Skip to main content

Introduction

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Themes from Klein

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 404))

  • 265 Accesses

Abstract

Themes from Klein: Knowledge, Scepticism, and Justification is a collection of essays written to honor retiring philosopher Peter D. Klein, whose work has been and continues to be influential in the ongoing development of contemporary epistemology. Klein has done important work on skepticism, the Gettier problem, the structure of justification, defeasibility theory and defeaters, and his own hotly debated theories, including infinitism and his attempt to systematize what he calls “useful falsehoods.” Klein’s ideas have been influenced, he tells us, by twentieth-century predecessors such as Roderick Chisholm, Ludwig Wittgenstein, and A. J. Ayer. But the reader of Klein’s work will be struck not by whatever similarity it bears to what has come before, nor by the extent to which it departs from the past, but rather by its intellectual integrity. Neither a conformist nor a reactionary, Peter Klein marches to the beat of one drummer: his reasoning. This introduction provides a broad overview of Klein’s ideas on each of the book’s themes (knowledge, skepticism, and justification).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See Klein (2017, 36–37) if you are ready to give up on fairytales concerning Gettier (1963).

  2. 2.

    Klein himself gives a useful runthrough of differences among theories of knowledge and theories of justification in his 1998a encyclopedia entry.

  3. 3.

    For more on misleading defeaters, see Klein (1979 and 1980).

  4. 4.

    In the 1971 paper, this is given as a definition of “propositional knowledge.”

  5. 5.

    In one later paper, Klein adds two additional conditions to avoid the interference of epistemic luck: S must be an ideal epistemic agent, believing all and only justified propositions for no other reason than that they are justified, and S must believe of each of these beliefs that it is justified (1984, 155–156). The final addition is intended to ensure that S is in fact an epistemic agent and not merely a very accurate machine, but the move is questionable, which may be why Klein prefers the 1971 paper (per email correspondence 2018). A more recent definition of a defeater appears in Klein 2017. Defeaters are discussed a bit more in the final part of this introduction. They are also discussed or refined in a number of the chapters in this book, especially Chaps. 9, 14, and 6, by Sharon Ryan, Matthew Kotzen, and Rodrigo Borges, respectively.

  6. 6.

    One of Klein ’s favorite points of attack against etiology-of-belief views is their inability to identify which reliable process is relevant to the formation of any given belief, or what causal mechanism produces, in general, beliefs that q from beliefs that p (2012, 161). He divides etiology views into four prevalent approaches: “tracking theories , safety theories, reliabilism, and virtue epistemology ” (see 2017, 42 for details).

  7. 7.

    Klein takes all causal/etiology views to be “naturalized” to varying degrees and his own view, by contrast, to be normative (1998b, 362).

  8. 8.

    Contrary to this assumption, Sanford C. Goldberg, in Chap. 13, offers an externalist account of epistemic obligation.

  9. 9.

    Knowledge that meets the minimally sufficient conditions for being knowledge is, according to Sosa, “animal knowledge.”

  10. 10.

    Klein (2007b, 5) grants that Sosa’s non-normative knowledge is also a kind of knowledge, but Klein thinks that animal knowledge is not the properly epistemological kind. Note also that the sort of agency useful for thinking about Klein’s views does not entail doxastic voluntarism (6).

  11. 11.

    Klein himself does not speak in terms of primitives or fundamentality within the epistemic. Defeasibility theory is nonetheless distinct from “reasons-first” views. See Sylvan and Sosa (2018) for a characterization of—and their disagreement with—the reason-firster.

  12. 12.

    Unlike Bertrand Russell, Klein does not require that the falsity of a belief be logically impossible in order for the belief to be certain (Klein 1992, 62).

  13. 13.

    For more Klein on skepticism, see also 1982 and 2002.

  14. 14.

    So too does Claudio de Almeida in Chap. 10.

  15. 15.

    Taking Klein out of context makes it easy to read his response to the skeptic as dogmatic . For example, he admits in a 1986 paper to having defended (in Klein 1981) that “since many of our beliefs are in fact such that there are no defeaters, the Cartesian requirement of indubitability is in fact satisfied” (1986, 381n12). This indeed sounds dogmatic. But Klein has substantially revised his view of defeaters since writing Certainty (for an example, see 1995, 230n5). Klein (2017) suggests we can find his best answers to skepticism in Klein 1981, 1995, and 2004c.

  16. 16.

    Doxastic justification is defined in the final section of this introduction.

  17. 17.

    Note that if we counted the truth of the skeptical hypothesis among things we know, reflection would not so easily move us to reject it.

  18. 18.

    Compare infinitism to foundationalism , according to which some beliefs (foundational ones) arrive with “justificational juice” that pours or is poured into other beliefs.

  19. 19.

    When there is a tether, it can vary in strength: our reasoning for believing p can be more or less resistant to defeat (Klein 1985, 107).

  20. 20.

    Klein believes that “it is a contingent fact that our justified beliefs tend to be true” (2017, 41).

  21. 21.

    These reasons can be occurrent beliefs or available dispositionally. But a known belief that p relies on a reason that has actually been deployed and subjected to reflection (see Klein 1984, 157; 1999, 300, 322; 2012, 152).

  22. 22.

    Klein does say that “[d]oxastic justification is parasitic on propositional justification” (2007b, 8), but he does not explicitly demand that the reasons necessary for propositional justification be all-things-considered reasons. Suppose you have some memories of seeing blackbirds and some memories of seeing bluebirds. Willfully ignoring your blackbird memories to focus only on your set of bluebird memories does not mean you are justified in believing the proposition “All birds are blue.” But the definition of propositional justification given above would allow that you could be doxastically justified in believing “All birds are blue” on the basis of your bluebird memories if your blackbird memories have understandably slipped your mind. Sometimes we forget. In more recent work, Klein avoids the ambiguity by referring to a single set of reasons R available to S that contains “all and only (1) the propositions that are the content of S’s beliefs and also (2) the propositions that are rational extensions of S’s beliefs” (2017, 47), but p (the proposition R supports) is a rational extension of S’s beliefs, so the newer definition is problematic.

  23. 23.

    The prohibition on reasoning in circles, even very large ones, is something he in most places takes for granted, although he does provide an argument in Klein 2003 (85).

  24. 24.

    Klein’s own proposal for reconciling infinitism and foundationalism appears in Klein 2014. The thought-string metaphor, again not to be confused with the tether between belief and truth, should not be taken too seriously, beyond what it is used to illustrate here. For one, Klein does not think of justification as something that is transferred along a chain of beliefs, so these strings are not “conductors”, so to speak, of justification. Furthermore, the beliefs in a chain of justification should not be understood as contiguously connected; reasoning does not cause beliefs on Klein’s view.

  25. 25.

    Klein points out that Paul Moser used the term before him and John Post first characterized the position (1998c, 919n1).

  26. 26.

    Peijnenburg & Atkinson’s chapter (Chap. 12) and Matthew Kotzen’s chapter (Chap. 14) are a testament to the relevance of Klein’s ideas to a generation informed by what we could call the “formal turn” of epistemology in recent decades.

References

  • Gettier, E. L. (1963). Is justified true belief knowledge? Analysis, 23, 121–123.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, P. (1971). A proposed definition of propositional knowledge. Journal of Philosophy, 67(16), 471–482.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klein, P. (1976). Knowledge, causality, and defeasibility. Journal of Philosophy, 73, 792–812.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klein, P. (1979). Criticism and comments: Misleading ‘misleading defeaters’. Journal of Philosophy, 76(7), 382–386.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, P. (1980). Misleading evidence and the restoration of justification. Philosophical Studies, 37(1), 81–89.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, P. (1981). Certainty: A refutation of scepticism. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, P. (1982). Reply to professor Odegard. Philosophical Books, 23(4), 198–203.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, P. (1983). Review of Keith Lehrer: Profiles. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 43(3), 409–419.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klein, P. (1984). Real knowledge. Synthese, 55(2), 143–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klein, P. (1985). The virtues of inconsistency. The Monist, 68(1), 105–135.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klein, P. (1986). Radical interpretation and global scepticism. In E. Lepore (Ed.), Truth and interpretation (pp. 369–386). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, P. (1987). On behalf of the skeptic. In S. Luper-Foy (Ed.), The possibility of knowledge: Nozick and his critics (pp. 267–281). Totowa: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, P. (1990). Epistemic compatibilism and canonical beliefs. In M. D. Roth & G. Ross (Eds.), Doubting: Contemporary perspectives on skepticism (pp. 99–119). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Klein, P. (1992). Certainty. In J. Dancy & E. Sosa (Eds.), A companion to epistemology (1st ed., pp. 61–64). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, P. (1995). Skepticism and closure: Why the evil genius argument fails. Philosophical Topics, 23(1), 213–236.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klein, P. (1996). Warrant, proper function, reliabilism and defeasibility. In J. Kvanvig (Ed.), Warrant and contemporary epistemology (pp. 97–130). Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, P. (1998a). The concept of knowledge. In E. Craig (Ed.), The encyclopedia of philosophy (Vol. V, pp. 266–276). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, P. (1998b). Epistemology. In E. Craig (Ed.), The encyclopedia of philosophy (Vol. III, pp. 362–365). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, P. (1998c). Foundationalism and the infinite regress of reasons. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 58(4), 919–925.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klein, P. (1999). Human knowledge and the infinite regress of reasons. Philosophical Perspectives, 13(Epistemology), 297–325.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, P. (2000a). The failures of dogmatism and a new pyrrhonism. Acta Analytica, 15(24), 7–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, P. (2000b). Why not infinitism? In R. Cobb-Stevens (Ed.), Epistemology: Proceedings of the twentieth world congress in philosophy (Vol. V, pp. 199–208). Bowling Green: Philosophy Documentation Center.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Klein, P. (2002). Skepticism. In P. K. Moser (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of epistemology (pp. 336–361). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, P. (2003). How a pyrrhonian skeptic might respond to academic skepticism. In S. Luper (Ed.), The skeptics: Contemporary essays (pp. 75–94). Aldershot: Ashgate Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, P. (2004a). Knowledge is true, non-defeated belief. In S. Luper (Ed.), Essential knowledge: Readings in epistemology (pp. 124–135). New York: Longman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, P. (2004b). There is no good reason to be an academic skeptic. In S. Luper (Ed.), Essential knowledge: Readings in epistemology (pp. 299–309). New York: Longman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, P. (2004c). Closure matters: Academic skepticism and easy knowledge. Philosophical Issues, 14(1), 165–184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klein, P. (2005). Infinitism’s take on justification, knowledge, certainty and skepticism. Veritas: Perspectives in Contemporary Epistemology (special edition), 50(4), 153–172.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, P. (2007a). How to be an infinitist about doxastic justification. Philosophical Studies, 134(1), 25–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klein, P. (2007b). Human knowledge and the infinite progress of reasoning. Philosophical Studies, 134(1), 1–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klein, P. (2008). Useful false beliefs. In Q. Smith (Ed.), Epistemology: New essays (pp. 25–61). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Klein, P. (2010). Self-profiles: Peter Klein. In J. Dancy, E. Sosa, & M. Steup (Eds.), A companion to epistemology (2nd ed., pp. 156–163). Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, P. (2012). What makes knowledge the most highly prized form of true belief. In T. Black & K. Becker (Eds.), The sensitivity principle in epistemology (pp. 152–169). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Klein, P. (2014). Reasons, reasoning, and knowledge: A proposed rapprochement between infinitism and foundationalism. In J. Turri & P. D. Klein (Eds.), Ad infinitum: New essays on epistemological infinitism (pp. 105–124). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Klein, P. (2017). The nature of knowledge. In R. Borges, C. de Almeida, & P. D. Klein (Eds.), Explaining knowledge: New essays on the Gettier problem (pp. 35–56). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sylvan, K., & Sosa, E. (2018). The place of reasons in epistemology. In D. Star (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of reasons and normativity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Fitelson, B., Braden, C. (2019). Introduction. In: Fitelson, B., Borges, R., Braden, C. (eds) Themes from Klein. Synthese Library, vol 404. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-04522-7_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics