725–740

    Google Scholar 

  • Hughes R.I.G. (1997) Models and representation. Philosophy of Science 64: S325–S336

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jones, M. R. (2005). Idealization and abstraction: A framework. In: M. R. Jones & N. Cartwright (Eds.), Idealization XII—Correcting the model: Idealization and abstraction in the sciences (Poznan studies in the philosophy of the sciences and the humanities) (Vol. 86, pp. 173–217). Amsterdam/New York, NY: Rodopi.

  • Maynard Smith J., Szathmáry E. (1995) The major transitions is evolution. W. H. Freeman, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan, M., Morrison, M.S. (eds) (1999) Models as mediators: Perspectives on natural and social science. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Poincaré, H. (1952). Science and hypothesis. New York, Dover Publications

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppes P. (1957) Introduction to logic. Princeton, Van Nostrand

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppes P. (1960) A comparison of the meaning and uses of models in mathematics and the empirical sciences. Synthese 12: 287–301

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suppes P. (1967) What is a scientific theory?. In: Morgenbesser S. (eds) Philosophy of science today. Basic Books, New York, pp 55–67

    Google Scholar 

  • Teller P. (2001) Twilight of the perfect model model. Erkenntnis 55: 393–415

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomson-Jones M. (2006) Models and the semantic view. Philosophy of Science 73: 524–535

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomson-Jones, M. (2007). Missing systems and the face value practice. Retrievable from http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/archive/00003519 and http://www.oberlin.edu/faculty/mthomson-jones.

  • Thomson-Jones, M. (in preparation a). Mathematical and propositional models.

  • Thomson-Jones, M. (in preparation b). Little fictions and missing systems.

  • van Fraassen B.C. (1970) On the extension of Beth’s semantics of physical theories. Philosophy of Science 37: 325–339

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen B.C. (1980) The scientific image. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen B.C. (1987) The semantic approach to scientific theories. In: Nersessian N.J. (eds) The process of science. Martinus Nijhoff, Dordrecht, pp 105–124

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolpert L., Jessell T., Lawrence P., Meyerowitz E., Robertson E., Smith J. (2007) Principles of development (3rd eds). Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Martin Thomson-Jones.

Additional information

This paper has been distilled from parts of Thomson-Jones (2007), a much longer, unpublished paper of the same title which can be found online at http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/archive/00003519 and http://www.oberlin.edu/faculty/mthomson-jones.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Thomson-Jones, M. Missing systems and the face value practice. Synthese 172, 283 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-009-9507-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-009-9507-y

Keywords

Navigation