Skip to main content
Log in

Infinite lies and explanatory ties: idealization in phase transitions

  • S.I.: Infinite Idealizations in Science
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Infinite idealizations appear in our best scientific explanations of phase transitions. This is thought by some to be paradoxical. In this paper I connect the existing literature on the phase transition paradox to work on the concept of indispensability, which arises in discussions of realism and anti-realism within the philosophy of science and the philosophy of mathematics. I formulate a version of the phase transition paradox based on the idea that infinite idealizations are explanatorily indispensable to our best science, and so ought to attract a realist attitude. I go on to offer a solution to the paradox by drawing a distinction between two types of indispensability: constructive and substantive indispensability. I argue that infinite idealizations are constructively indispensable to explanations of phase transitions, but not substantively indispensable. This helps to resolve the paradox, I maintain, since realist commitment tracks substantive, and not constructive, indispensability.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. There are a number of different types of idealization in science. See McMullin (1985), and Weisberg (2007) for more on types of idealization.

  2. See Bangu (2009), Batterman (2002a, b, 2005, 2009), Batterman and Rice (2014), de Donato Rodríguez and Santos (2012), Liu (2001, 2004), Pincock (2011, 2007), Strevens (2008), and Wayne (2011, 2012) for examples of infinite idealizations playing an explanatory role and for discussion of the nature of such explanations.

  3. This line has been pushed by Batterman (2002a, b, 2005, 2009), Batterman and Rice (2014), Strevens (2008), and Wayne (2011).

  4. See e.g., Callender (2001), Menon and Craig (2013).

  5. For discussion of the so-called paradox see Batterman (2002a, 2005), Butterfield (2011), Callender (2001), Liu (1999, 2001, 2004), Menon and Craig (2013), Prigogine (1997), and Shech (2013).

  6. For discussion see Baker (2005), Colyvan (2001) and Maddy (1992).

  7. Following Baron (2016), Woodward (2003) and Woodward and Hitchock (2003), I prefer to construe difference-making counterfactually: A makes a difference to B when if A had not occurred, B would not have occurred. Strevens explicitly resists this way of thinking about difference-making. For Strevens, difference-making is to be understood via causal entailment: A makes a difference to B when A is essential to a causal derivation of B, i.e., a derivation of B from A using a causal law.

  8. Similarly, consider the explanation for the bow-spacing of a rainbow. In our best explanations for the structure of rainbows, the wave-length of light is set to 0. By zeroing out the length of light-waves, it becomes possible to treat light as a ray. Once we’re in the arena of ray dynamics, the structure of a rainbow becomes explicable. On the picture that Strevens paints, the idealization here—treating the wavelength of light as 0—tells us that the wavelength of light makes no difference to the bow-spacing of a rainbow. For discussion of this case see Pincock (2011).

  9. Recall that these are our best scientific theories, and so realism is justified by the same broad realist attitude that gets us into the phase transition paradox in the first place. That being said, I relax this assumption in Sect. 5.1.

  10. To clarify the reasoning being used here:

    1. 1.

      If it is not possible to explain P in a manner that is consistent with background theories that we believe to be true, then either it is not possible to produce a complete and accurate scientific account of nature that is consistent, or it is not possible to produce a consistent and complete scientific account of nature that is accurate or it is not possible to produce a consistent and accurate scientific account of nature that is complete.

    2. 2.

      It is possible to produce a complete, accurate and scientific account of nature.

    3. 3.

      So, it is possible to explain P in manner that is consistent with background theories that we believe to be true.

References

  • Baker, A. (2005). Are there genuine mathematical explanations of physical phenomena? Mind, 114, 223–238.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bangu, S. (2009). Understanding thermodynamic singularities: Phase transitions, data and phenomena. Philosophy of Science, 76, 488–505.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baron, S. (2016). The explanatory dispensability of idealizations. Synthese, 193, 365–386.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Batterman, R. (2002). Asymptotics and the role of minimal models. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 53, 21–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Batterman, R. (2002). The devil in the details. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Batterman, R. (2005). Critical phenomena and breaking drops: Infinite idealizations in physics. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 36, 225–244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Batterman, R. (2009). Idealization and modeling. Synthese, 169, 427–446.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Batterman, R. W. (2010). On the explanatory role of mathematics in empirical science. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 61, 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Batterman, R. W., & Rice, C. C. (2014). Minimal model explanations. Philosophy of Science, 81, 349–376.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Butterfield, J. (2011). Less is different: Emergence and reduction reconciled. Foundations of Physics, 41, 1065–1135.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Callender, C. (2001). Taking thermodynamics too seriously. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 32, 539–553.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Colyvan, M. (2001). The indispensability of mathematics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • de Donato Rodríguez, X., & Santos, A. A. (2012). The structure of idealization in biological theories: The case of the wright-fisher model. Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 43, 11–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hawking, S. W. (1974). Black hole explosions? Nature, 248, 30–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kadanoff, L. P. (2000). Statistical physics: Statics, dynamics and renormalization. Singapore: World Scientific.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Liu, C. (1999). Explaining the emergence of cooperative phenomena. Philosophy of Science, 66, S92–S106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liu, C. (2001). Infinite systems in sm explanations: Thermodynamic limit, renormalization (semi-) groups, and irreversibility. Philosophy of Science, 68, S325–S344.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liu, C. (2004). Approximations, idealizations, and models in statistical mechanics. Erkenntnis, 60, 235–263.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maddy, P. (1992). Indispensability and practice. Journal of Philosophy, 89, 275–289.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McMullin, E. (1985). Galilean idealization. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Science, 16, 247–273.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Menon, T., & Callender, C. (2013). Turn and face the strange... ch–ch-changes: Philosophical questions raised by phase transitions. In Batterman, R. (Ed.) The oxford handbook of philosophy of physics. Oxford University Press, Oxford.

  • Pincock, C. (2007). Mathematical idealization. Philosophy of Science, 74, 957–967.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pincock, C. (2011). Mathematical explanation of the rainbow. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 42, 13–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Priest, G. (2002). Beyond the limits of thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Prigogine, I. (1997). The end of certainty. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shech, E. (2013). What is the paradox of phase transitions? Philosophy of Science, 80, 1170–1181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, M. (2008). Depth: An account of scientific explanation. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wayne, A. (2011). Expanding the scope of explanatory idealization. Philosophy of Science, 78, 830–841.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wayne, A. (2012). Emergence and singular limits. Synthese, 184, 341–356.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M. (2007). Three kinds of idealization. Journal of Philosophy, 104, 639–659.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen: A theory of causal explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J., & Hitchock, C. (2003). Explanatory generalizations, part 1: A counterfactual account. Noûs, 37, 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Sam Baron.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Baron, S. Infinite lies and explanatory ties: idealization in phase transitions. Synthese 196, 1939–1961 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-1678-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-1678-y

Keywords

Navigation