Skip to main content
Log in

Multiple realization and the commensurability of taxonomies

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The past two decades have witnessed a revival of interest in multiple realization and multiply realized kinds. Bechtel and Mundale’s (Philos Sci 66(2):175–207, 1999) illuminating discussion of the subject must no doubt be credited with having generated much of this renewed interest. Among other virtues, their paper expresses what seems to be an important insight about multiple realization: that unless we keep a consistent grain across realized and realizing kinds, claims alleging the multiple realization of psychological kinds are vulnerable to refutation. In this paper I argue that, intuitions notwithstanding, the terms of their recommendation make it impossible to follow, while also misleadingly insinuating that its application virtually guarantees mind-brain identity. Instead of a matching of grains, what multiple realization really requires is a principled method for adjudicating upon differences between tokens. Shapiro’s (J Philos 97(12):635–654, 2000) work on multiple realization can be understood as an attempt to adumbrate just such a method. While his “causal relevance” criterion can easily be mistaken for Bechtel and Mundale’s grain requirement, my analysis reveals exactly where and why these two tests diverge.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. It only appears to be tendentious when a certain paradigm of realization and MR, the so-called “dimensioned” view, has one under its sway (see Gillett 2003).

  2. Shapiro ultimately uses his analysis to draw out a dilemma confronting the MR advocate. If a given functional kind is not multiply realized, the traditional argument for its autonomy and irreducibility falls away. If on the other hand the kind is multiply realized, the kind will not be a proper scientific kind, i.e. of the sort that can enter into laws. “Brittleness” might be a multiply realized property, but glass, steel and biscuits are each brittle in their own way: there can be no general science of brittle things. Ranging over such genuinely diverse physical realizations means the kind will not enter into laws (i.e. exhibit lawlike or projectable properties), except for those which are true analytically—such as all mousetraps catch mice, and all eyes see—and this in turn “undercut[s] the traditional motivation for admitting functional kinds into the ontologies of the special sciences” (Shapiro 2000, p. 637). In this paper I will not be addressing this issue, but see Couch (2009a, pp. 262–264) for some criticisms. In more recent work Shapiro himself seems to have backed away from this position (Polger and Shapiro 2016).

  3. Bechtel and Mundale’s test at this point can be seen as a bowdlerized version of Shapiro’s causal relevance criterion, which screens off causally irrelevant details when comparing realizing kinds (much as Bechtel and Mundale’s “coarse-graining” procedure does).

  4. The nearest they come is this: “When comparing psychological states across different individuals, psychologists...tend to ignore differences and focus on commonalities” (1999, p. 202). If anything, however, one would have thought that this fact should actually discourage kind splitting (see text).

  5. In subsequent work, Couch (2009a, b) has been more careful in his remarks, and has brought out explicitly the importance of scientific taxonomy in the individuation of both neural and psychological kinds. Still I notice that in these papers he doesn’t rely on granularity arguments, and indeed is even mildly critical of them (2009b, p. 267). When grains hold sway, MR stands little chance of receiving a fair hearing.

  6. By contrast, Couch (2009b, p. 514) puts forward human eyes and pigeon eyes as plausible candidates for MR, and comments: “Accepting that this example is plausible is a revision from an earlier view of mine”.

References

  • Aizawa, K. (2009). Neuroscience and multiple realization: A reply to Bechtel and Mundale. Synthese, 167(3), 493–510.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aizawa, K., & Gillett, C. (2009). Levels, individual variation, and massive multiple realization in neurobiology. In J. Bickle (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy and neuroscience (pp. 539–81). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., & Mundale, J. (1999). Multiple realizability revisited: Linking cognitive and neural states. Philosophy of Science, 66(2), 175–207.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Couch, M. B. (2004). A defense of Bechtel and Mundale. Philosophy of Science, 71(2), 198–204.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Couch, M. B. (2009a). Functional explanation in context. Philosophy of Science, 76(2), 253–269.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Couch, M. B. (2009b). Multiple realization in comparative perspective. Biology and Philosophy, 24, 505–519.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F. (2007). Explaining the brain. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gillett, C. (2003). The metaphysics of realization, multiple realizability, and the special sciences. Journal of Philosophy, 100(11), 591–603.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, S. (2002). Testing multiple realizability: A discussion of Bechtel and Mundale. Philosophy of Science, 69(4), 606–610.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Polger, T. W. (2009). Evaluating the evidence for multiple realization. Synthese, 167(3), 457–472.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Polger, T. W., & Shapiro, L. A. (2016). The multiple realization book. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1967). Psychological predicates. In W. Capitan & D. Merrill (Eds.), Art, mind, and religion (pp. 37–48). Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, L. A. (2000). Multiple realizations. Journal of Philosophy, 97(12), 635–654.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, L. A. (2008). How to test for multiple realization. Philosophy of Science, 75(5), 514–525.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This paper was presented to the American Philosophy of Science Association on 3 November 2016, in Atlanta, Georgia. I am particularly indebted to Larry Shapiro and Tom Polger for helpful discussion, as well as three anonymous reviewers. Warm thanks also to Kim Sterelny and Paul E. Griffiths.

Funding This research was supported by an Australian Government Research Training Program (RTP) Scholarship.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to John Zerilli.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

No potential conflict of interest was reported by the author.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Zerilli, J. Multiple realization and the commensurability of taxonomies. Synthese 196, 3337–3353 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1599-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1599-1

Keywords

Navigation