Skip to main content

On Krifka’s “Nominal Reference, TemporalConstitutionandQuantification in Event Semantics”

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
A Reader's Guide to Classic Papers in Formal Semantics

Part of the book series: Studies in Linguistics and Philosophy ((SLAP,volume 100))

  • 556 Accesses

Abstract

Krifka, in his paper “Nominal reference, temporal constitution and quantification in event semantics”, provides the first formal mereological (algebraic) analysis of the relation between nominal reference and temporal constitution (also based on his 1986 PhD thesis). The focus is on two manifestations of this relation in the grammar of natural languages. First, as many observed, there are direct structural analogies between the following two sets of distinction: namely, mass/count and atelic/telic. They are clearly reflected in their parallel cooccurrence patterns with quantifiers, numerical and measure expressions. Second, nominal reference and temporal constitution interact and mutually constraint each other in the derivation of meaning of complex verbal predicates. One key example is aspectual composition(ality) e.g., eat soup (atelic) versus eat two apples (telic). In order to provide an adequate analysis of the relevant data Krifka’s principal innovation is to assume a single join semi-lattice structure, undetermined with respect to atomicity, relative to which he defines two higher-order, cross-categorial predicates for reference types of natural language predicates: namely, quantized and cumulative. Specifically in the case of aspectual composition, the interactions and mutual constraints between the structure of objects and eventualities stem from the systematic mappings (homomorphisms) whose source is the lexical semantics of verbs. Such mappings are also independently motivated by other phenomena exhibiting systematic interactions objects and eventualities.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The term ‘temporal constitution’is a translation of the German ‘Zeitkonstitution’, coined by François (Francois, 1985).

  2. 2.

    The use “count nouns (or NPs)” and “mass nouns (or NPs)” here reflects the fact that there is no general agreement concerning the level of linguistic description on which these categories are grammatically relevant. Starting with Verkuyl (1971, 1972) at least, there have been debates whether the telic/atelic distinction, and subsequently also the mass/count distinction (Pelletier & Schubert, 2002), are distinctions that are relevant at the level of lexical items at all, and whether they should instead be viewed as distinctions at the level of phrasal constructions, as constructional properties of NPs, VPs and sentences.

  3. 3.

    For Krifka (1989, 1998), these two sets of distinctions are taken to be semantic properties of nominal and verbal predicates, rather than being inherent in entities in the domain, in the external world. There are debates and numerous misunderstandings concerning the status of these categories. The key question is whether these are ontological categories (Bach, 1986; Parsons, 1990, i.a.) or whether these are categories that are properties of verbal and nominal predicates (Krifka, 1986, 1989; Filip Filip, 1993a, b; Partee, 1999, i.a.) (See Filip, 2011, 2012 for summaries of these debates.)

  4. 4.

    There is a long-standing tradition of observations related to aspectual composition(ality), which can be traced to the nineteenth century philology (e.g., Streitberg, 1891). Some notable precursors are Poutsma (1926) and Jacobsohn (1933) (cited by Verkuyl, 1971, 1972, also 2005 and elsewhere, who credits them as the major sources of inspiration for his theory of aspectual compositionality), Garey (1957) (inspiration for Filip, 1985 and Krifka, 1986) and Leech (1969, p.137) who speaks of ‘semantic concord’ between nominal arguments and complex verbal predicates.

  5. 5.

    The interpretations that are relevant for this test concern the temporal extent of singular eventualities denoted by predicates in the scope of these temporal modifiers. The interpretations that are irrelevant are iterative and generic interpretations. Moreover, for time-span modifiers, we need disregard the shifted inchoative interpretation of atelic predicates under which the time-span modifier denotes the measure of time until the onset of denoted eventualities from ‘now’ or some other reference point (see also Vendler, 1957, p. 147) (e.g., The children ran in an hour understood as meaning they started running after an hour from some understood reference point), and for durative modifiers, the irrelevant interpretations regard the duration of the result state that follows the set terminal point in the denotation of telic verbal expressions (e.g., John put the wine into the fridge for half an hour).

  6. 6.

    This, among others, obviates the minimal part problem posed by the putative divisive reference of mass nouns and process-denoting (atelic) predicates (Taylor, 1977; Bach, 1981, i.a.), and also unintuitive results such that there is a sharp sortal difference between what walk (atelic, non-atomic domain) and walk a mile (telic, atomic domain) describe, even though it arguably is the same eventuality in the world under two different descriptions (Krifka, 2001).

  7. 7.

    In compliance with later developments in event semantics, here the term ‘eventuality’ (coined by Bach, 1981) is used instead of ‘event’, given that ‘event’ is now restricted to mean an entity in the denotation of telic (accomplishment, and also achievement, according to some at least) predicates, and given that by ‘events’ Krifka (1989) intends to cover the domain from which both telic and atelic predicates draw their denotation.

  8. 8.

    Krifka (1989) uses S, rather than O, for the relevant predicate variable.

  9. 9.

    For a formal definition of an extensive measure function see Champollion and Krifka, 2016, §13.21.

  10. 10.

    Schwarzschild (2002, 2006) relies on a closely related property of monotonocity in his analyses of closely related phenomena.

  11. 11.

    Measure phrases, such as five meters, are of type [N/N] and analyzed by means of the number (n) expressed by the numerical word (five) and a measure function (μ), expressed by some measure word (meter). Syntactically speaking, numericals (five) belong to a basic category NM (numerical number), and consequently measure words (meter) have the category [N/N, NM] (see (4), Krifka (1989, p.83).

  12. 12.

    Krifka (1989) analyzes extensive measure phrases (such as five ounces(of)) as ‘quantizing modifiers’ that derive quantized predicates from non-quantized ones, namely, denoted by mass terms (beer, gold) and plural terms (apples): ∀P∀P[qmodo(P,P) ↔ ¬qua(P) ∧ qua(P(P))] (Krifka, 1989, D28, p.82). In later works, he specifies the input of measure phrases in terms of the property of cumulative reference.

  13. 13.

    This is reminiscent of Strawson’s (1959) view that the possibilities for identifying eventualities without reference to objects are limited, because eventualities fail to provide “a single, comprehensive and continuously usable framework” of reference of the kind provided by physical objects (Strawson, 1959, p. 46ff.).

  14. 14.

    “An hour full of running is naturally assumed to be without gaps, like a bathtub full of water. A year full of winning (iterative) has got to have gaps, like a street full of policemen” (Vlach, 1981, p. 282, fn. 17).

  15. 15.

    As Krifka (1998, and elsewhere) also observes, similar notions and relations mediating between participants and eventualities were proposed by others: e.g., [+ADD-TO] V property (Verkuyl, 1972, 1993), ‘measuring out’ tied to the internal direct object DP (Tenny, 1987, 1994), ‘structure-preserving binding relations’ (Jackendoff, 1996).

  16. 16.

    Dowty’s (1987, 1989, 1991) treatment of Incremental Theme as one of the lexical determinants of argument selection is not entirely uncontroversial. For instance, Jackendoff (1996), Rappaport Hovav and Levin (2002, 2005, pp. 284–285) argue that Incremental Theme is not a factor in argument selection, while agreeing that the intuition behind it, which concerns structure-preserving mappings between eventualities and some suitable objects, plays an important role in a variety of aspectual phenomena.

  17. 17.

    Related observations were also made by L. Carlson (1981), Mittwoch (1988), Dahl (1991) and Moltmann (1991).

  18. 18.

    Borer (2005) argues that a telic interpretation must be licensed by a quantity DP, with a definite DP being one subtype, including definite mass nouns and definite plurals.

  19. 19.

    This idea is inspired by the Localist Theory (Gruber, 1965), which inspired the framework of Conceptual Semantics of Jackendoff (1991, 1996).

  20. 20.

    Kagan (2013) applies this idea to a full-fledged scalar approach to the semantics of Russian prefixes.

  21. 21.

    The line between incremental and non-incremental verbs is not always easy to draw, given that nearly all episodic verbs may be interpreted as incremental in a suitable context, cp. ‘latent incremental theme verbs’ (Rappaport Hovav & Levin, 2005).

Bibliography

  • Allen, R. L. (1966). The verb system of present-day American English. Mouton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bach, E. (1981). On time, tense and aspect: An essay in English metaphysics. In R. Pragmatics (Ed.), Peter Cole (pp. 63–81). Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bach, E. (1986). The algebra of events. Linguistics and Philosophy, 9, 5–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bach, E., Jelinek, E., Kratzer, A., & Partee, B. (Eds.). (1995). Quantification in natural languages. Studies in linguistics and philosophy, 54. Kluwer Academic Publishers Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bale, A., & Coon, J. (2014). Classifiers are for numerals, not for nouns: Consequences for the mass/count distinction. Linguistic Inquiry, 45(4), 695–707.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beavers, J. (2008). Scalar complexity and the structure of events. In J. Dölling, T. Heyde-Zybatow, & M. Schäfer (Eds.), Event structures in linguistic form and interpretation (pp. 245–268). Mouton de Gruyter.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Beavers, J. (2013). Aspectual classes and scales of change. Linguistics, 54(special issue), 681–706.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bolinger, D. (1975). Aspects of language. Harcourt and Brace.

    Google Scholar 

  • Borer, H. (2005). Structuring sense, Volume I: In name only (Vol. 1) and Volume II: The normal course of events (Vol. 2). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carlson, L. (1981). Aspect and quantification in tense and aspect. In P. Tedeschi & A. Zaenen (Eds.), Syntax and semantics, 14 (pp. 31–64). Ann Arbor.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, H. (1975). Amounts and measures of amount. Noûs, 9, 143–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Champollion, L., & Krifka, M. (2016). Mereology. In M. Aloni (Ed.), The Cambridge handbook of semantics (pp. 513–541). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chierchia, G. (1998). Plurality of mass nouns and the notion of “semantic parameter”. In S. Rothstein (Ed.), Events and grammar (Studies in linguistics and philosophy) (Vol. 7, pp. 53–103). Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Chierchia, G. (2010). Mass nouns, vagueness and semantic variation. Synthese, 174, 99–149.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chierchia, G. (2015). How universal is the mass/count distinction? Three grammars of counting. In A. Li, A. Simpson, & W.-T. D. Tsai (Eds.), Chinese syntax in a cross-linguistic perspective (pp. 147–175). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1970). Remarks on nominalization. In R. A. Jacobs & P. S. Rosenbaum (Eds.), Readings in English transformational grammar (pp. 184–221). Ginn.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1975). Reflections on language. Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1981). Lectures on government and binding. Foris Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dahl, Ö. (1991). Review: Manfred Krifka, Nominalreferenz und Zeitkonstitution: Zur Semantik von Massentermen, Pluraltermen und Aspektklassen. Language, 67, 813–816.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1967). The logical form of action sentences. In N. Rescher (Ed.), The logic of decision and action (pp. 81–95). Pittsburgh University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1969). The individuation of events. In Essays in honor of Carl G. Hempel (pp. 216–234). Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Declerck, R. (1979). Aspect and the bounded/unbounded (telic/atelic) distinction. Linguistics and Philosophy, 17, 761–794.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dowty, D. R. (1979). Word meaning and Montague grammar. Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dowty, D. R. (1988). “Thematic Proto-Roles, Subject Selection, and Lexical Semantic Defaults”, ms. (Paper presented at the 1987 LSA Colloquium. San Francisco).

    Google Scholar 

  • Dowty, D. R. (1989). On the semantic content of the notion ‘thematic role‘. In B. H. Partee, G. Chierchia, & R. Turner (Eds.), Properties, types, and meanings, vol. II (pp. 69–130). Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Dowty, D. R. (1991). Thematic proto-roles and argument selection. Language, 67, 547–619.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Farkas, D. F., & de Swart, H. (2010). The semantics of incorporation. CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Filip, H. (1985). Der Verbalaspekt und die Aktionsarten dargelegt am Beispiel des Tschechischen. Master’s thesis, Universität München.

    Google Scholar 

  • Filip, H. (1989). Aspectual properties of the AN-construction in German. In W. Abraham & T. Janssen (Eds.), Tempus - Aspekt - Modus. Die lexikalischen und grammatischen Formen in den germanischen Sprachen (‘Tense - Aspect - Mood. Lexical and Grammatical Forms in the Germanic Languages’) (pp. 259–292). Linguistische Arbeiten, Band 237). Max Niemeyer Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Filip, H. (1990). Thematic roles and aspect. In B. Birch, K. Hunt, & V. Samiian (Eds.), Proceedings of the Western conference on linguistics (WECOL) 20 (pp. 88–99). California State University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Filip, H. (1992). Aspect and interpretation of nominal arguments. In C. P. Canakis, G. P. Chan, & J. M. Denton (Eds.), Proceedings of the Chicago linguistic society (CLS) 28 (pp. 139–158). The University of Chicago.

    Google Scholar 

  • Filip, H. (1993a). Aspect, situation types and noun phrase semantics. Ph.D. thesis, University of California at Berkeley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Filip, H. (1993b). Verbal aspect and object case marking: A comparison between Czech and Finnish. In J. A. Nevis & V. Samiian (Eds.), Proceedings of the Western conference on linguistics (WECOL) 22 (pp. 43–59). California State University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Filip, H. (1996). Quantification, aspect and lexicon. In G.-J. M. Kruijff, G. Morrill, & D. Oehrle (Eds.), Proceedings of the ESSLLI’96 conference on formal grammar (pp. 43–56). Charles University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Filip, H. (1997). Integrating telicity, aspect and NP semantics: The role of thematic structure. In J. Toman (Ed.), Formal approaches to Slavic linguistics (FASL) III. The College Park meeting 1994 (pp. 61–96). Ann Arbor Michigan Slavic Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Filip, H. (1999). Aspect, eventuality types and noun phrase semantics. Routledge. A revised version of Aspect, situation types and noun phrase semantics. Ph.D. thesis, University of California at Berkeley (1993).

    Google Scholar 

  • Filip, H. (2000). The quantization puzzle. In J. Pustejovsky & C. L. Tenny (Eds.), Events as grammatical objects, from the combined perspectives of lexical semantics, logical semantics and syntax (pp. 39–95). CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Filip, H. (2004). The telicity parameter revisited. In Proceedings of SALT XIV (pp. 92–109). Cornell University/CLC Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Filip, H. (2005a). On accumulating and having it all: Perfectivity, prefixes and bare arguments. In H. Verkuyl, H. de Swart, & A. van Hout (Eds.), Perspectives on aspect. Studies in theoretical psycholinguistics (Vol. 32, pp. 125–148). Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Filip, H. (2005b). In G. N. Carlson & F. J. Pelletier (Eds.), Reference and quantification: The Partee effect. Festschrift for Barbara hall Partee (pp. 229–288). CSLI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Filip, H. (2008). Events and Maximalization: The case of telicity and Perfectivity. In S. Rothstein (Ed.), Theoretical and Crosslinguistic approaches to the semantics of aspect (pp. 217–256). John Benjamins.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Filip, H. (2011). Aspectual class and Aktionsart. In C. Maienborn, K. von Heusinger, & P. Portner (Eds.), Semantics: An international handbook of natural language meaning (pp. 1186–1217). Mouton de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Filip, H. (2012). Lexical Aspect. In R. I. Binnick (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of tense and aspect (pp. 721–751). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Filip, H. (2017). The semantics of perfectivity. In P. M. Bertinetto (Ed.), Special issue of the Italian journal of linguistics. Symposium Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Filip, H., & Rothstein, S. (2005). Telicity as a semantic parameter. In J. Lavine, S. Franks, H. Filip, & M. Tasseva-Kurktchieva (Eds.), Formal approaches to Slavic linguistics (FASL) XIV. The Princeton University meeting (pp. 139–156). University of Michigan Slavic Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Filip, H., & Sutton, P. R. (2017). Singular count NPs in measure constructions. Paper presented at the semantics and linguistic theory 27, University of Maryland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fillmore, Ch. J. (1971). Lectures on Deixis, (Lectures delivered to the 1971 Santa Cruz Linguistics Institute; distributed by the Indiana University Linguistics Club, Bloomington.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Francois, J. (1985). Aktionsart, Aspekt und Zeitkonstitution. In C. Schwarze & D. Wunderlich (Eds.), Handbuch der Lexikologie (pp. 229–249). Kronberg.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gabbay, D. M., & Moravcsik, J. M. E. (1973). Sameness and individuation. Journal of Philosophy, 70, 513–526.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garey, H. B. (1957). Verbal aspects in French. Language, 33, 91–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grimm, S. (2012). Number and individuation. Ph.D. thesis, Stanford University. Stanford, CA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gruber, J. S. (1965). Studies in lexical relations. Ph.D. thesis, Massachusetts Institute of Technology.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hay, J., Kennedy, C., & Levin, B. (1999). Scalar Structure Underlies Telicity in “Degree achievements”. In Proceedings of SALT IX (pp. 127–144). Cornell University/CLC Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackendoff, R. (1991). Parts and boundaries. Cognition, 41(1), 9–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackendoff, R. (1996). The proper treatment of measuring out, telicity, and perhaps even quantification in English. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory, 14(2), 305–354.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jacobsohn, H. (1933). Aspektfragen. Indogermanische Forschungen, 51, 292–318.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, M. (1977). The syntax and semantics of Kikuyu tense and aspect. Ph.D. thesis, Ohio State University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kagan, O. (2013). Scalarity in the domain of verbal prefixes. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory, 31, 483–516.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy, C. (2012). The composition of incremental change. In V. Delmonte & L. McNally (Eds.), Telicity, change, state: A cross-categorical view of event structure (pp. 103–121). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy, C., & Levin, B. (2008). Measure of change: The adjectival core of degree achievements. In L. McNally & C. Kennedy (Eds.), Adjectives and adverbs: Syntax, semantics, discourse (pp. 156–182). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy, C., & McNally, L. (2005). Scale structure and the semantic typology of gradable predicates. Language, 81, 345–381.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kiparsky, P. (1998). Partitive case and aspect. In M. Butt & W. Geuder (Eds.), Projecting from the lexicon (pp. 265–307). CSLI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kratzer, A. (2004). Telicity and the meaning of objective case. In J. Guéron & J. Lecarme (Eds.), The syntax of time (pp. 398–424). The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krifka, M. (1986). Nominalreferenz und Zeitkonstitution. Zur Semantik von Massentermen, Individualtermen, Aspektklassen. Ph.D. thesis, Universität München, Germany.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krifka, M. (1989). Nominal reference, temporal constitution and quantification in event semantics. In R. Bartsch, J. van Benthem, & P. van Emde Boas (Eds.), Semantics and contextual expressions (pp. 75–115). Foris.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Krifka, M. (1990). Four thousand ships passed through the lock: Object-induced measure functions on events. Linguistics and Philosophy, 13, 487–520.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krifka, M. (1992). Thematic relations as links between nominal reference and temporal constitution. In I. A. Sag & A. Szabolcsi (Eds.), Lexical matters (pp. 29–53). CSLI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krifka, M. (1995). Common nouns: A contrastive analysis of Chinese and English. In G. N. Carlson & F. J. Pelletier (Eds.), The generic book (pp. 398–411). Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krifka, M. (1998). The origins of telicity. In S. Rothstein (Ed.), Events and grammar (pp. 197–235). Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Krifka, M. (2001). The mereological approach to aspectual composition. Paper presented at the Conference “Perspectives on Aspect”, University of Utrecht, The Netherlands.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krifka, M. (2007). Masses and countables: Cognitive and linguistic factors. Paper presented at the CASTL Workshop “The Syntax and Semantics of Measurement”, Tromsø, Norway.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krifka, M., Pelletier, F. J., Carlson, G. N., Ter Meulen, A., Chierchia, G., & Link, G. (1995). Genericity: An introduction. In G. N. Carlson & F. J. Pelletier (Eds.), The generic book (pp. 1–124). University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Landman, F. (2011). Count nouns – Mass nouns – Neat nouns – Mess nouns. In M. Glanzberg, B. H. Partee, & J. Šķilters (Eds.), Formal semantics and Pragmatics: Discourse,Context and models. The Baltic international yearbook of cognition, logic and communication 6. New Prairie Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Landman, F. (2016). Iceberg semantics for count nouns and mass nouns: The evidence from portions. The Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition Logic and Communication, 11, 1–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lasersohn, P. (1995). Plurality, conjunction and events. Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Leech, G. N. (1969). The new English grammar: A descriptive introduction. M.I.T. Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leisi, E. (1953). Der Wortinhalt. Seine Struktur im Deutschen und Englischen. Quelle und Mayer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levin, B., & Rappaport Hovav, M. (2005). Argument realization. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Link, G. (1983). The logical analysis of plurals and mass terms: A lattice-theoretical approach. In R. Bäuerle, C. Schwarze, & A. von Stechow (Eds.), Meaning, use, and interpretation of language (pp. 302–323). De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Link, G. (1987). Algebraic semantics of event structures. In J. A. G. Groenendijk, M. Stokhof, & A. von Stechow (Eds.), Proceedings of the sixth Amsterdam colloquium (pp. 243–272). ILLC.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lønning, J. T. (1987). Mass terms and quantification. Linguistics and Philosophy, 10, 1–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mittwoch, A. (1988). Aspects of English aspect: On the interaction of perfect, progressive, and durational phrases. Linguistics and Philosophy, 11, 203–254.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moltmann, F. (1991). Measure adverbials. Linguistics and Philosophy, 14(6), 629–660.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mourelatos, A. P. D. (1978/1981). Events, processes and states. Linguistics and Philosophy, 2, 415–434. Reprinted 1981 in Tedeschi, P., & Zaenen, A. (Eds.), Syntax and semantics 1914: Tense and aspect (pp. 1191–1212). Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parsons, T. (1990). Events in the semantics of English: A study in subatomic semantics. The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Partee, B. H. (1995). “Quantificational Structures and Compositionality.” Bach, E. et al. (1995). 541–601.

    Google Scholar 

  • Partee, B. H. (1999). Nominal and temporal semantic structure: Aspect and quantification. In E. Hajičová, T. Hoskovec, O. Leška, & P. Sgall (Eds.), Prague Linguistic Circle Papers (Vol. 3, pp. 91–108).

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Pelletier, J. F., & Schubert, L. K. (2002). Mass expressions. In D. Gabbay & F. Guenthner (Eds.), Handbook of philosophical logic, 10 (pp. 1–87). Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piñón, C. (2008). Aspectual composition with degrees. In L. McNally & C. Kennedy (Eds.), Adjectives and adverbs in semantics and discourse (pp. 183–219). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Platzack, C. (1979). The semantic interpretation of aspect and Aktionsarten: A study of internal time reference in Swedish. Foris Publications.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Poutsma, H. P. (1926). A grammar of late modern English, part II. Nordhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rappaport Hovav, M. (2008). Lexicalized meaning and the internal temporal structure of events. In S. Rothstein (Ed.), Theoretical and crosslinguistic approaches to the semantics of aspect (pp. 13–42). John Benjamins.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rappaport Hovav, M., & Levin, B. (2002). Change of state verbs: Implications for theories of argument projection. Proceedings of the 28th Annual Meeting of the Berkeley Linguistics Society, 28, 269–280.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rothstein, S. (2004). Structuring events: A study in the semantics of lexical aspect. Wiley-Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rothstein, S. (2010). Counting and the mass/count distinction. Journal of Semantics, 27(3), 343–397.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rothstein, S. (2011). Counting, measuring and the semantics of classifiers. The Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication, 6, 1–41.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rothstein, S. (2017). Semantics for counting and measuring. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sauerland, U. (2003). A new semantics for number. In R. B. Young & Y. Zhou (Eds.), Proceedings of SALT XIII (pp. 258–275). Cornell University/CLC Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sauerland, U., Anderssen, J., & Yatsushiro, K. (2005). The plural is semantically unmarked. In S. Kepser & M. Reis (Eds.), Linguistic evidence. Empirical, theoretical and computational perspectives (pp. 413–434). De Gruyter Mouton.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Schoorlemmer, M. (1995). Participial passive and aspect in Russian. Utrecht University. OTS dissertation series.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwarzschild, R. (2002). The grammar of measurement. In B. Jackson (Ed.), Proceedings of SALT XII (pp. 225–245). Cornell University/CLC Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwarzschild, R. (2006). The role of dimensions in the syntax of noun phrases. Syntax, 9(1), 67–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, C. S. (1991/1997). The parameter of aspect. Kluwer. Reprinted in Carlota S. Smith (Ed.) (1997). The parameter of aspect (2nd Ed., pp. 227–261). Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P. F. (1959). Individuals. An essay in descriptive metaphysics. Methuen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Streitberg, W. (1891). Perfective und imperfective Actionsart im Germanischen. Beiträge zur Geschichte der deutschen Sprache und Literatur, 15, 7–177.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sudo, Y. (2017). Countable nouns in japanese. Proceedings of WAFL, 11, 1–11.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppes, P., & Zinnes, J. L. (1963). Basic measurement theory. In D. R. Luce & e.a. (Eds.), Handbook of mathematical psychology (Vol. 1, pp. 2–76). Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sutton, P. R., & Filip, H. (2016). Mass/count variation: A Mereological, two-dimensional semantics. In S. Rothstein & J. Šķilters (Eds.), Baltic international yearbook of cognition, logic, and communication 11. New Prarie Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sutton, P. R., & Filip, H. (2021). The count/mass distinction for granular nouns. In H. Filip (Ed.), Countability in the nominal and verbal domain. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Talmy, L. (1985). Lexicalization patterns: Semantic structure in lexical forms. In T. Shopen (Ed.), Language typology and syntactic description: Grammatical categories and the lexicon (Vol. 3, pp. 57–149). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, B. (1977). Tense and continuity. Linguistics and Philosophy, 1, 199–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tenny, C. (1987). Grammaticalizing aspect and affectedness. Ph.D. thesis, MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tenny, C. (1992). The aspectual Interface hypothesis. In I. Sag & A. Szabolsci (Eds.), Lexical matters (pp. 1–27). Center for the Study of Language and Information.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tenny, C. (1994). Aspectual roles and the syntax-semantics interface. Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tenny, C., & Pustejovsky, J. (2000). A history of events in linguistic theory. In C. L. Tenny & J. Pustejovsky (Eds.), Events as grammatical objects, from the combined perspectives of lexical semantics, logical semantics and syntax (pp. 3–37). CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Orman Quine, W. (1960). Word and object. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vendler, Z. (1957). Verbs and times. Philosophical Review, 56, 143–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Verkuyl, H. J. (1971). On the compositional nature of the aspects. Ph.D. thesis, University of Utrecht.

    Google Scholar 

  • Verkuyl, H. J. (1972). On the compositional nature of the aspects. Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Verkuyl, H. J. (1993). A theory of aspectuality. The interaction between temporal and Atemporal structure. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Verkuyl, H. J. (1999). Aspectual issues. Structuring time and quantity (CSLI Lecture Notes) (Vol. 98). CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Verkuyl, H. J. (2005). Aspectual composition: surveying the ingredients. In H. J. Verkuyl & H. de Swart (Eds.), Perspectives on aspect. Studies in theoretical psycholinguistics (pp. 19–39). Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vlach, F. (1981). The semantics of the progressive. In P. J. Tedeschi & A. Zaenan (Eds.), Syntax and semantics 14: Tense and aspect (pp. 271–291). Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wierzbicka, A. (1967). On the semantics of verbal aspect in polish. In To honor Roman Jakobson. Volume 3 (pp. 2231–2249). Mouton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yatsushiro, K., Sauerland, U., & Alexiadou, A. (2017). The unmarkedness of plural: Crosslinguistic data. In M. LaMendola & J. Scott (Eds.), BUCLD 41: Proceedings of the 41st annual Boston University conference on language development (pp. 753–765). Cascadilla.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zucchi, A., & White, M. (1996). Twigs, sequences, and the temporal constitution of predicates. In Semantics and linguistic theory (SALT) VI (pp. 329–346). CLC Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zucchi, A., & White, M. (2001). Twigs, sequences, and the temporal constitution of predicates. Linguistics and Philosophy, 24, 223–270.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Appendix

Appendix

(1)

Temporal trace function τ: E → T

Krifka (1989), p. 97 (D 40)

 

∀e∀e’[τ(e ∪E e’) = τ(e) ∪T τ(e’)]

 
 

The run time of the sum of two events e and e’ is the sum of the run time of e and the run time of e’.

(2)

Locative trace function: π: E → L

Lasersohn (1995), Krifka (1998)

 

∀e∀e’[π(e ∪Ee’) = π(e) ∪L π(e’)]

 

The path trace of the sum of two events e and e’ is the sum of the path trace of e and the path trace of e’.

 

Example: [[walk two miles]] = λx,e[walk(x,e) ∧ agent(e,x) ∧

 

mile(π(e)) = 2]

 

A set of sums of walking eventualities, each to the amount of two miles

(3)

a derived measure function μ’. Intuitively, it describes the transfer of a measure function from one domain to another, on the assumption that there is a homomorphism h from one domain to the other, i.e., a function that preserves some structural relation defined on its domain in a similar relation defined on the range (Krifka, 1989, p.80). For example, a measure function μ for times like hour, week or year can be used as a derived measure function μ’ on temporal traces of eventualities:

 

(a) ∀e[μ’(e) = μ(τ(e))] Krifka (1989), p. 97 (D41)

 

 where τ(e) = t, the temporal trace of e

 

(b) hour’(e) = hour(τ(e))

 

(c) ⟦sing for an hour⟧ = λx,e[sing(e) ∧ agent(e,x) ∧ hour’(e) = 1]

(4)

Two-place predicates that capture the structure-preserving ‘transfer’ properties of thematic relations that mediate between objects and eventualities (Krifka, 1998, D 29-D 33, p. 92, and 2001)

 

 • Summativity (cumulativity)

 

 ∀R[sum(R) ↔∀e,e’,x,x’ [R(e,x) ∧ R(e’,x’) → R(e∪Ee’, x∪Ox’)]]

 

 A general condition for the relation between thematic relations and the join operations. For example, two events of drinking a glass of wine yield an event of drinking two glasses of wine (Krifka, 1989, D29, p.92).

 

 • Uniqueness for Objects

 

 ∀R[uni-o(R) ↔∀e,x,x’[R(e,x) ∧ R(e,x’) → x = x’]]

 

 There canbenotwo distinctobjectswhichbearthethematicrelationR to the same event (Krifka, 1989, D30).

 

 • Uniqueness for Eventualities

 

 ∀R[uni-e(R) ↔ ∀e,e’,x[R(e,x) ∧ R(e’,x) → e = e’]]

 

 There can be no two distinct events which bear R to the same object, that is, an event is related to a specific object. E.g., adrinking of aglass of wine is rela -ted only to this glass of wine as a theme/patient and to nothing else (Krifka, 1989, D31).

 

 (o.k.: eat, write; not o.k.: read, see, push, ride)

 

 • Mapping to Subobjects

 

 ∀R[map-o(R) ↔∀e,e’,x [R(e,x) ∧ e’ ⊂ Ee → ∃ x’[x’ ⊂ Ox ∧ R(e’,x’)]]

 

 If an event bears R to anobject,anysubpart of the event bears R to some subpart of the object. E.g. every proper subpart of anevent eof drinking aglass of wine corresponds to a proper subpart of the glass of wine (Krifka, 1989, D32).

 

 (o.k.: eat, write; not o.k.: read, see, push, ride)

 

 • Mapping to Subeventualities

 

 ∀R[map-e(R) ↔∀e,x,x’[R(e,x) ∧ x’ ⊂ Ox → ∃e’[e’ ⊂ Ee ∧ R(e’,x’)]].

 

 If an event bears R to an object, any subpart of the object bears R to some subpart of the event (Krifka, 1989, D32).

 

 (o.k.: eat, write, read; not o.k.: see, push, ride)

(5)

Classification of thematic relations (Krifka, 1989, p. 96 (14), 1998, 2001)

Example

sum

uni-o

map-e

map-o

uni-e

 

eat an apple, write a letter

+

+

+

+

+

Strictly Incremental Theme

read a book

+

+

+

Incremental Theme

push a cart,see a movie

+

+

Theme/Stimulus

(6)

a.

Strictly Incremental Theme:

∀R[sinc(R) ↔ uni-o(R) ∧ map-o(R) ∧ map-e(R) ∧ uni-e(R)]

 

b.

Incremental Theme:

∀R[inc(R) ↔ uni-o(R) ∧ map-o(R) ∧ map-e(R)]

(7)

Maximal Participant:

 

∀x[max(P, x) ↔ P(x) ∧ ¬∃y[P(y) ∧ x < y]] Zucchi and White (1996, 2001)

 

An individual is a maximal P iff it is P and it is not a proper part of another P.

(8)

write a sequence ⟧ = λyλe∃x[write’(e) ∧ ag(y, e) ∧ pat (x, e) ∧

 

max (λz∃e’[write’(e’) ∧ ag(y, e’) ∧ pat(z, e’) ∧ sequence’(z) ∧ τ(e’) ≤ tR], x)]

 

Zucchi and White (2001), p. 261)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Filip, H. (2022). On Krifka’s “Nominal Reference, TemporalConstitutionandQuantification in Event Semantics”. In: McNally, L., Szabó, Z.G. (eds) A Reader's Guide to Classic Papers in Formal Semantics. Studies in Linguistics and Philosophy, vol 100. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-85308-2_14

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics