Skip to main content

Forms of Structuralism: Bourbaki and the Philosophers

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Structures Mères: Semantics, Mathematics, and Cognitive Science

Part of the book series: Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics ((SAPERE,volume 57))

Abstract

In this paper, we argue that, contrary to the view held by most philosophers of mathematics, Bourbaki’s technical conception of mathematical structuralism is relevant to philosophy of mathematics. In fact, we believe that Bourbaki has captured the core of any mathematical structuralism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Here is the original text in French: “Les mathématiciens, comme tous les scientifiques, ont besoin de visées téléologiques qui leur permettent de structurer et de légitimer leurs discours. Bourbaki avait réussi à donner une aura indiscutable à la pensée mathématique, en lui procurant un ressort—le structuralisme—et une finalité—la recherche d’une architecture aboutie et hiérarchisée de ses concepts et résultats.”.

  2. 2.

    There is one important exception to this, namely the so-called structuralist school in philosophy of science of the 1970’s and 1980’s, led by Suppes, Suppe, Moulines and Balzer. Some of them explicitly based their work on Bourbaki’s technical notion of structure. See, for instance, Erhard Scheibe’s work in philosophy of physics.

  3. 3.

    To be fair, although Dieudonné and Cartier, as well as others, have claimed that category theory provided a more convenient framework for structural mathematics, to use Dieudonné terminology, he never offered a proper and general analysis of the notion of abstract mathematical structure in the language of categories nor can we find a clear claim made by a member of Bourbaki that the latter provides foundations for mathematics.

  4. 4.

    As we will see, this is not unfounded and unjustified.

  5. 5.

    The main source here is his book: (Corry 1996). We agree with many claims made by Corry, in particular the claim that the volume on set theory stands apart in Bourbaki’s output, and not because of its clarity and rigor. We disagree on one particular, but important point about Corry’s approach, as we will make clear.

  6. 6.

    When Corry uses the italics, he refers to the technical notion of structure.

  7. 7.

    Note that this is an aesthetic evaluation. Elsewhere, Mac Lane called it “a cumbersome piece of pedantry.”(Lane 1996, 181). This is also an aesthetic judgment. It might nonetheless still be essentially correct, despite being ugly.

  8. 8.

    Bourbaki’s axiomatic set theory was definitely odd, idiosyncratic and arguably inadequate. The details of Bourbaki’s set theory has no impact on our main claim. However, for more on Bourbaki’s set theory, see for instance (Mathias 2014).

  9. 9.

    I have looked at this method in more details in the following two papers: (Marquis 2014, 2016).

  10. 10.

    It has to be pointed out that when Bourbaki writes and decides to systematically develop this standpoint, he finds resistance among contemporary mathematicians who believed that the axiomatic method was unable to produce any genuinely new concepts and results. At the risk of repeating ourselves, Bourbaki sees the axiomatic method as a creative method in mathematics. For a discussion of the creative role of axioms in mathematics, see also (Schlimm 2011).

  11. 11.

    This is a point where the introduction of category theory would have changed the picture considerably. Indeed, a whole section should be written on the development of the axiomatic method in the language of categories, as was done by Grothendieck in his paper on homological algebra (Grothendieck 1957). It can be argued that Grothendieck’s way of doing mathematics is a natural extension of Bourbaki’s presentation in The Architecture of Mathematics. Thus, one aspect of Grothendieck’s style is not that surprising when seen in this light.

  12. 12.

    We are not saying that this is original with Bourbaki. The idea, at least restricted to algebra, was already implicit in van der Waerden’s Moderne Algebra and explicit in a paper written by Helmut Hasse in 1931. See Hasse (1986). Since some members of Bourbaki have worked with Hasse and others of the German school in these years, it is not entirely ridiculous to believe that they had discussed these matters with them.

  13. 13.

    This claim might sound silly, but it is fairly easy to explain how it happened by looking at the Bourbaki archives and the evolution of the project. It has to be kept in mind that Bourbaki had no logician among its members. Claude Chevalley was the only founding member who was interested in logic and metamathematics and there is clear evidence that he was responsible for the presence of logic and the metamathematical standpoint in the various versions of the notion. Other members, like Dieudonné and Weil, thought that logic and metamathematics were peripheral and secondary to the whole enterprise.

  14. 14.

    The notion of mother structure is nowhere to be found in the official texts.

  15. 15.

    We have to point out, as many have done, that Bourbaki’s presentation of logic and set theory is very idiosyncratic and it is difficult to understand why he clung to his vocabulary and axioms. One obvious example is his choice to talk about assemblage to designate what any other logician calls a formula. Most commentators would focus on his choice of the \(\tau \) operator and his axioms for set theory, and rightly so. He could easily have used standard notation and notions at that point, since after all, Kleene’s monumental Introduction to Metamathematics was published in 1952, to mention but the most famous textbook available at the time. Bourbaki was well aware of Hilbert and Ackermann’s book published in 1928, but he unfortunately did not adopt its conventions.

  16. 16.

    We are not following Bourbaki’s conventions, which we find unnecessarily complicated and we simplify both the notation and the presentation.

  17. 17.

    This can easily be translated into purely formal requirements of the usual kind.

  18. 18.

    It is, indeed, very tempting to start the analysis in the category of sets and define the notion of species of structures directly there. That would yield a perfectly acceptable mathematical analysis of that latter notion. It is probably what Bourbaki would have done, had he agreed on a way to do it. It was done by Ehresmann in (Ehresmann 1965) and, more recently and in a different context, by Joyal in (Joyal 1981). Our goal, and we believe Bourbaki’s goal too, is to provide a genuine metamathematical analysis, something that is required to anchor a structuralist standpoint about the whole of abstract mathematics.

  19. 19.

    Two specific and surprising cases have to be mentions: the notion of homeomorphism for topological spaces and the notion of equivalence of categories. In the case of topological spaces, mathematicians did not see immediately what the right notion was and there was some confusion in the literature for quite some time. See Moore (2007) for details. As for categories, Eilenberg and Mac Lane introduced the notion of isomorphism of categories in 1945, thinking that it was the proper criterion of identity for them. The right notion, namely the notion of equivalence, was introduced by Grothendieck in his paper in homological algebra in 1957, thus twelve years after the publication of Eilenberg and Mac Lane’s original paper. See Marquis (2009).

  20. 20.

    Dieudonné does not give the definition of a topological space either, believing that “the degree of abstraction required for the formulation of the axioms of such a structure is decidedly greater that it was in the preceding examples; the character of the present article makes it necessary to refer interested readers to special treatises” (Bourbaki 1950, 227).

  21. 21.

    Corry is very well aware of the fact that there were no general analysis of the notion of isomorphism before Bourbaki. Indeed, in a different paper, he says “None of these concepts, however, is defined in a general fashion so as to be a priori available for each of the particular algebraic systems [in van der Waerden’s textbook]. Isomorphisms for instance, are defined separately for groups and for rings and fields, and van der Waerden showed in each case that the relation “is isomorphic to” is reflexive, transitive and symmetric” (Corry 2001, 172).

  22. 22.

    Notice the ambiguity here. We are still in metamathematics, but it is all too easy to fall back on a purely set theoretical reading of the definitions and notions given. We are talking about set theoretical formulas all along. We have to write down formulas such that, when they are interpreted in sets, then the \(f_i\)s are bijections.

  23. 23.

    This is very surprising. Of course, Bourbaki does not literally mean that a species of structure is a text, for it has to be an interpretation of that text in a mathematical domain. There is no doubt that Bourbaki understood that, but this is what one reads. I suspect that the emphasis on the text was deliberate in order to underline the metamathematical nature of the analysis.

  24. 24.

    See, for instance definition 3 in the first section of the volume on general topology. The reference is explicit. The definition given by Bourbaki of isomorphism of topological spaces is not the standard definition. Bourbaki then immediately shows that the definition that follows from the general notion of isomorphism of structure is equivalent to the standard definition of homeomorphism. Corry is absolutely correct to point out that “the verification of this simple fact (which is neither done nor suggested in the book) is a long and tedious (though certainly straightforward) formal exercice”(Corry 1992, 330). However, it misses the main point, which is essentially metamathematical.

  25. 25.

    Thus, we disagree with Corry’s evaluation that by 1957, category theory had reached the status of an independent discipline that enabled generalized formulations of several recurring mathematical situations. Mac Lane had further developed some central ideas in his article on ‘duality’ (Corry 1992, 332). Category was not yet an independent discipline and although it did enabled generalized formulations of several recurring mathematical situations, these were restricted to algebraic topology and homological algebra. Mac Lane’s paper was not very influential and it is with hindsight that one sees into it some of the ideas that will become central after 1957, once they will be shown to be systematically related to central concepts of the theory.

  26. 26.

    Makkai published only one “official” paper on FOLDS, namely (Makkai 1998). There is much more available on his web site: http://www.math.mcgill.ca/makkai/. For an informal presentation of FOLDS and some aspects of its motivation, see (Marquis 2018). Emily Riehl pointed out to me that the claim made in the footnote 37 of the latter that the simplex category with morphisms restricted to the injective functions is the FOLDS-signature for simplicial sets is wrong. It is the FOLDS-signature for semi-simplicial sets.

  27. 27.

    It could be argued that homotopy type theory with the univalence axiom also provides a solution. See, HoTT (UFP 2013). We will not discuss HoTT here.

  28. 28.

    One of the things that Bourbaki did not see is the importance of the relations between structures, in particular between algebraic and topological structures, which are made explicit and possible by category theory. The most striking example of that interaction that was available from early on is the equivalence between the category of affine schemes and the (opposite) of the category of commutative rings. It is this interaction that allowed Grothendieck to develop new foundations for algebraic geometry, foundations that are not given by the axiomatic method.

References

  • Atiyah, M. (2007). Bourbaki, A secret society of mathematicians and the artist and the mathematician-a book review. Notices of the AMS, 54(9), 1150–1152.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benacerraf, P. (1965). What numbers could not be. The Philosophical Review, 74(1), 47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bourbaki, N. (1950). The architecture of mathematics. American Mathematical Monthly, 57, (221–232).

    Google Scholar 

  • Burgess, J. P. (2015). Rigor and structure. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cartan, H. (1943). Sur le fondement logique des mathématiques. Revue scientifique, LXXXI, 3–11.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartan, H. (1979/80). Nicolas Bourbaki and contemporary mathematics. Math. Intelligencer, 2(4), 175–180.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartier, P. (1998). Le structuralisme en mathématiques: mythes ou réalité?. Bures-sur-Yvette: Technical report.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chihara, C. S. (2004). A structural account of mathematics. New York: The Clarendon Press, Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cole, J. C. (2010). Mathematical structuralism today. Philosophy Compass, 5(8), 689–699.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Corry, L. (1992). Nicolas Bourbaki and the concept of mathematical structure. Synthese, 92(3), 315–348.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Corry, L. (1996). Modern algebra and the rise of mathematical structures (Vol. 17). Science Networks Basel: Historical Studies. Birkhäuser Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Corry, L. (2001). Mathematical structures from Hilbert to Bourbaki: the evolution of an image of mathematics. In U. Bottazzini, & A. D. Dalmedico (Eds.), Changing images in mathematics: from the french revolution to the new millenium, studies in the history of science, technology and medicine (pp. 167–186). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Corry, L. (2009). Writing the ultimate mathematical textbook: Nicolas Bourbaki’s ‘Éléments de mathématique’. In E. Robson & J. Stedall (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of the history of mathematics (pp. 565–588). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dieudonné, J. A. (1970). The work of Nicholas Bourbaki. The American Mathematical Monthly, 77(2), 134.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ehresmann, C. (1965). Catégories et structures. Paris: Dunod.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grothendieck, A. (1957). Sur quelques points d’algèbre homologique. Tôhoku Mathematical Journal, 2(9), 119–221.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (2014). Why is there philosophy of mathematics at all?. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hasse, H. (1986). The modern algebraic method. The Mathematical Intelligencer, 8(2), 18–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hellman, G. (1989). Mathematics without numbers: towards a modal-structural interpretation. Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hellman, G. (1996). Structuralism without structures. Philosophia Mathematica. Series III, 4(2), 100–123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hellman, G. (2003). Does category theory provide a framework for mathematical structuralism? 11(2), 129–157.

    Google Scholar 

  • Joyal, A. (1981). Une théorie combinatoire des séries formelles. Advances in Mathematics, 42(1), 1–82.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krömer, R. (2006). La “machine de Grothendieck” se fonde-t-elle seulement sur des vocables métamathématiques? Bourbaki et les catégories au cours des années cinquante. Revue d’histoire des mathématiques, 12, 119–162.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mac Lane, S. (1986). Letters to the editor. The Mathematical Intelligencer, 8(2), 5–5.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mac Lane, S. (1996). Structure in mathematics. Philosophia Mathematica. Series III, 4(2), 174–183.

    Google Scholar 

  • Makkai, M. (1998). Towards a categorical foundation of mathematics. In J. A. Makowsky & E. V. Ravve (Eds.), Logic Colloquium ’95 (Haifa) (Vol. 11, pp. 153–190), Lecture Notes in Logic. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marquis, J.-P. (2009). From a geometric point of view: a study in the history and philosophy of category theory. In: Logic, epistemology, and the unity of science, vol. 14. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marquis, J.-P. (2015). Mathematical abstraction, conceptual variation and identity. In: P.-E. Bour, G. Heinzmann, W. Hodges, & P. Schroeder-Heister (Eds.), Logic, methodology and philosophy of science, proceedings of the fourteen international congress, pp. 299–322. London: College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marquis, J.-P. (2016). Stairway to heaven: the abstract method and levels of abstraction in mathematics. The Mathematical Intelligencer, 38(3), 41–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marquis, J.-P. (2018). Unfolding FOLDS: a foundational framework for abstract mathematical concepts. In: E. Landry (Ed.), Categories for the working philosophers, pp. 136–162. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mathias, A. R. D. (2014). Hilbert, Bourbaki and the scorning of logic. In: Infinity and truth, pp. 47–156. Hackensack, NJ: World Sci. Publ.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. H. (2007). The evolution of the concept of homeomorphism. Historia Math, 34(3), 333–343.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Patras, F. (2001). La pensée mathématique contemporaine. PUF.

    Google Scholar 

  • The Univalent Foundations Program. (2013). Homotopy type theory—univalent foundations of mathematics. Princeton, NJ: The Univalent Foundations Program; Princeton, NJ: Institute for Advanced Study (IAS).

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlimm, D. (2011). On the creative role of axiomatics. The discovery of lattices by Schröder, Dedekind, Birkhoff, and others. Synthese, 183(1), 47–68.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, S. (1997). Philosophy of mathematics. Structure and ontology. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

The author gratefully acknowledge the financial support of the SSHRC of Canada while this work was done. This paper is part of a larger project on Bourbaki and structuralism which would not have seen the day without Michael Makkai’s influence and generosity. I want to thank him for the numerous discussions we had on the subject. I also want to thank Alberto Perruzzi and Silvano Zipoli for inviting me to present this work at the conference on Bourbaki, mother structures and category theory.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jean-Pierre Marquis .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 The Editor(s) (if applicable) and The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Marquis, JP. (2020). Forms of Structuralism: Bourbaki and the Philosophers. In: Peruzzi, A., Zipoli Caiani, S. (eds) Structures Mères: Semantics, Mathematics, and Cognitive Science. Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics, vol 57. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-51821-9_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics