Skip to main content

On Ernest Nagel on Teleology in Biology

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Ernest Nagel: Philosophy of Science and the Fight for Clarity

Part of the book series: Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science ((LEUS,volume 53))

  • 379 Accesses

Abstract

This chapter revisits Ernest Nagel’s view of teleology in biology. In some of his writings from the 1950s to the 1970s, Nagel contended for the legitimacy of teleology in biology but argued against its uniqueness. In addition, Nagel also offered a goal-contribution account in the biological function debate which emerged in the 1960s and the 1970s. While questions of legitimacy and uniqueness of teleology draw little attention today, the biological function debate remains in focus in philosophy of biology. Although the ongoing debate does mention Nagel’s name occasionally, his view, often merely understood as the goal-contribution account, is treated as outdated. However, this treatment is limited, because it fails to consider Nagel’s another important thesis, that is, eliminativism. In this chapter, I attempt to do three things. First, I articulate Nagel’s view, by showing that the eliminativist Nagel considered it acceptable to eliminate teleological terms in biological discourse, and that he also treated them as anthropomorphic vestiges. Second, I defend Nagel’s view and use it to clarify the current biological function debate, by distinguishing a descriptive dimension of this debate from its prescriptive dimension. Third, I hope to deepen Nagel’s view, by pushing it to a further and perhaps its logical conclusion, that is, Kant’s view of biological teleology.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    In this chapter, phrases like “biological teleology”, “teleology in biology” and “teleological terms, statements and explanations in biological discourse” are used interchangeably. Admittedly, at the start only the third seems the most appropriate, since it is an uncontroversial fact that teleological expressions are widespread in biological discourse. The main difficulty of the other two is that some authors (e.g., Ghiselin 2002), while acknowledging the previous fact, deny the existence of “genuine” teleological phenomena in biological sciences. However, as will be clear in this chapter (Sects. 10.4 and 10.5), this difficulty can be removed by distinguishing non-intentional accounts of teleology from its intentional accounts. If non-intentional accounts are prescribed, it is unproblematic to use phrases such as “biological teleology” and “teleology in biology”. Meanwhile, the same clarification also works for function terms, given the fact that some authors (e.g., Ghiselin 2001) also contend that function terms are not teleological terms. Yet, these authors, while attributing non-intentional accounts to function terms, insist on attributing intentional accounts to teleological terms and dismiss the latter as illegitimate in biological discourse. In this chapter I try to avoid these sometimes-frustrating terminological issues. I consider the possibility of attributing non-intentional accounts to both and prefer to treat function terms as teleological terms. Indeed, on these terminological issues, I am following the clarification approach (“clarifying…meaning and implications”) endorsed by Nagel, rather than the legislation approach (“legislating what sort of things it is permissible or possible for the empirical sciences to investigate”) he opposed (Nagel 1936, p. 6; also see Nagel 1945). The clarification approach is also supported by logical empiricists in general, and runs close to, in my view, the spirit of a Kantian Critique.

  2. 2.

    For instance, Jeffrey McDonough (2020, pp. 151–152) recently shows from historical evidence that “most natural philosophers in the early modern period remained deeply committed to teleology”, and that the persistent impression conveyed in traditional historiography that “teleology was simply undermined by the so-called scientific revolution” (2020, p. 152) should be corrected. However, in my view, while traditional historiography can be disputed in its use of historical materials, it is also essential to understand that it mainly plays an ideological role, in legislating a Whiggish narrative for either the triumph of mechanism (for instance, the success of mechanism started from the scientific revolution) or the return of teleology (like, teleology was banned for a long time, now it is time for its re-emergence). In these cases, the authors care little about the historical accuracy of their narratives. For an example, see Walsh (2008).

  3. 3.

    Again, there is a terminological issue here. Some might object that it is impermissible to place currently popular organizational accounts under the systematic approach, because, first, current organizational accounts (Mossio et al., 2009; Saborido et al., 2011; Saborido, 2014; Mossio & Saborido, 2016), in contrast to earlier ones (McLaughlin 2003; Schlosser 1998), claim to have integrated the virtues of both evolutionary and systematic approaches; second, they are also interpreted as belonging to the etiological approach (Artiga and Martinez 2016). In this chapter, I hope to evade this terminological issue, by following earlier organizational accounts (especially Schlosser, 1998) to explicitly place the under the systematic approach as against the evolutionary approach; current organizational accounts, I believe, will not object to this classification, since they oppose Artiga and Martinez (2016)’s interpretation and stress their own ahistorical character. Overall, these terminological issues constitute a non-negligible part of current “philosophical” discussions, in which hasty dismissals by presupposing different meanings of the same term flow around. In my hope, the clarification approach endorsed by Nagel in particular and logical empiricists in general might play a limited role in relieving “the climate of opinions” and promoting rational discussions.

  4. 4.

    Indeed, while there are almost no declared eliminativists today in the biological function debate, the position of some philosophers (e.g., Craver 2001; Cummins 1975; Hardcastle 1999) runs rather close to Nagel’s version of eliminativism. I learn this from Garson (2014) who prefers to call them conventionalists.

  5. 5.

    One objection often voiced against the systematic approach in the biological function debate refers to the normativity problem. According to this objection, most systematic accounts are problematic, because they are unable to capture the normative implications of function terms: the function of a biological entity is said to be different from its mere effect, because it is supposed to give rise to its effect; or put it positively, any account of biological function should distinguish functions from mere accidents, and captures the possibility of dysfunction or malfunction. For instance, Millikan (1989, p. 299) claims that “[systematic] accounts of purpose or function in terms of present disposition or structure run afoul exactly when they confront the most central issue of all, namely, the problem of what failure of purpose and defectiveness are”. To avoid this normativity problem, the evolutionary approach recommends that the function of a biological entity should be interpreted as its selected effect. While it is impossible to argue in detail here, I agree with Davies (2000), Craver (2001), Boorse (2002) and Brunnander (2011) that the normativity problem does not exist, and it actually retains an anthropomorphic mode of thinking.

  6. 6.

    Indeed, this echoes the distinction between descriptive semantics and normative/pure semantics made by other logical empiricists like Rudolf Carnap (1942/1948, pp. 11–15).

  7. 7.

    I learn from Garson (2014) that Schyfter (2015) adopts a similar view from the standpoint of social epistemology.

  8. 8.

    Very interestingly, one of the main participants of the early biological function debate and the chief supporter of the evolutionary approach Wright (1976) already provided such a hypothetical scenario, in which “a metaphor dies when the metaphorically extended use of a term becomes established more or less independently of the original paradigm” (p. 19). As a matter of fact, only after having detected the meaning change of function terms, could Wright assign himself the new task of meeting “the requirement of literal translatability” (p. 18).

  9. 9.

    For instance, within the evolutionary approach, one can place emphasis on the recent past (e.g., Godfrey-Smith 1994), or other types of selection (e.g., Garson 2011, 2012), or the non-selective history (e.g. Buller 1998). Within the systematic approach, one can focus on plasticity (e.g. Nagel 1977/1979; Enç and Adams 1992), or negative feedback (e.g. Faber 1984), or reproduction (e.g. Schlosser 1998), or self-maintaining networks (e.g. Mossio et al., 2009). In principle, one can even devise a rather peculiar account and prescribes it as a rule on how to use function terms. While this peculiar account might violate actual biological usage in every word, the point is that it is not refutable if treated as offering prescriptive rules.

  10. 10.

    Further, consider the objection resulting from the normativity problem, mentioned in Footnote 5. If this objection is driven by an anthropomorphic mode of thinking, then the normativity problem cannot be solved in principle, since, no matter how many different laws and facts from biology are defined into function terms, accounts of biological function remain non-intentional and are therefore unable to achieve a genuine anthropomorphic status. So, in addition to the motivation of capturing actual biological usage, another motivation of offering so many accounts of biological function seems a rather implicit anthropomorphic tendency, channeled through the normativity problem.

  11. 11.

    As can be anticipated, some will take issues with this point and claim that, since the biological function debate attempts to describe actual biological usage and even recommend biologists new rules of using function terms, it helps vocabularies used by biologists to achieve a higher level of systematicity and comprehensiveness, and is resultantly still relevant to genuine biological knowledge. In fact, I do not dispute this claim, and my point is rather that giving so many accounts are unnecessary to adequately expressing biological knowledge.

  12. 12.

    Here it is important to distinguish objects predicatable of life (extension) and life itself (intension). What we general call biological knowledge is only knowledge about the former, rather than the latter (Ben-Naim, ms). Indeed, it is safe to say that we possess no genuine knowledge about life itself, even though we recognize so many things as alive in the world.

  13. 13.

    As Kant maintained, “information […] about […] the origination and the inner possibility of these forms [of living beings] […] is that with which theoretical natural science is properly concerned”, and “positing ends of nature in its products […] in accordance with teleological concepts […] provides no [such] information at all” (1790/2000, 5: p. 417).

  14. 14.

    Resonating with eliminativism in the biological function debate, in the life definition debate there is also an eliminativist stance which tends to remove the concept of life from biology (Machery 2012; Mariscal and Doolittle 2018); correspondingly, there are also biologists and philosophers who attempt to relate life, like those who relate biological function, to different portions of biological knowledge (Bich and Green 2016; Koonin 2012; Mix, 2015; Smith 2016; Trifonov 2011). Yet, eliminativism is less defensible regarding life: if the reality of life is not denied (very implausible), while biological teleology can be reduced to life as the anthropomorphic tendency, life (to emphasize again, I mean the pure phenomenon of life, not ordinary biological phenomena) is irreducible to anything else. For this point, see also Voegelin (1933/1998, p. 144).

  15. 15.

    As is often known to Kant scholars, Kant conceived of the principle of teleology (and life) as merely regulative rather than constitutive. Then some judged Kant’s pessimism over a scientific biology (due to the lack of constitutive principles) inadequate (e.g., Zammito, 2006). However, my view is that Kant’s sophisticated discussion on teleology and life remains little understood, due to the failure of clarifying different meanings of the regulative-constitutive distinction. For details, see Friedman (1992) and Chen (2019, pp. 275–91).

  16. 16.

    As one reviewer helpfully points out, at least in the descriptive dimension of the debate there remains the possibility of selecting a best account in terms of its ability to describe and predict relevant biological usage. Indeed, even though pluralism might be the best solution given current biological usage, it is still plausible that in a different spatial–temporal world a dominant account exists as it best describes and predicts biological usage in that world.

References

  • Allen, C., & Bekoff, M. (1995). Biological function, adaptation, and natural design. Philosophy of Science, 62(4), 609–622.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allen, C., et al. (Eds.). (1998). Nature’s purposes. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Amundson, R., & Lauder, G. V. (1994). Function without purpose. Biology & Philosophy, 9(4), 443–469.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ariew, A. R., et al. (Eds.). (2002). Functions. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Artiga, M., & Martínez, M. (2016). The Organizational account of function is an etiological account of function. Acta Biotheoretica, 64(2), 105–117.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Artiga, M. (2011). Re-organizing organizational accounts of function. Applied Ontology, 6(2), 105–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Artiga, M. (2014). The modal theory of function is not about functions. Philosophy of Science, 81(4), 580–591.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ayala, F. J. (1970). Teleological explanations in evolutionary biology. Philosophy of Science, 37(1), 1–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beckner, M. (1969). Function and teleology. Journal of the History of Biology, 2, 151–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ben-Naim, A. (ms). Can entropy be defined for, and the second law applied to living systems? Unpublished manuscript. https://arxiv.org/abs/1705.02461

  • Bich, L., & Green, S. (2016). Is defining life pointless? Operational definitions at the frontiers of biology. Synthese, 195(6), 1–28.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bigelow, J., & Pargetter, R. (1987). Functions. The Journal of Philosophy, 84(4), 181–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boorse, C. (2002). A rebuttal on functions. In A. Ariew, R. Cummins, & M. Perlman (Eds.), Functions: New essays in the philosophy of psychology and biology (pp. 63–112). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brunnander, B. (2011). On the theoretical motivation for positing etiological functions. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 41(3), 371–390.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buller, D. (1998). Etiological theories of function: A geographical survey. Biology & Philosophy, 13(4), 505–527.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buller, D. (1999). Natural teleology. In D. Buller (Ed.), Function, selection, and design (pp. 1–27). State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1942/1948). Introduction to Semantics. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chen, B. (2019). A Historico-logical Study of Vitalism: Life and Matter. Doctoral Dissertation, Ghent University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F. (2001). Role functions, mechanisms, and hierarchy. Philosophy of Science, 68(1), 53–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, R. (1975). Functional analysis. Journal of Philosophy, 72(20), 741–765.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cusimano, S., & Sterner, B. (2019). Integrative pluralism for biological function. Biology & Philosophy, 34(55). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-019-9717-8

  • Davies, P. (2000). Malfunctions. Biology & Philosophy, 15, 19–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davies, P. (2001). Norms of nature: Naturalism and the nature of functions. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Prado Salas, J. G. (2018). Whose purposes? Biological teleology and intentionality. Synthese, 195(10), 4507–4524.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Delancey, C. S. (2006). Ontology and teleofunctions: A defense and revision of the systematic account of teleological explanation. Synthese, 150(1), 69–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • El-hani, N. C., & Nunes-Neto, F. N. (2009). Function in biology: Etiological and organizational perspectives. Acta Biológica Colombiana, 14, 111–132.

    Google Scholar 

  • Enc, B., & Adams, F. (1992). Functions and goal directedness. Philosophy of Science, 59(4), 635–654.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Faber, R. J. (1984). Feedback, selection, and function: A reductionistic account of goal-orientation. In R. Cohen & M. W. Wartofsky (Eds.), Methodology, metaphysics and the history of science (pp. 43–135). D. Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. (1992). Regulative and constitutive. The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 30(1), 73–102.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garson, J. (2008). Function and teleology. In A. Plutynski & S. Sarkar (Eds.), A companion to the philosophy of biology (pp. 525–549). Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garson, J. (2011). Selected effects and causal role functions in the brain: The case for an etiological approach to neuroscience. Biology & Philosophy, 26(4), 547–565.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garson, J. (2012). Function, selection, and construction in the brain. Synthese, 189(3), 451–481.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garson, J. (2014). Realism, conventionalism, and irrealism about biological functions: A reply to Schyfter. Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective, 3(6), 77–81.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garson, J. (2016). A critical overview of biological functions. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garson, J. (2017a). A generalized selected effects theory of function. Philosophy of Science, 84(3), 523–543.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garson, J. (2017b). Against organizational functions. Philosophy of Science, 84(5), 1093–1103.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garson, J. (2018). How to be a function pluralist. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 69(4), 1101–1122.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garson, J. (2019a). What biological functions are and why they matter. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garson, J. (2019b). There are no ahistorical theories of function. Philosophy of Science, 86(5), 1146–1156.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gayon, J. (2010). Defining life: Synthesis and conclusions. Origins of Life & Evolution of Biospheres, 40(2), 231–244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ghiselin, M. T. (2001). Can biologists and philosophers see eye to eye on function? History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences, 23(2), 279–284.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ghiselin, M. T. (2002). Teleology: Grounds for avoiding both the word and the thing. History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences, 24(3/4), 487–491.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (1993). Functions: Consensus without unity. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 74(3), 196–208.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (1994). A modern history theory of functions. Noûs, 28(3), 344–362.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P. E. (1993). Functional analysis and proper functions. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 44(3), 409–422.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P. E. (2006). Function, homology, and character individuation. Philosophy of Science, 73(1), 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hardcastle, V. (1999). Understanding functions: A pragmatic approach. In V. Hardcastle (Ed.), Where biology meets psychology: Philosophical essays (pp. 27–43). MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C.G. (1959/1965). The logic of functional analysis. In Aspects of Scientific Explanation. (pp. 297–330). Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huneman, P. (Ed.). (2013). Functions: Selection and mechanisms. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jonas, H. (1966). The phenomenon of life. Dell Publishing Co., Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1790/2000). Critique of the Power of Judgment (Guyer, P., & Matthews, E. Trans.). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1769/2005). Notes and fragments (Bowman, C., Guyer, P., & Rauscher, F., Trans.). Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koonin, E. V. (2012). Defining life: An exercise in semantics or a route to biological insights? Journal of Biomolecular Structure and Dynamics, 29(4), 603–605.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kraemer, D. M. (2013). Statistical theories of functions and the problem of epidemic disease. Biology & Philosophy, 28(3), 423–438.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E. (2012). Why I stopped worrying about the definition of life... and why you should as well. Synthese, 185(1), 145–164

    Google Scholar 

  • Mariscal, C., & Doolittle, W. F. (2018). Life and life only: A radical alternative to life definitionism. Synthese, 197, 2975–2989.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthewson, J. (2020). Does proper function come in degrees? Biology & Philosophy, 35(4), 1–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. (1974). Teleological and teleonomic: A new analysis. In R. S. Cohen & M. W. Wartofsky (Eds.), Methodological and Historical Essays in the Natural and Social Sciences (pp. 91–117). D. Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • McDonough, J. (2020). Not dead yet: Teleology and the ‘Scientific Revolution.’ In J. McDonough (Ed.), Teleology: A History (pp. 150–179). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • McLaughlin, P. (2003). What Functions Explain: Functional Explanation and Self-reproducing Systems. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. G. (1989). In defense of proper functions. Philosophy of Science, 56(2), 288–302.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, S. D. (1993). Dispositions or etiologies? A comment on Bigelow and Pargetter. The Journal of Philosophy, 90(5), 249–259.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mix, L. J. (2015). Defending definitions of life. Astrobiology, 15(1), 15–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mossio, M., & Saborido, C. (2016). Functions, organization and etiology: A reply to Artiga and Martinez. Acta Biotheoretica, 64(3), 263–275.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mossio, M., Saborido, C., & Moreno, A. (2009). An organizational account of biological functions. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 60(4), 813–841.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1936). Impressions and appraisals of analytic philosophy in Europe I. The Journal of Philosophy, 33(1), 5–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1945). Probability and non-demonstrative inference. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 5(4), 485–507.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1953). Teleological explanations and teleological systems. In H. Feigl & M. Brodbeck (Eds.), Readings in the Philosophy of Science (pp. 537–558). Appleton-Century-Crofts.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1956). A formalization of functionalism. Logic without Metaphysics: And Other Essays in the Philosophy of Science (pp. 247–283). The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1961/1979). The Structure of Science: Problem in the Logic of Scientific Explanation. Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1977/1979). Teleology revisited: A. Goal-directed processes in biology; B. Functional explanations in biology. In Teleology Revisited and Other Essays in the Philosophy and History of Science (pp. 275–316). Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nanay, B. (2010). A modal theory of function. The Journal of Philosophy, 107(8), 412–431.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nanay, B. (2012). Function Attributions Defend on the Explanatory Context: A Reply to Neander and Rosenberg’s Reply to Nanay. The Journal of Philosophy, 109(10), 623–627.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neander, K. (1991). Functions as selected effects: The conceptual analyst’s defense. Philosophy of Science, 58, 168–184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neander, K. (2017). Functional analysis and the species design. Synthese, 194(4), 1147–1168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neander, K., & Rosenberg, A. (2012). Solving the circularity problem for functions: A response to Nanay. The Journal of Philosophy, 109(10), 613–622.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nissen, L. A. (1997). Teleological Language in the Life Sciences. Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Odenbaugh, J., & Griffiths, P. (2020). Philosophy of biology. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2020/entries/biology-philosophy

  • Preston, B. (1998). Why is a wing like a spoon? A pluralist theory of function. The Journal of Philosophy, 95(5), 215–254.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prior, E. W. (1985). What is wrong with etiological accounts of biological function? Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 66(3–4), 310–328.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quarfood, M. (2006). Kant on biological teleology: Towards a two-level interpretation. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part c: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 37(4), 735–747.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ruse, M. (1971). Functional statements in biology. Philosophy of Science, 38(1), 87–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ruse, M. (2000). Teleology: Yesterday, today, and tomorrow? Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part c: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 31(1), 213–232.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saborido, C., et al. (2014). New directions in the philosophy of biology: A new taxonomy of functions. In M. C. Galavotti (Ed.), New Directions in the Philosophy of Science (pp. 235–251). Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Saborido, C., Mossio, M., & Moreno, A. (2011). Biological organization and cross-generation functions. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62(3), 583–606.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schlosser, G. (1998). Self-re-production and functionality. Synthese, 116(3), 303–354.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, P. H. (2004). An alternative to conceptual analysis in the function debate: Introduction. The Monist, 87(1), 136–153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schyfter, P. (2015). Function by Agreement. Social Epistemology, 29(2), 185–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, K. C. (2016). Life is hard: Countering definitional pessimism concerning the definition of life. International Journal of Astrobiology, 15(4), 277–289.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, R. (1950). Purposeful and non-purposeful behavior: A rejoinder. Philosophy of Science, 17(4), 327–332.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trifonov, E. N. (2011). Vocabulary of definitions of life suggests a definition. Journal of Biomolecular Structure and Dynamics, 29(2), 259–266.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Den Berg, H. (2015). Kant on Proper Science: Biology in the Critical Philosophy and the Opus Postumum. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Voegelin, E. (1933/1998). The history of the race idea (H. Ruth, trans.). Louisiana State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walsh, D. M. (1996). Fitness and function. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 47(4), 553–574.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walsh, D. M. (2008). Teleology. In M. Ruse (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy of biology (pp. 113–137). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walsh, D. M., & Ariew, A. (1996). A taxonomy of functions. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 26(4), 493–514.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, G. (1966). Adaptation and natural selection. Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt, W. C. (1972). Teleology and the logical structure of function statements. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 3, 1–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wouters, A. G. (2003). Four notions of biological function. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part c: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 34(4), 633–668.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wouters, A. G. (2005). The function debate in philosophy. Acta Biotheoretica, 53(2), 123–151.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wright, L. (1968). The case against teleological reductionism. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 19(1), 211–223.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wright, L. (1973). Functions. The Philosophical Review, 82(2), 139–168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wright, L. (1976). Teleological explanations: An etiological analysis of goals and functions. University of California Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Zammito, J. H. (2006). Teleology then and now: The question of Kant’s relevance for contemporary controversies over function in biology. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 37(4), 748–770.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2022 The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Chen, B. (2022). On Ernest Nagel on Teleology in Biology. In: Neuber, M., Tuboly, A.T. (eds) Ernest Nagel: Philosophy of Science and the Fight for Clarity. Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science, vol 53. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-81010-8_10

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics