Skip to main content
Log in

Truth in the Investigations

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

According to a widespread interpretation, in the Investigations Wittgenstein adopted a deflationary or redundancy theory of truth. On this view, Wittgenstein’s pronouncements about truth should be understood in the light of his invocation of the equivalences ‘p’ is true = p and ‘p’ is false = not p. This paper shows that this interpretation does not do justice to Wittgenstein’s thoughts. I will be claiming that, in fact, in his second book Wittgenstein is returning to the pre-Tractarian notion of bipolarity, and that his new development of this notion in the Investigations excludes the redundancy-deflationary reading. Wittgenstein’s thoughts about truth are instead compatible with another interpretative option: Wittgenstein remains faithful to his methodological pronouncements, and he merely presents us with (grammatical) platitudes about the notions of “true” and “false”.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Wittgenstein (2010), henceforth referred to as PI.

  2. Thus, the topic comes up after the discussion of the rule-following considerations. Here, Wittgenstein seems to agree with what he says in PI 136. Indeed, he restates the close connection between “proposition” and “true” and “false” (PI 225). On another occasion, he rejects the centrality of the verificationist position he himself held at a certain point (PI 353). And such refusal is also coherent with the claims in PI 136. It fits nicely with the claim that it is a “bad picture” to presuppose a definition of “true” which “fits” with that of “proposition”. On yet another occasion, Wittgenstein confirms the idea that we can’t give up the notions of “true” and “false”. So, that as he says in PI 136, they “belong” to the notion of proposition (PI 241).

  3. To take a few examples, Baker and Hacker (1980, p. 317), Dummett (1978, pp. xxxiv, 317), Forster (2009, pp. 60–64), Kripke (1982, p. 86), Read (2000, p. 75), Priest (2004, p. 210) and Williams (2004, p. 268; 2009, pp. 64, 144) take Wittgenstein’s observations to amount to a “redundancy theory of truth”. Bolton (1979, pp. 159–166) speaks in more general terms of a “Ramseyan view”; for Koethe (1996, p. 136) Wittgenstein conforms to a redundancy account of the truth-predicate under Ramsey’s influence. Blackburn (1998, pp. 166) uses the terms “deflationary” and “redundancy” interchangeably, even if he elsewhere prefers to speak of a “redundancy theory” (Blackburn 2010, p. 210). Goldstein (1999, p. 260) speaks of “deflationism” or “minimalism” and McGinn, (1984, p. 71) of “deflationism”. Finally, according to Glock (1996, p. 144, 366) Wittgenstein held a “redundancy” view in his so-called intermediate period, but turned to a Quinean–inspired-view later on. I think it is impossible to decide if it’s better to call it a “deflationary” or a “redundancy” theory based on Wittgenstein’s pronouncements. On the one hand, the fact that the truth-bearer appears in quotation marks suggests that he is thinking of sentences, hence he has a deflationary (or disquotational) interpretation of the equivalence in mind. On the other hand, Wittgenstein does not deal with the topic only in the Investigations. And, as authors like Baker and Hacker (2005, p. 347n) and Glock (2004, p. 57) point out, some of his pre-Investigations comments suggest that he adopted a redundancy theory. As an illustration, in the Philosophical Grammar, Wittgenstein notes that “one can say that the quotation marks in the sentence “‘p’ is true” are simply superfluous”. This is so because “‘p’ is true” can only be understood if one understands the grammar of the sign “p” as a propositional sign” (Wittgenstein 1974, p. 79; henceforth PG). However, the context makes it clear that Wittgenstein is not contrasting propositions with sentences. The thought that prompts the question about the status of the quotation marks is that “the ink mark is after all not true; in the way in which it’s black and curved”. So, Wittgenstein draws a contrast between ‘p’ as a sign that stays for a sentence or a proposition and the letter p. Hence, the fragment does not really confirm the claim that Wittgenstein adopted the redundancy theory. Nonetheless, I still think that invoking the “redundancy theory” is preferable, as surely, if we want to look for a possible influence, we should turn to Ramsey. In any case, I will speak in general terms of a redundancy-deflationary interpretation—even if I have chosen to refer to Wittgenstein’s identities as the “equivalence” and not the “disquotational” schema.

  4. Wittgenstein (1961), henceforth TLP.

  5. For reasons of space, the matter of whether this should further be understood in a so-called “resolute” or “elucidatory” perspective will not be confronted. I am tempted to favor the “elucidatory” reading, and yet an analysis of the implications of the notion of bipolarity for these two types of readings is very complex, and it is better left for another occasion.

  6. Baker and Hacker (2005, p. 353) are of the same opinion. According to them “the equivalence gives only a small part of the grammar of ‘true”’. For similar pronouncements see also Connelly (2013), and to a certain extent at least Diamond (2003) and Vision (2005).

  7. On this see e.g. Dummett (1978, pp. xx–xi, 24).

  8. Thus, Wittgenstein declares his debt to Ramsey in the Introduction to the Investigations, and Ramsey himself remembers his indebtedness to Wittgenstein (see e.g. Ramsey 1927, p. 170). For more details about the relationship between Ramsey and Wittgenstein see Moore (1954).

  9. This is not meant to suggest that Ramsey influenced Wittgenstein on this point. As a matter of fact, the question of the direction of the influence is rather complex. Ramsey first formulated the redundancy theory in a note from 18th November 1921 (see Ramsey 1991, p. 103). Nonetheless, Wittgenstein notices as soon as 1914 that “‘p’ is true = ‘p’. p” (Wittgenstein 1984, p. 113, henceforth NB) and that “‘p’ is true, says nothing else but p!” (NB, 9). For more on the question of who influenced who see Glock (2004).

  10. Wittgenstein (2000). In the following, references to Wittgenstein’s Nachlass (as cited in the von Wright catalogue Wright 1982, 1993) are by MS or TS number followed by page number.

  11. Changes in this paragraph from 1936 to 1945 are insignificant. To mention a few examples, instead of “But this is a bad picture” as in the final version, Wittgenstein earlier speaks of “being easy to commit an (or fall into) error” (Denn hier is es nun leicht, in einen Irrtum zu verfallen). Also, he refers to the “bad picture” as a schlechtes Bild in the final version and as an irreführendes (misleading) Bild in earlier versions.

  12. Wittgenstein (2012), henceforth BT.

  13. On this see also Baker and Hacker (2005b, p. 292) and Glock (2004, p. 57); for the latter this is a clear sign that Wittgenstein had no qualms with quantifying over propositions.

  14. As Wittgenstein puts it in the Tractatus, “If the world had no substance, then whether a proposition had sense would depend on whether another proposition was true” (TLP 2.021), where “Objects make up the substance of the world” (TLP 2.021).

  15. Another metaphor that explains the notion is that of an arrow “which divides all the points of a plane into right and left” (NB, p. 102).

  16. TLP 6.1203, but for the same notation see NB, 115, 127–129, and also Wittgenstein (1979, pp. 136–137), henceforth AWL.

  17. I thank one of the anonymous Reviewers for calling attention to the fact that there might be reasons to contest my reading of the notion of bipolarity in PI 251 and PI 556. The Reviewer has pointed out that in PI 251 Wittgenstein might actually be dismissing bipolarity, because he compares “I can’t imagine the opposite of this” with a questionable assertion that “I can’t imagine the thing itself”. Also, that in PI 556 Wittgenstein actually presents us with three options for defining negation, and he does not choose one of the three. The Reviewer’s first concern is interesting because it points to a translation problem. The fragment the Reviewer relies on states “Ich kann mir, was du sagst, nicht vorstellen”, which literally means “I can’t imagine what you say” and not “I can’t imagine the thing itself” (on this see the Hacker-Schulte translation, which is much more faithful to the original than the Anscombe translation). Wittgenstein is thus not comparing bipolarity with an elusive question about “thing themselves”, and we have no reason to suppose he is dismissing bipolarity. Regarding PI 556, the Reviewer is certainly correct. Nonetheless, the context of the paragraph makes it clear that there is a good reason why Wittgenstein doesn’t choose the bipolarity-option: he is not considering our language—but an imaginary one. As is well known, for Wittgenstein the meaning of “negation” (as for any other connective) is derived from the rules for its use (see PI 147n, but also my discussion below. So, if the new language would have the same rules as ours, then bipolarity would be the correct choice. But it is impossible to choose one of the three options (PI 557)—the new language might just have different rules than our language.

  18. A similar point is made by Hamilton (2014, p. 116).

  19. The “correspondence theory” interpretation of the Tractatus has occasionally been criticized. For authors like Beckermann (1995), Künne (2003, p. 123) and Hacker (2000, p. 386); but also Baker and Hacker (2005, pp. 349–57) Wittgenstein held a redundancy or a semantic theory of truth in the Tractatus. And there are reasons to acknowledge some of the points made by these interpreters, as Wittgenstein does acknowledge ES as soon as 1914 (see footnote 9 above). Nevertheless, the fact of the matter remains that Wittgenstein’s Tractatus has ontological ingredients that would be superfluous in a redundancy-deflationary theory: it invokes notions such as states of affairs and facts. And these are not idle notions—Wittgenstein relies on them when he defines “truth” and “falsehood”. For example, we are told that “If an elementary proposition is true, the state of affairs exists: if an elementary proposition is false, the state of affairs does not exist” (TLP 4.25). So, even if one chooses to not call the Tractarian view a “correspondence theory”, he must still acknowledge that Wittgenstein does have a substantial notion of truth in mind; that he does have a definition of “true” and “false”. For a discussion of the pros of the redundancy-deflationary interpretation of the Tractatus, but also of the reasons for discarding it see Glock (2006).

  20. For a similar argument see Vision (2005, p. 170).

  21. And he holds on to this idea in all the post-Tractarian writings-see e.g. PG 243-6, RFM VIII 30, PI 147n and Wittgenstein (1976, p. 383); henceforth LFM.

  22. Wittgenstein (1981), henceforth RFM.

  23. I came to realise how this could represent a counter-argument for my reading thanks to Pasquale Frascolla.

  24. In the Nachlass the text corresponds to MS 118: 108v.

  25. For similar pronouncements see LFM, 188. However, one might like to point out that, more recently, authors like Floyd (2001) and Kienzler and Grève (2016) suggest that our interpretation relies on false premises. As Floyd puts it, “It seems to me that Wittgenstein is asking his interlocutor what the notions of true and provable mean in the context of the interlocutor’s ‘proof”’ (Floyd 2001, p. 303). To this our answer is that the matter does not really affect our discussion. Our interest is not in Wittgenstein’s actual view in the Remarks. Rather, our purpose is to get a grip on Wittgenstein’s views in the Investigations, and the similarities between PI 136 and RFM justify our choice to analyze them side by side.

  26. See TS 221: 248.

References

  • Baker, G. P., & Hacker, P. M. S. (1980). Wittgenstein, meaning and understanding: Essays on the philosophical investigations. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baker, G. P., & Hacker, P. M. S. (2005). Wittgenstein: Understanding and meaning—an analytical commentary on the ‘Philosophical Investigations’ vol. 1 Essays (2., extensively ed.). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Baker, G. P., & Hacker, P. M. S. (2005b). Wittgenstein: Understanding and meaning—an analytical commentary on the “Philosophical Investigations” 2 Exegesis §§1–184 (2., extensively ed.). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Beckermann, A. (1995). Wittgenstein, Neurath und Tarski über Wahrheit. Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung, 49, 529–552.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackburn, S. (1998). Symposium: Realism and truth. Wittgenstein, Wright, Rorty, Minimalism. Mind, 107(425), 157–181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blackburn, S. (2010). Practical tortoise raising and other philosophical essays. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bolton, D. (1979). An approach to Wittgenstein’s philosophy. Atlantic Highlands: Humanities Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, R. B. (1994). Making it explicit. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Connelly, J. (2013). Wittgenstein, non-factualism, and deflationism. International Journal of Philosophical Studies, 21, 559–585.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1969). True to the facts. The Journal of Philosophy, 66(21), 748–764.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Diamond, C. (2003). Unfolding truth and reading Wittgenstein. SATS, 4, 24–58.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dummett, M. (1978). Truth and other enigmas. Harvard: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1879). Begriffsschrift, a formula language of pure thought modelled on that of arithmetic. In J. Heijenoort (Ed.) (1967) From Frege to Gödel: A source book in mathematical logic, 1879–1931 (pp. 1–82). Cambridge, MA: Harvard Univesity Press.

  • Floyd, J. (2001). Prose versus proof: Wittgenstein on Gödel, Tarski and truth. Philosophia Mathematica, 9, 280–307.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forster, M. N. (2009). Wittgenstein on the arbitrariness of grammar. Princeton, Oxford: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Glock, H.-J. (1996). A Wittgenstein dictionary. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Glock, H. (2004). Ramsey and Wittgenstein: mutual influences. In M. J. Frapolli (Ed.), F. P. Ramsey: Critical reassessments (pp. 41—68). London, New York: Continuum Studies in British Philosophy.

  • Glock, H. J. (2006). Truth in the Tractatus. Synthese, 148, 345–368.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldstein, L. (1999). Clear and queer thinking: Wittgenstein’s development and his relevance to modern thought. New York: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hacker, P. M. (2000). Was he trying to whistle it? In A. Crary & R. J. Read (Eds.), The new Wittgenstein (pp. 353–383). Oxford: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamilton, A. (2014). Routledge philosophy guidebook to Wittgenstein and on certainty. Oxford: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kenny, A. (1973). Wittgenstein. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kienzler, W., & Grève, S. S. (2016). Wittgenstein on Gödelian ‘Incompleteness’, Proofs and Mathematical Practice: Reading Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics, Part I, Appendix III, Carefully. In S. S. Grève & J. Mácha (Eds.), Wittgenstein and the creativity of language (pp. 76–116). London: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koethe, J. (1996). The continuity of Wittgenstein’s thought. Ithaca, London: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. A. (1982). Wittgenstein on rules and private language: An elementary exposition. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Künne, W. (2003). Conceptions of truth. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • McGinn, C. (1984). Wittgenstein on meaning. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. E. (1954). Wittgenstein’s lectures in 1930–1933. Mind, 63(249), 1–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Priest, G. (2004). Wittgenstein’s remarks on Gödel’s theorem. In M. Kölbel & B. Weiss (Eds.), Wittgenstein’s lasting significance (pp. 207–228). London, New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1999). The threefold cord: Mind, body and world. Columbia: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, V. O. (1953). From a logical point of view: Logico-philosophical essays. Harvard: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey, F. P. (1927). Facts and propositions. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 7(1), 153–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey, F. P. (1991). Notes on philosophy, probability and mathematics. In M. C. Galavotti (Ed.). Napoli: Bibliopolis.

  • Read, R. (2000). What ‘there can be no such thing as meaning anything by any word’ could possibly mean. In A. Crary & R. Read (Eds.), The new Wittgenstein (pp. 74–83). London, New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1998). Autobiography. London, New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vision, G. (2005). The truth about philosophical investigations I §§134-137. Philosophical Investigations, 28, 159–176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • von Wright, G. H. (1982). Wittgenstein. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Wright, G. H. (1993). The Wittgenstein papers. In J. C. Klagge & A. Nordmann (Eds.), Ludwig Wittgenstein: Philosophical occasions 1912–1951 (pp. 480–515). Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, M. (2004). Wittgenstein, truth and certainty. In M. Kölbel & B. Weiss (Eds.), Wittgenstein’s lasting significance (pp. 249–285). London, New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, M. (2009). Blind obedience: The structure and content of Wittgenstein’s later philosophy. London, New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1961). Tractatus logico-philosophicus. D. F. Pears and B.F. McGuinness (Trans.). London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1974). Philosophical grammar. In R. Rhees (Ed.), A. Kenny (Trans.). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1976). Wittgenstein’s lectures on the foundations of mathematics, Cambridge 1939, From the Notes of R. G. Bosanquet, Norman Malcolm, Rush Rhees, and Yorick Smythies. In C. Diamond (Ed). London: Harvester.

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1981). Remarks on the foundations of mathematics. In G. E. M. Anscombe, R. Rhees, & G. H. von Wright (Eds.), G. E. M. Anscombe (Trans.) (revised edition). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1984). Notebooks 1914–1916. In G. E. M. Anscombe, and G. H. von Wright (Eds.), G. E. M. Anscombe (Trans.). Oxford: Blackwell.

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1979). Wittgenstein’s Lectures, Cambridge 1932–1935. In A. Ambrose (Eds.). Oxford: Blackwell.

  • Wittgenstein, L. (2000) Nachlass: The Bergen Electronic Edition, The Wittgenstein Archives at the University of Bergen (Ed). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Wittgenstein, L. (2010). Philosophical investigations. In P. M. S. Hacker & J. Schulte (Eds.), P. M. S. Hacker, and J. Schulte (Trans.). Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.

  • Wittgenstein, L. (2012). Big typescript: TS 213. In C. G. Luckhardt and M. Aue (Eds.). Oxford: Blackwell.

Download references

Acknowledgements

My deepest gratitude goes to Diego Marconi. I could have never written this paper without his suggestions, especially those regarding the notion of bipolarity. I am also very grateful to Razvan Purdel, Fabrizio Calzavarini, Florin Bican and the anonymous referees of this journal for their comments and their help with improving the previous drafts of this article.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Nicoletta Bartunek.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Bartunek, N. Truth in the Investigations. Synthese 196, 4091–4111 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1643-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1643-1

Keywords

Navigation