Skip to main content
Log in

A default-free solution to the imperfective paradox

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This article advances the first semantics that is neither for nor against a default implicational link between the progressive and perfective forms, when it comes to solving the imperfective paradox. Depending on the doxastic context of its use, we contend that the progressive form sometimes allows and sometimes does not allow the inference of the corresponding simple form. In other words, the preparatory phase of an event might or might not be believed to lead to its culmination. Indeed, the context can put constraints on beliefs about the time of the culmination and whether or not it allows this inference to be made. From a formal perspective, this new solution to the imperfective paradox combines a specific modal approach with an event-structure analysis originating in event semantics. Finally, this approach solves the associated difficulties (e.g., pauses, past futures, interruptions and sensibility to description) that have plagued the most well-known theories in this field.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Some are rather neutral on this point, such as Binnick (1991).

  2. Vendler (1957), Kenny (1963), Dowty (1979), Vlach (1981), Lascarides (1991) and Baggio and Lambalgen (2007).

  3. Bennett and Partee (1978) and Parsons (1989).

  4. Inertia worlds are possible worlds identical to the actual world up to the time in question and whose future development is the most compatible with the past events.

  5. Dowty (1979).

  6. Baggio and Lambalgen (2007) and Baggio et al. (2008) provide strong empirical evidence of this claim related to our linguistic intuitions.

  7. On a more technical level, Baggio and van Lambalgen draw on the Event Calculus framework elaborated in van Lambalgen and Hamm (2005).

  8. Baggio and Lambalgen (2007).

  9. This difference between the two theories could be tested experimentally, for instance, by observing whether there is a correlation between the difficulty or the duration of an accomplishment and the belief that it will terminate, without the need of explicit disabling conditions.

  10. Michaelis (2003).

  11. Parsons (1989) provides another important formulation of this same view but the differences are not relevant to our argument.

  12. Parsons (1989) similarly maintains the following: “The difference between a progressive and a non-progressive event sentence is, roughly, whether the sentence requires for its truth that the eventuality picked out by the verb culminates, or whether it only needs to ‘go on’ for a while [to ‘hold’ in Parsons’ terms]”.

  13. Dowty (1979).

  14. Notice that Reichenbach also uses the reference point in his analysis of perfect tenses. For instance, in the sentence John had run, we do not speak directly about the event time at which John runs but instead use an intermediate point \(t_{R}\) for the event time preceding this reference time, which itself occurs before the speech time. However, we will not deal with perfect tenses in this article and instead focus exclusively on progressive tenses.

  15. (Naumann and Piñón 1997) already insisted on the importance of considering the beliefs of the speaker in an analysis of the imperfective paradox.

  16. (Priest 2008) is a good manual for an introduction to semantics associating possible worlds with more than two truth-values.

  17. For a similar though distinct move, see the distinction between objective and subjective truth argued in (Wulf 2000).

  18. This is what is defended by (Dowty 1979) with the inertia worlds.

  19. As suggested by some reviewers, improvements of this semantics could be carried, for instance by formally distinguishing the different agents or by using intervals of time.

  20. Quantification in natural language is sufficiently lax to allow for the domain of quantification to not correspond exactly to the whole set of times constituting the previous day.

  21. This analysis could be extended to deal with unicorns and other non-existent objects. Several solutions exist within the possible world approach: for instance, see Priest (2005).

References

  • Bach, E. (1981). On time, tense, and aspect: An essay in english metaphysics. In P. Cole (Ed.), Syntax and semantics 14: Radical pragmatics (pp. 63–82). New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baggio, G., & van Lambalgen, M. (2007). The processing consequences of the imperfective paradox. Journal of Semantics, 24(4), 307–330.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baggio, G., van Lambalgen, M., & Hagoort, P. (2008). Computing and recomputing discourse models: An ERP study. Journal of Memory and Language, 59, 36–53.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, M., & Partee, B. H. (1978). Toward the logic of tense and aspect in English. Bloomington: Indiana University Linguistics Club.

    Google Scholar 

  • Binnick, R. I. (1991). Time and the verb: A guide to tense and aspect. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chierchia, G., & McConnell-Ginet, S. (1990). Meaning and grammar: An introduction to semantics. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cooper, R. (1985). Aspectual classes in situation semantics. Stanford: Number n 14; n 27 in Aspectual Classes in Situation Semantics. Center for the Study of Language and Information, Stanford University.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Swart, H. (1998). Aspect shift and coercion. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory, 16, 347–385.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dowty, D. (1979). Word meaning and montague grammar. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Engelberg, S. (2002). The semantics of the progressive. In Proceedings of the 2001 conference of the Australian linguistics society (pp. 1–8).

  • Fagin, R., Moses, Y., Halpern, J. Y., & Vardi, M. Y. (2003). Reasoning about knowledge. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, N. (1947). The problem of counterfactual conditionals. Journal of Philosophy, 44(5), 113–128.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hinrichs, E. (1983). The semantics of the english progressive—A study in situation semantics. In Proceedings of the 19th regional meeting of the Chicago linguistics society (pp. 171–182). Chicago.

  • Kenny, A. (1963). Action, emotion and will. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Korta, K., & Perry, J. (2011). Critical pragmatics: An inquiry into reference and communication. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, S. T., & Portner, P. (2006). Tense and time. In D. M. Gabbay & F. Guenthner (Eds.), Handbook of philosophical logic (Vol. 7, pp. 277–346). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Landman, F. (1992). The progressive. Natural Language Semantics, 1(1), 1–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lascarides, A. (1991). The progressive and the imperfective paradox. Synthese, 87(6), 401–447.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michaelis, L. A. (2003). A unification-based model of aspectual type-shifting. Ph.D. thesis, University of Colorado, Boulder.

  • Moens, M., & Steedman, M. (1988). Temporal ontology and temporal reference. Computational Linguistics, 14, 15–28.

    Google Scholar 

  • Naumann, R., & Piñón, C. (1997). Decomposing the progressive. In Proceedings of the 11th Amsterdam colloquium (pp. 241–246). Amsterdam.

  • Parsons, T. (1989). The progressive in english: Events, states and processes. Linguistics and Philosophy, 12(2), 213–241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Portner, P. (1998). The progressive in modal semantics. Language, 74(4), 760–787.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Portner, P. (2011). Perfect and progressive. In C. Maienborn, K. von Heusinger, & P. Portner (Eds.), Semantics: An international handbook of natural language meaning (pp. 1217–1261). Berlin: De Gruyter Mouton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Priest, G. (2005). Towards non-being: The logic and metaphysics of intentionality: The logic and metaphysics of intentionality. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Priest, G. (2008). An introduction to non-classical logic: From if to is. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Prior, A. N. (1957). Time and modality. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prior, A. N. (1967). Past, present and future. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, F. (2004). Literal meaning. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, H. (1947). Elements of symbolic logic. New York: Dover Publications. (Republished 1980).

    Google Scholar 

  • Sperber, D., & Wilson, D. (1996). Relevance: Communication and cognition. Hoboken: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Lambalgen, M., & Hamm, F. (2005). The proper treatment of events. Malden: Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Vendler, Z. (1957). Verbs and times. The Philosophical Review, 66(2), 143–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vendler, Z. (1967). Linguistics in philosophy (Vol. 19). Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vlach, F. (1981). The semantics of the progressive. In P. Tedeschi & A. Zaenen (Eds.), Syntax and semantics 14: Tense and aspect (pp. 271–292). New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1969). On certainty. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. (G.E.M. Anscombe and G.H. von Wright (eds.), trans. by D. Paul and G.E.M. Anscombe).

    Google Scholar 

  • Wulf, D. (2000). The imperfective paradox in the english progressive and other semantic course corrections. Ph.D. dissertation, University of Washington, Seattle, WA.

  • Wulf, D. (2009). Two new challenges for the modal account of the progressive. Natural Language Semantics, 17(3), 205–218.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We would like to thank three anonymous referees for their valuable comments that greatly helped to improve the paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mathieu Vidal.

Additional information

All the concepts, theses and discussions that form the content of this paper sprang from a genuine collective work of both authors. Since he wrote down the whole formal part of the paper which presents the core of our solution, Mathieu Vidal’s name features in first position.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Vidal, M., Perrin, D. A default-free solution to the imperfective paradox. Synthese 196, 273–297 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1474-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1474-0

Keywords

Navigation