Skip to main content

Can There Be Institutions Without Constitutive Rules?

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Tuomela on Sociality

Part of the book series: Philosophers in Depth ((PID))

Abstract

Institutions depend on rules. But on what kind of rules? It has been argued that they depend on constitutive rules, this in contrast to ordinary social practices, which depend on regulative rules instead. The underlying idea is that constitutive rules differ categorically from regulative rules. Against this, I argue that regulative rules can be transformed into constitutive rules by doing little more than introducing a status term. The presence or absence of a status term does not make a difference to whether a social practice qualifies as an institution. In light of this, I propose that, pace Searle, there can be institutions without constitutive rules. Furthermore, even if it sounds somewhat paradoxical, regulative rules can constitute institutions. This implies that the distinction between social practices and institutions cannot be drawn in terms of these two kinds of rules. Following Tuomela, I propose to draw this distinction in terms of social norms instead: in contrast to ordinary social practices, institutions are governed by social norms. Hence, what is distinctive of institutions is that they feature deontic powers.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 119.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    It is not entirely clear whether this structural feature should be regarded as part of what constitutive rules are. Although Searle mentions it throughout his work, he has also made a few claims that suggest a weaker view. In particular, early on he claimed that constitutive rules can have the same structure as regulative rules (Searle 1969, p. 34). Strikingly, this comes close to the claim that I defend below, that regulative rules can constitute institutions as well.

  2. 2.

    Searle (1995) and Tuomela (1995, 2013) maintain that institutions must be accepted collectively. By this they mean that they depend on attitudes that are irreducibly collective. Tuomela takes this to imply that people must be collectively committed to the relevant rules. Searle (2010) has abandoned this requirement and regards general acceptance as sufficient.

  3. 3.

    More complex regulative rules feature permissions, prohibitions or other kinds of obligations or rights. Note that Searle takes regulative rules to have the structure of an imperative. And some such rules do indeed to have this surface structure. Think, for instance, of ‘wear a tie to a formal dinner’ or ‘keep to the right.’ However, such statements specify actions that people are supposed to perform. In light of this, I believe that they are better explicated in terms of deontic powers (cf. Hart 1961).

  4. 4.

    Because of this, Guala and I use the term ‘constitutive rule’ for a combination of a base rule and a status rule, a B and an S that pertain to one and the same status (Hindriks and Guala 2015). To avoid confusion, I follow Searle and Tuomela here and use the term for base rules only.

  5. 5.

    When a regulative rule is in force, there will also be a status, even if only implicitly. For instance, money and property function as such even if people do not have words for these statuses (Hindriks and Guala 2015, pp. 473–477).

  6. 6.

    As they regulate behavior, status rules are a special kind of regulative rule.

  7. 7.

    Tuomela presented his criticism in two places. In a response to a critical appreciation that I made of his book Social Ontology (Tuomela 2017). And in an unpublished comment that was intended to be included as an appendix to his paper ‘Social Corporations as Social Institutions’ (Tuomela 2020). I include the comment as an appendix to this paper. And I thank his wife, Maj Tuomela, who has been so kind as to grant me permission to use and reproduce it here.

  8. 8.

    Earlier Searle claimed that the rule ““drive on the right side of the road” regulates driving; but driving can exist prior to the existence of that rule.” (1995, p. 27)

  9. 9.

    See Raz (1986) for an insightful discussion of internal value and social meaning. MacIntyre (1981) uses the contrast between internal and external values to distinguish between social practices and institutions, but exactly in the opposite way. He argues that values are internal to social practices and external to institutions (which he takes to be complex organizations).

  10. 10.

    Tuomela claims that “R does not say how the institution of property can be used.” (n.d.) However, the right to use that which you own is in principle unrestricted. So, R is formulated as it should be. To be sure, it is incomplete as an account of property, because it does not feature the right to exclude others from using it and the rights of transfer. But this is because it is a toy example. Note that Searle (2015, p. 510) disqualifies our account of property as unrealistic. But he fails to note that we are not concerned with the everyday institution of property, which is why we add an asterisk to ‘property*’, as I have done in Sect. 1.

  11. 11.

    In fact, our main goal is to integrate the notion of a constitutive rule in a unified theory of institutions (Guala and Hindriks 2015; Hindriks and Guala 2015). This theory combines it with regulative rule theories as well as equilibrium theories. See Ross (1957) for an attempt to eliminate constitutive rules avant la lettre. He regards status terms as meaningless.

  12. 12.

    In a similar vein, Copp (2020) observes that reduction is not elimination.

  13. 13.

    Elsewhere, Tuomela elaborates on this as follows: “Given this, we can say that there is a constitutive norm “E counts as the ethos of g” (e.g. E could express the norm that g be democratic). This norm is a constitutive, conceptually necessary ought-to-be norm for g: Things ought to be so that the ethos E be upheld and promoted in g by the members through their related activities, and accordingly there will be relevant regulative norms specifying what kinds of democratic activities are normatively expected from the members of g.” (2017, pp. 215–216)

  14. 14.

    Tuomela (2017, p. 216) goes on to claim that Searle makes the same point. However, Searle’s account does not feature higher-order rules or ought-to-be norms. Instead, his point is that we start with imperatives and end with deontic powers, as I discussed earlier in this section.

  15. 15.

    Garcia (1987) defends the somewhat similar idea that constitutive rules come with classificatory obligations. The idea is that people ought to classify, for instance, dollar bills as such and that they ought to correct others who misclassify them. However, if there are such obligations, they are generic linguistic obligations that are not specific to status terms.

  16. 16.

    Tuomela also claims that constitutive rules or norms constitute and create “groups capable of acting as groups” (2017, p. 216) But in what sense? Earlier, Tuomela (2013) had argued that group agents are both causally efficacious and fictitious. As these claims are difficult to square, I pressed him on this (Hindriks 2015, 2017). In response, he has admitted that they are only ‘loosely fictitious’, the point being that their intentional attitudes are extrinsic instead of intrinsic (Tuomela 2017, p. 215). (The claim that they are fictitious no longer appears in the paperback edition of Social Ontology.) This leaves me with the question of why, as Tuomela claims, regulative rules cannot do the ‘job’ of constituting group agents (2017, p. 216). Perhaps this is because, on his view, constitutive rules are ought-to-be rules.

  17. 17.

    What is more, I regard entities that have statuses as irreducibly institutional. As I have argued elsewhere, they are materially constituted by entities at a lower level (Hindriks 2012, 2013).

  18. 18.

    This is due to the fact that concepts involve dispositions to draw certain inferences (Peacocke 1992). However, someone might have an imperfect understanding of a status concept and lack a full grasp of the deontic powers that are involved. This is particularly likely when status terms have a legal meaning, which can be quite technical. Even then, however, status terms and concepts can be useful as placeholders. Participants will have some sense of what they are all about and can consult experts if need be.

  19. 19.

    Base properties and status indicators can also be captured by (the antecedents of) regulative rules. However, if they are sufficiently complex, it is more convenient to specify them in separate base rules.

  20. 20.

    An important disagreement between us concerns what it takes for a norm to govern a practice. According to Tuomela, this requires that the participants are collectively committed to the norm. I allow for a wider range of motivations, including for instance peer pressure. Importantly, their motivation can be low and need not induce compliance (Hindriks 2019, 2021).

References

  • Belnap, N. 1993. On Rigorous Definitions. Philosophical Studies 72 (2–3): 115–146.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Copp, D. 2020. Collective Obligations and the Point of Morality. In Routledge Handbook of Collective Responsibility, 93–112. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elias, N. 1969. The Civilizing Process. Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garcia, J.L.A. 1987. Constitutive Rules. Philosophia 17 (3): 251–270.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guala, F., and F. Hindriks. 2015. A Unified Social Ontology. The Philosophical Quarterly 65 (259): 177–201.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hart, H.L.A. 1961. The Concept of Law. Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hindriks, F. 2005. Rules and Institutions: Essays in Meaning, Speech Acts and Social Ontology. Erasmus University Rotterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2009. Constitutive Rules, Language, and Ontology. Erkenntnis 71 (2): 253–275.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2012. But Where Is the University? Dialectica 66 (1): 93–113.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013. The Location Problem in Social Ontology. Synthese 190 (3): 413–437.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2015. Social Ontology: Collective Intentionality and Group Agents, Raimo Tuomela. Oxford University Press, 2013, xiv + 310 pages. Economics and Philosophy 31(2): 341–348.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2017. Group Agents and Social Institutions. In Social Ontology and Collective Intentionality: Critical Essays on the Philosophy of Raimo Tuomela with his Responses, ed. G. Preyer and G. Peter, 197–210. Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2019. Norms that Make a Difference: Social Practices and Institutions. Analyse & Kritik 41 (1): 125–146.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2021. Rules, Equilibria and Virtual Control: How to Explain Persistence, Resilience and Fragility. Erkenntnis: 1–23. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-021-00406-9.

  • Hindriks, F., and F. Guala. 2015. Institutions, Rules, and Equilibria: A Unified Theory. Journal of Institutional Economics 11 (3): 459–480.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D.K. 1983. Philosophical Papers Vol 1. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A. 1981. After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory. University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke, C. 1992. A Study of Concepts. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ransdell, J. 1971. Constitutive Rules and Speech-Act Analysis. The Journal of Philosophy 68 (13): 385. https://doi.org/10.2307/2025037.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. 1955. Two Concepts of Rules. The Philosophical Review 64 (1): 3–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. 1986. The Morality of Freedom. Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross, A. 1957. Tu-tu. Harvard Law Review 5: 812–825.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J.R. 1969. Speech Acts. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1995. The Construction of Social Reality. The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2010. Making the Social World: The Structure of Human Civilization. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2015. Status Functions and Institutional Facts: Reply to Hindriks and Guala. Journal of Institutional Economics 11 (3): 507–514.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tuomela, R. 1995. The Importance of Us. Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2002. The Philosophy of Social Practices: A Collective Acceptance View. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2003. Collective Acceptance, Social Institutions, and Social Reality. American Journal of Economics and Sociology 62 (1): 123–165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013. Social Ontology: Collective Intentionality and Group Agents. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2017. Response to Frank Hindriks. In Social Ontology and Collective Intentionality: Critical Essays on the Philosophy of Raimo Tuomela with His Responses, ed. G. Preyer and G. Peter, 211–217. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2020. Institutions in Action, The Nature and the Role of Institutions in the Real World. In Institutions in Action: The Nature and the Role of Institutions in the Real World, ed. Tiziana Andina and Petar Bojanić, 1–8. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Warnock, G.J. 1971. The Object of Morality. Lethuen.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am very grateful to Francesco Guala, Arto Laitinen and Maj Tuomela, as well as the editors of this volume, for their comments on this chapter.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Frank Hindriks .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Appendix: Tuomela on the Transformation View

Appendix: Tuomela on the Transformation View

Tuomela presented part of his criticism of the Transformation View in an unpublished comment that was intended to be included as an appendix to his paper ‘Social Corporations as Social Institutions’ (Tuomela 2020). I thank his wife, Maj Tuomela, for her kind permission to present it here in full.

1.1 Constitutive Rules Are Not Reducible to Regulative Ones

Hindriks and Guala (2015), pp. 472–474, claim that constitutive rules are conservative (viz. non-creative) and a kind of eliminable transformations of regulative rules. But this contradicts at least my account because a constitutive rule in my account is an irreducible higher-order normative presupposition (a group-level ought-to-be rule, cf. Searle 2015). It says what the Y-term in the Searlean formula “X counts as Y in context C” is and also that X constitutes it. The constitutive rule is relatively stable in contrast to a regulative rule that primarily says how Y functions in an institutional context S.

The constitutive rule, C, in the Hindriks-Guala (H-G) paper (p. 472) says that if a person is the first to occupy a piece of land, it is his property, and that he hence has the right to use it. This can be seen as a general constitutive and defining feature of property. In these authors’ view the regulative rule (R) involved here is a conjunction saying in effect that if one is the first to occupy a piece of land then, in a quasi-Lockean sense, it is his property (corresponding to Y in Searlean constitutive norms); and if this is the case the resulting rule is claimed by the authors to entail that he has the right to use the piece of land (see Searle 2015, for criticism of this point). But R does not say how the institution of property can be used, so to speak, which is what a regulative rule should do at least according to my account. However, as will be shown below, in the H-G account C and R on the basis of their sameness of form have basically the same content. This implies that neither one is logically or conceptually primary, lacking a difference in the sense that I have claimed above concerning constitutive and regulative rules.

I will below state the H-G regulative rule R in the abbreviated form “If Occ, then Right” (p. 472). Fully formulated we have this: “If Occ, then Prop, and hence Right”. The rule C has the form “If Occ, then Prop and if Prop, then Right”. The two conjuncts jointly entail “If Occ, then Right”, i.e. the rule R. R and C thus are equivalent in relation to their consequences and in this sense have the same content in these authors’ account, given the assumptions made above. (What the authors regard as a theoretical term, viz. here ‘property’—corresponding to the “theoretical” term Y in the Searlean formula “If X then Y in C”—does not get eliminated by non-theoretical terms; see Guala and Hindriks (2015) and below for this.)

The central critical point against the H-G account as viewed from the point of view of my approach should be laid bare: the authors have in my view incorrectly mixed constitutive rules with regulative ones in their form-based treatment of the rules in question. However, at least in my account form need not distinguish them but rather their different functions. A constitutive rule should primarily say what something X is constituted as, while the regulative rule says how the constituted item or fact is supposed to be used or to function. Rules such as C and R qua, respectively, constitutive and regulative ones, are generally supposed to answer different questions and have different contents, which, however, the authors’ above simple logical formalism does not tell us but rather regards as equivalent. These authors’ rule C is indeed a constitutive one but their regulative rule R is also constitutive as to its form because having the right involves a right-involving status function entailing deontic power. Yet rule R does not show how to concretely use the institution of property as it should qua being a regulative rule. It can be concluded that the Hindriks-Guala proof does not succeed in eliminating constitutive rules in favor of regulative ones. What has above been said about the case of property applies mutatis mutandis to the institutions of money and marriage, etc.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2023 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Hindriks, F. (2023). Can There Be Institutions Without Constitutive Rules?. In: Garcia-Godinez, M., Mellin, R. (eds) Tuomela on Sociality. Philosophers in Depth. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-22626-7_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics