Skip to main content
Log in

Emotional sharing and the extended mind

  • S.I.: Groups
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This article investigates the relationship between emotional sharing and the extended mind thesis. We argue that shared emotions are socially extended emotions that involve a specific type of constitutive integration between the participating individuals’ emotional experiences. We start by distinguishing two claims, the Environmentally Extended Emotion Thesis and the Socially Extended Emotion Thesis (Sect. 1). We then critically discuss some recent influential proposals about the nature of shared emotions (Sect. 2). Finally, in Sect. 3, we motivate two conditions that an account of shared emotions ought to accommodate: (i) Reciprocal Other-awareness and (ii) Integration. Consideration of (ii) and discussion of relational accounts of joint attention lead us to the proposal that a construal of socially extended emotions in terms of a constitutive integration of the participating individuals’ experiences is more promising than proposals that simply appeal to various forms of social situatedness, embeddedness, or scaffolding.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. First-, second- and third-wave construals are typically presented if not as exclusive at least as substitutive accounts (cf. Menary 2007, 2010).

  2. For an internalist criticism of the extended consciousness claim, see Horgan and Kriegel (2008).

  3. As this list makes evident, any comprehensive investigation of the Extended Emotion Thesis would have to consider a whole series of interrelated phenomena. Compare, for instance, emotions that are merely triggered or enhanced by social factors with emotions that are more robustly structured by social scaffolding. Clearly, a case where my distress is enhanced by the distress of five other people in a waiting room, who also missed their transatlantic flight, must be distinguished from the case where one feels embarrassment as the result of unwanted social attention. The latter must on its part be distinguished from a consideration of the ‘enculturation’ of many of our emotions, such as shame, guilt, or embarrassment (Parkinson et al. 2005; Cole et al. 2006). Whereas, say, embarrassment qua intrinsically social emotion might be constitutively dependent upon the existence of a concrete social relation, contrition or patriotism might be felt in the absence of concrete others, even if their formation and acquisition are constitutively dependent upon specific socio-cultural configurations (Tracy et al. 2007).

  4. For a similar distinction, see Krueger (2014).

  5. A few noticeable exceptions include Krueger (2014), Slaby (2014) and Stephan et al. (2014). However, as we shall see, these proposals exhibit some shortcomings when it comes to specifying the precise criteria for social extension.

  6. To be sure, there are a number of other contemporary authors who have engaged in thorough analyses of emotional sharing. First and foremost, one should mention here Gilbert (2002, 2014) and Salmela (2012, 2014; Salmela and Nagatsu 2016a, b). Concerning Gilbert, as shall become clear in the following, our account significantly diverges from her normativist one. For a more detailed criticism of Gilbert’s account of emotional sharing, see Szanto forthcoming. As for Salmela, and this will become clearer below (Sect. 3), we consider our account complementary to his.

  7. See also Schmid (forthcoming). Incidentally, we are not convinced that this view is correctly ascribed to Scheler. For a different interpretation of the Scheler quote, see Zahavi (2014, p. 245) and Krebs (2015, pp. 112–124).

  8. By ‘mutual awareness of sharing’ we mean that the fact of sharing an experience is mutually manifest or ‘out in the open’ for the involved subjects. Such mutual manifestation might be established, for example, by a “sharing look” (Carpenter and Liebal 2011). Mutual awareness of sharing differs from having common knowledge about the shared experience, if one understands common knowledge as essentially involving iterative epistemic states (following Schiffer 1972 and, on one interpretation of his account, Lewis 1969).

  9. This relational approach stands in contrast to the reductionist approach advocated by Peacocke (2005). According to Peacocke, it would be possible to characterize each subject’s psychological state in joint attention independently of the fact that she is co-attending with someone else, by appealing to what he terms ascriptive interpersonal self-consciousness, i.e., “awareness that one features, oneself, in someone else’s consciousness” (Peacocke 2014, p. 2). The contrast between Peacocke’s and Campbell’s accounts of joint attention is rooted in the contrast between a representationalist and a relationalist view of perceptual experience. It is worth noting that in spite of their contrasting accounts of joint attention, both Peacocke and Campbell concur in thinking of joint attention as more primitive than common knowledge (see previous footnote) (Campbell 2005, p. 295; Peacocke 2005, p. 299), and as a personal-level phenomenon (Campbell 2011, p. 416; Peacocke 2005, p. 301).

  10. One of the supporting ideas of Campbell’s account of joint attention is that unless we think of the latter in relational terms, as a primitive relation, we would have a hard time making sense of the idea that subjects can be engaged in it without entertaining states of implausible complexity. A further motivation is a relational, acquaintance-based view of perceptual experience (of which the relational approach to joint attention is an extension, see Campbell 2002). For a more detailed discussion of Campbell’s relational approach to joint attention, vis-à-vis other approaches to it, see León (2016).

  11. To be clear, the idea here is not that all instances of joint attention involve an affective component, but that they often do (as highlighted by developmental research, see Hobson 2002).

  12. Notice that there is nothing in this requirement that rules out mistakes. I might believe that others are feeling like me and that we are having a shared emotion, but be mistaken about what they feel, and consequently be mistaken about there actually being a shared emotion. Other possible mistakes include what might be called ‘shared emotions-in-the-vat scenarios’, or various real-life cases of, say, solitary terrorist perpetrators, who, due to some psycho-pathological or ideological delusions, affectively identify with an imaginary group of collaborators or fellow travelers (or ‘fellow-feelers’).

  13. This is not to rule out that affective mimicry may be concomitantly present in shared emotions. Indeed, there might be good empirical reasons to think that processes of interpersonal synchronization and attunement greatly facilitate emotional integration and interpersonal identification in cases of shared emotions involving the co-presence of the participating individuals (see Hatfield et al. 2014; Salmela and Nagatsu 2016a, b). Moreover, we concede that affective mimicry and emotional contagion may be genetic or developmental precursors to shared emotions. And notice that also classical phenomenologists such as Scheler (2008), Walther (1923) or Stein (1922) would readily accept this. But our point is that processes of affective mimicry and emotional contagion do not constitute a necessary requirement for and certainly do not in and of themselves amount to emotional sharing.

  14. One consequently has to allow for a certain continuum in the degrees of sharedness, as also suggested by other authors (Salmela 2012, 2014; Salmela and Nagatsu 2016a, b).

  15. What about the case of a consenting sadomasochist couple in which both parties gain pleasure from their interaction and co-regulate their pleasure, even if they draw pleasure from opposite actions within their interaction? One way of marking the difference between this case and the rapist case is by saying that emotional convergence, understood as an overarching integration of complementary emotional experiences, is not foreclosed in the former case. (Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for pressing this point).

  16. Salmela and Nagatsu talk about “mutual awareness” of shared emotional appraisal and affective experience among the participants in a shared emotion (Salmela and Nagatsu 2016a, p. 9; Salmela and Nagatsu 2016b, p. 36, 40), but leave the notion of mutual awareness unspecified. Likewise, as previously suggested, their reference to processes of interpersonal affective synchrony differs from what we mean by emotional integration (see above footnote 13).

References

  • Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (2008). The bounds of cognition. London: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baron-Cohen, S. (1993). From attention-goal psychology to belief-desire psychology. In S. Baron-Cohen, H. Tager-Flusberg, & D. Cohen (Eds.), Understanding other minds: Perspectives from autism (pp. 59–82). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bruner, J. (1977). Early social interaction and language acquisition. In H. R. Schaffer (Ed.), Studies in mother-infant interaction (pp. 271–289). New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, J. (2002). Reference and Consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, J. (2005). Joint attention and common knowledge. In N. Eilan, C. Hoerl, T. McCormack, & J. Roessler (Eds.), Joint attention: Communication and other minds. Issues in philosophy and psychology (pp. 287–297). New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Campbell, J. (2011). An object-dependent perspective on joint attention. In A. Seemann (Ed.), Joint attention: New developments in psychology, philosophy of mind, and social neuroscience (pp. 415–430). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carpenter, M., & Liebal, K. (2011). Joint attention, communication, and knowing together in infancy. In A. Seemann (Ed.), Joint attention: New developments in psychology, philosophy of mind, and social neuroscience (pp. 159–181). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cash, M. (2013). Cognition without borders: “Third wave” socially distributed cognition and relational autonomy. Cognitive Systems Research, 25–26, 61–71.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carter, A. J., Gordon, E. C., & Palermos, O. S. (2016). Extended emotion. Philosophical Psychology, 29(2), 198–217.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2008). Supersizing the mind. Embodiment, action and cognitive extension. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Clark, A. (2009). Spreading the joy? Why the machinery of consciousness is (probably) still in the head. Mind, 118(472), 963–993.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2010). Coupling, constitution and the cognitive kind. A reply to Adams and Aizawa. In R. Menary (Ed.), The extended mind (pp. 81–100). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58(1), 7–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cole, P. M., Tamang, B. L., & Shrestha, S. (2006). Cultural variations in the socialization of young children’s anger and shame. Child Development, 77(5), 1237–1251.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cole, P. M., Tamang, B. L., & Shrestha, S. (2006). Cultural variations in the socialization of young children’s anger and shame. Child Development, 77(5), 1237–1251.

    Google Scholar 

  • Colombetti, G. (2014). The feeling body. Affective science meets the enactive mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Colombetti, G., & Krueger, J. (2015). Scaffoldings of the affective mind. Philosophical Psychology, 28(8), 1157–1176.

    Google Scholar 

  • Colombetti, G., & Roberts, T. (2015). Extending the extended mind: The case for extended affectivity. Philosophical Studies, 172(5), 1243–1263.

    Google Scholar 

  • Damasio, A. (1994). Descartes’ error. emotion, reason, and the human brain. London: Penguin.

  • De Jaegher, H. (2013). Rigid and fluid interactions with institutions. Cognitive Systems Research, 25(25–26), 19–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Rivera, J., & Páez, D. (2007). Emotional climate, human security, and cultures of peace. Journal of Social Issues, 63(2), 233–253.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eilan, N. (forthcoming). Joint attention and the second person. http://www2.warwick.ac.uk/fac/soc/philosophy/people/eilan/jasphum.pdf. Accessed 28 March 2016.

  • Gallagher, S. (2013). The socially extended mind. Cognitive Systems Research, 25–26, 4–12.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S., & Crisafi, A. (2009). Mental institutions. Topoi, 28(1), 45–51.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, M. (2002). Collective guilt and collective guilt feelings. The Journal of Ethics, 6(2), 115–143.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, M. (2014). How we feel: Understanding everyday collective emotion ascription. In C. von Scheve & M. Salmela (Eds.), Collective emotions (pp. 17–31). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P. E., & Scarantino, A. (2009). Emotions in the wild: The situated perspective on emotion. In P. Robbins & M. Aydede (Eds.), The Cambridge handbook of situated cognition (pp. 437–453). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gross, J. J. (2002). Emotion regulation: Affective, cognitive, and social consequences. Psychophysiology, 39(3), 281–291.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hatfield, E., Carpenter, M., & Rapson, R. L. (2014). Emotional contagion as a precursor to collective emotion. In C. von Scheve & M. Salmela (Eds.), Collective emotions (pp. 108–122). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Helm, B. W. (2008). Plural agents. Noûs, 42(1), 17–49.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobson, R. P. (1993). Autism and the development of mind. Hove: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobson, R. P. (2002). The cradle of thought. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hobson, R. P. (2005). What puts the jointness into joint attention? In N. Eilan, C. Hoerl, T. McCormack, & J. Roessler (Eds.), Joint attention: Communication and other minds. Issues in philosophy and psychology (pp. 185–204). New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Hobson, R. P., & Hobson, J. (2011). Joint attention or joint engagement? Insights from autism. In A. Seemann (Ed.), Joint attention: New developments in psychology, philosophy of mind, and social neuroscience (pp. 115–136). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horgan, T., & Kriegel, U. (2008). Phenomenal intentionality meets the extended mind. The Monist, 91(2), 347–373.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huebner, B. (2011). Genuinely collective emotions. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 1(1), 89–118.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1976). Ideen zu einer reinen Phänomenologie und phänomenologischen Philosophie. Erstes Buch: Allgemeine Einführung in die reine Phänomenologie. In K. Schuhmann (Ed.), Husserliana 3 (pp. 1–2). Den Haag: Martinus Nijhoff.

  • Kagan, A., & Lassiter, C. (2013). The coupling-constitution fallacy: Much ado about nothing. Pragmatics & Cognition, 21(1), 178–192.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kiverstein, J., & Farina, M. (2012). Do sensory substitution devices extend the conscious mind? In F. Paglieri (Ed.), Consciousness in interaction: The role of the natural and social context in shaping consciousness (pp. 19–40). Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirchhoff, M. D. (2012). Extended cognition and fixed properties: Steps to a third-wave version of extended cognition. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 11(2), 287–308.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krebs, A. (2015). Zwischen Ich und Du. Eine dialogische Philosophie der Liebe. Berlin: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kriegel, U. (2009). Subjective consciousness: A self-representational theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krueger, J. (2011). Extended cognition and the space of social interaction. Consciousness and Cognition, 20(3), 643–657.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krueger, J. (2013). Merleau-Ponty on shared emotions and the joint ownership thesis. Continental Philosophy Review, 46(4), 509–531.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krueger, J. (2014). Varieties of extended emotions. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 13(4), 533–555.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krueger, J. (2016). The affective ‘We’: Self-regulation and shared emotions. In T. Szanto & D. Moran (Eds.), The phenomenology of sociality: Discovering the ‘We’ (pp. 263–277). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krueger, J., & Szanto, T. (2006). Extended emotions. Philosophy. Compass, 11(12), 863–878.

    Google Scholar 

  • León, F. (2016). Shared experiences and other minds. Ph.D. thesis, Faculty of Humanities, University of Copenhagen.

  • León, F., & Zahavi, D. (2016). Phenomenology of experiential sharing: The contribution of Schutz and Walther. In A. Salice & H. B. Schmid (Eds.), The phenomenological approach to social reality: History, concepts, problems (pp. 219–234). Cham: Springer International Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. K. (1969). Convention. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loughlin, V. (2013). Sketch this: Extended mind and consciousness extension. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 12(1), 41–50.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menary, R. (2007). Cognitive integration: Mind and cognition unbounded: Attacking the bounds of cognition. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menary, R. (2010). Cognitive integration and the extended mind. In R. Menary (Ed.), The extended mind (pp. 227–243). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1964). The primacy of perception. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moll, H. (2012). Von der Teilnahme an gemeinsamer Aufmerksamkeit zum Begriff von Perspektiven: Stufen einer Entwicklung. In P. Stekeler-Weithofer (Ed.), Wittgenstein: Philosophie und Wissenschaft (pp. 251–267). Hamburg: Felix Meiner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moll, H., & Meltzoff, A. (2011). Joint attention as the fundamental basis of understanding perspectives. In A. Seemann (Ed.), Joint attention: New developments in psychology, philosophy of mind and social neuroscience (pp. 393–413). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neisser, U. (1976). Cognition and reality. San Francisco: W.H. Freeman and Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parkinson, B., Fischer, A. H., & Manstead, A. S. R. (2005). Emotion in social relations. Cultural, group, and interpersonal processes. New York: Psychology Press.

  • Peacocke, C. (2005). Joint attention: Its nature, reflexivity and relation to common knowledge. In N. Eilan, C. Hoerl, T. McCormack, & J. Roessler (Eds.), Joint attention: Communication and other minds. Issues in philosophy and psychology (pp. 287–297). New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Peacocke, C. (2014). Interpersonal self-consciousness. Philosophical Studies, 170(1), 1–24.

  • Reddy, V. (2008). How infants know minds. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, R. C. (2003). The emotions. An essay in aid of moral psychology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Roberts, T. (2015). Extending emotional consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 22(3–4), 108–128.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands, M. (2003). Externalism: Putting mind and world back together again. Chesham: Acumen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands, M. (2010). The new sciences of the mind. From extended mind to embodied phenomenology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands, M. (2015). Consciousness unbound. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 22(3–4), 34–51.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmela, M. (2012). Shared emotions. Philosophical Explorations, 15(1), 33–46.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmela, M. (2014). The functions of collective emotions in social groups. In A. Konzelmann Ziv & H. B. Schmid (Eds.), Institutions, emotions, and group agents (pp. 159–176). Dordrecht: Springer.

  • Salmela, M., & Nagatsu, M. (2016a). How does it really Feel to act together? Shared emotions and the phenomenology of we-agency. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 1–22.

  • Salmela, M., & Nagatsu, M. (2016b). Collective emotions and joint action. Journal of Social Ontology, 2(1), 33–57.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scheler, M. (2008). The nature of sympathy. London: Transaction Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scherer, K. R. (2005). What are emotions? And how can they be measured? Social Science Information, 44(4), 695–729.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schiffer, S. (1972). Meaning. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmid, H. B. (2005). Wir-Intentionalität: Kritik des ontologischen Individualismus und Rekonstruktion der Gemeinschaft. Freiburg: Karl Alber.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmid, H. B. (2009). Plural action. Essays in philosophy and social science. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmid, H. B. (2014). The feeling of being a group: Corporate emotions and collective consciousness. In C. v Scheve & M. Salmela (Eds.), Collective emotions. Perspectives from psychology, and sociology (pp. 3–16). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Schmid, H. B. (2014b). Plural self-awareness. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 13(7), 7–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmid, H. B. (forthcoming). Collective emotions: Phenomenology, ontology, and ideology what should we learn from Max Scheler’s war propaganda? Max Scheler Jahrbuch. https://www.academia.edu/17469415/Collective_Emotions_phenomenology_Ontology_and_Ideo-logy.

  • Schutz, A. (1967). The phenomenology of the social world. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slaby, J. (2014). Emotions and the extended mind. In C. v Scheve & M. Salmela (Eds.), Collective emotions. Perspectives from psychology, and sociology (pp. 32–46). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Stein, E. (1922). Beiträge zur philosophischen Begründung der Psychologie und der Geisteswis-senschaften. Edith Stein Gesamtausgabe, Vol. 6. Wien: Herder 2010.

  • Stephan, A., Walter, S., & Wilutzky, W. (2014). Emotions beyond brain and body. Philosophical Psychology, 27(1), 65–81.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. (2010). Minds: extended or scaffolded? Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 9(4), 465–481.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sullivan, G. B. (2015). Collective emotions. Social and Personality Psychology Compass, 9(8), 383–393.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sutton, J. (2010). Exograms and interdisciplinarity: History, the extended mind and the civilizing process. In R. Menary (Ed.), The extended mind (pp. 189–225). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Szanto, T. (2015). Collective emotions, normativity and empathy: A Steinian account. Human Studies, 38(4), 503–527.

    Google Scholar 

  • Szanto, T. (2016). Collectivizing persons and personifying collectives: Reassessing scheler on group personhood. In T. Szanto & D. Moran (Eds.), Phenomenology of sociality: Discovering the We (pp. 296–312). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Szanto, T. (2016). Husserl on collective intentionality. In A. Salice & H. B. Schmid (Eds.), The phenomenological approach to social reality: History, concepts, problems (pp. 145–172). Cham: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Szanto, T. (forthcoming). The phenomenology of shared emotions: Reassessing Gerda Walther. In S. Luft & R. Hagengruber (Eds.), Women phenomenologists on social ontology. Dordrecht: Springer.

  • Tollefsen, D. P. (2006). From extended mind to collective mind. Cognitive Systems Research, 7(2/3), 140–150.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M. (1995). Joint attention as social cognition. In C. Moore & P. Dunham (Eds.), Joint attention: Its origins and role in development (pp. 103–130). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M. (2003). The Key is Social Cognition. In D. Gentner & S. Goldin-Meadow (Eds.), Language in mind. Advances in the study of language and thought (pp. 47–57). Cambridge: MIT Press.

  • Tomasello, M., Carpenter, M., Call, J., Behne, T., & Moll, H. (2005). Understanding and sharing intentions: The origins of cultural cognition. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 28, 675–735.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tracy, J. L., Robins, R. W., & Tangney, J. P. (Eds.). (2007). The self-conscious emotions: Theory and research. New York: Guilford Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Scheve, C., & Salmela, M. (Eds.). (2014). Collective emotions. Perspectives from psychology, and sociology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walther, G. (1923). Zur Ontologie der sozialen Gemeinschaften. Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische Forschung, 6, 1–158.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ward, D. (2012). Enjoying the spread: Conscious externalism reconsidered. Mind, 121(483), 731–751.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, M. (2015). Extended consciousness: An interim report. The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 53(S1), 155–175.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, R. A. (2004). Boundaries of the mind: The individual in the fragile sciences-cognition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, R. A., & Clark, A. (2009). How to situate cognition: Letting nature take its course. In P. Robbins & M. Aydede (Eds.), The Cambridge handbook of situated cognition (pp. 55–77). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (1999). Self-awareness and alterity: A phenomenological investigation. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2005). Subjectivity and selfhood: Investigating the first-person perspective. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2014). Self and other: Exploring subjectivity, empathy, and shame. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2015). You, Me, and We: The sharing of emotional experiences. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 22(1–2), 84–101.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2016). Second-person engagement, self-alienation, and group-identification. Topoi,. doi:10.1007/s11245-016-9444-6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D., & Kriegel, U. (2016). For-me-ness: What it is and what it is not”. In D. O. Dahlstrom, A. Elpidorou, & W. Hopp (Eds.), Philosophy of mind and phenomenology: Conceptual and empirical approaches (pp. 36–53). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D., & Rochat, Ph. (2015). Empathy \(\ne \) sharing: Perspectives from phenomenology and developmental psychology. Consciousness and Cognition, 36, 543–553.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D., & Salice, A. (2017). Phenomenology of the we: Stein, Walther, Gurwitsch. In J. Kiverstein (Ed.), The Routledge handbook of philosophy of the social mind (pp. 515–527). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zawidski, T. W. (2012). Trans-human cognitive enhancement, phenomenal consciousness and the extended mind. International Journal of Machine Consciousness, 4(1), 215–227.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The authors thank two anonymous reviewers for Synthese, for helpful comments on previous versions of this paper. Felipe León gratefully acknowledges the support from the University of Copenhagen’s Excellence Program for Interdisciplinary Research to the 2013–2016 project “The disrupted ‘we’: Shared intentionality and its psychopathological distortions”. Thomas Szanto’s work on this paper was funded by his European Union (EU) Horizon-2020 Marie Skłodowska-Curie Individual Fellowship project SHARE (655067): Shared Emotions, Group Membership, and Empathy.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Felipe León.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

León, F., Szanto, T. & Zahavi, D. Emotional sharing and the extended mind. Synthese 196, 4847–4867 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1351-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1351-x

Keywords

Navigation