Skip to main content
Log in

Betwixt and between: the enculturated predictive processing approach to cognition

  • S.I.: Predictive Brains
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Many of our cognitive capacities are the result of enculturation. Enculturation is the temporally extended transformative acquisition of cognitive practices in the cognitive niche. Cognitive practices are embodied and normatively constrained ways to interact with epistemic resources in the cognitive niche in order to complete a cognitive task. The emerging predictive processing perspective offers new functional principles and conceptual tools to account for the cerebral and extra-cerebral bodily components that give rise to cognitive practices. According to this emerging perspective, many cases of perception, action, and cognition are realized by the on-going minimization of prediction error. Predictive processing provides us with a mechanistic perspective that helps investigate the functional details of the acquisition of cognitive practices. The argument of this paper is that research on enculturation and recent work on predictive processing are complementary. The main reason is that predictive processing operates at a sub-personal level and on a physiological time scale of explanation only. A complete account of enculturated cognition needs to take additional levels and temporal scales of explanation into account. This complementarity assumption leads to a new framework—enculturated predictive processing—that operates on multiple levels and temporal scales for the explanation of the enculturated predictive acquisition of cognitive practices. Enculturated predictive processing is committed to explanatory pluralism. That is, it subscribes to the idea that we need multiple perspectives and explanatory strategies to account for the complexity of enculturation. The upshot is that predictive processing needs to be complemented by additional considerations and conceptual tools to realize its full explanatory potential.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Cognitive practices are specific means for the completion of cognitive tasks. The most important examples include reading, writing, and mathematical cognition. In many cases, they are involved in the enactment of more general cognitive capacities, such as problem solving, reasoning, or remembering.

  2. I will use the notions of embodied action and bodily manipulation interchangeably.

  3. It should be noted that the present treatment is markedly different from previous anthropological accounts of enculturation. For example, Shimahara (1970) operates mainly at a behavioral level and defines enculturation as a dynamical process of “cultural conditioning and reflective responses to the cultural environment” (Shimahara 1970, p. 148). In contrast to the present account of enculturation, this view is mainly interested in the ontogenetic change of behavioral patterns associated with culture in the broadest sense of the term. It does not speak to the neuronal, bodily, and environmental conditions of a specific class of cognitive processes, which is the purpose of the enculturation account presented here. Similarly, Brown, Collins, and Duguid’s (1989) view of enculturation is thought to apply to “learning to speak, read, and write, or becoming school children, office workers, researchers, and so on” (Brown et al. 1989, pp. 33–34). Furthermore, their account of enculturation rests on a presupposed distinction between “authentic” and “school activities”, the latter being considered as insufficient for the acquisition of cognitive skills that are relevant in the real world outside educational contexts. This distinction seems to be arbitrary, because it is intelligible that there are many cases where it would hardly be possible to attribute specific components of enculturation to well-defined socio-cultural contexts in which they are realized. For this reason, the present account of enculturation is a distance to the view that this distinction helps elucidate the complex process of enculturation. In sum, although the very notion of ‘enculturation’ has been frequently employed in cultural anthropology, the present account does not share any central commitments with these earlier views.

  4. In the present treatment, I am not concerned with the metaphysical consequences that may or may not be derived from the distinction of personal and sub-personal levels of explanation. Rather, the consideration of levels of explanation serves to specify the epistemic stances that are relevant for EPP.

  5. This account is markedly different from recent attempts to explain the phenomenal experience of time and temporal order in terms of PP (Friston and Buzsáki 2016; Hohwy et al. 2016; Kiebel et al. 2008). These attempts are not interested in the temporal resolution of explanations in terms of PP per se, but rather in a PP style explanation of the properties of temporality that characterize our phenomenology.

  6. For a discussion of effective connectivity and its relation to PP, see Clark (2016a, pp. 146–150; 2013b).

  7. An additional example of enculturated cognition—with its emphasis on the indispensable functional role on the bodily manipulation of symbols and other tokens of representational systems—is Wells’s (2002) interpretation of Turing’s (1936) seminal paper on computable numbers. According to Turing, computing machines—which are now known as Turing machines—move along a tape that is constituted by squares, each of which is the vehicle of a symbol (0 or 1): “Computing is normally done by writing certain symbols on paper. We may suppose this paper is divided into squares like a child’s arithmetic book. In elementary arithmetic the two-dimensional character of the paper is sometimes used. But such a use is avoidable, and I think that it will be agreed that the two-dimensional character of paper is no essential of computation. I assume then that the computation is carried out on one-dimensional paper, i.e. on a tape divided into squares” (Turing 1936, p. 249). This suggests that computing machines can be understood as a model of the human computation of numbers. An important consequence is that the cognitivist interpretation of Turing’s work underestimates the importance of the interaction between the component parts of the machine and the tape (Dutilh Novaes 2012; Wells 2002). Turing’s computing machines bear thus a striking resemblance to accounts of arithmetic that emphasize the integration of the brain, the rest of the body, and the cognitive niche (Dutilh Novaes 2013; Menary 2015a). Many thanks to an anonymous reviewer for the suggestion to take this example into account.

  8. John Dewey’s (1896, pp. 358–359) account of looking—understood as an active and embodied process—is certainly an ancestor of the approach to eye movements suggested here: “Upon analysis, we find that we begin not with a sensory stimulus, but with a sensorimotor coordination, the optical-ocular, and that in a certain sense it is the movement of body, head and eye muscles determining the quality of what is experienced. In other words, the real beginning is with the act of seeing; it is looking, and not a Sensation of light.”

  9. This distinction between the extended cognition and the CI view of brain-body-niche interactions becomes more obvious when we take the distinct principles into account to which they subscribe: “Philosophers working within the extended mind framework diverge on whether they seek to emphasize the similarities or the differences between cognitive processes involving or not involving external devices. Those who emphasize the similarities typically endorse the so-called ‘parity principle’ and concentrate on the metaphysical question of the boundaries of the mind. By contrast, those who emphasize the differences rely the so-called ‘complementarity principle’, and seek to investigate the transformative power of engaging with external devices for human cognition [...]” (Dutilh Novaes 2013, p. 47). EPP is fully committed to the complementarity principle.

  10. I owe this point to an anonymous reviewer.

References

  • Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (2001). The bounds of cognition. Philosophical Psychology, 14(1), 43–64.

    Google Scholar 

  • Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (2010). The value of cognitivism in thinking about extended cognition. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 9(4), 579–603. doi:10.1007/s11097-010-9184-9.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, M. L. (2010). Neural reuse: A fundamental organizational principle of the brain. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 33(4), 245–266.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, M. L. (2015). After phrenology: Neural reuse and the interactive brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, M. L. (2016). Neural reuse in the organization and development of the brain. Developmental Medicine and Child Neurology, 58(4), 3–6.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, M. L., & Chemero, A. (2013). The problem with brain GUTs: Conflation of different senses of “prediction” threatens metaphysical disaster. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 36(3), 204–205.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, M. L., & Finlay, B. L. (2014). Allocating structure to function: The strong links between neuroplasticity and natural selection. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience. doi:10.3389/fnhum.2013.00918.

  • Anderson, M. L., Richardson, M. J., & Chemero, A. (2012). Eroding the boundaries of cognition: Implications of embodiment. Topics in Cognitive Science, 4(4), 717–730.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ansari, D. (2012). Culture and education: New frontiers in brain plasticity. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 16(2), 93–95. doi:10.1016/j.tics.2011.11.016.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ansari, D. (2015). Mind, brain, and education: A discussion of practical, conceptual, and ethical issues. In J. Clauen & N. Levy (Eds.), Handbook of neuroethics (pp. 1703–1719). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baron-Cohen, S., & Belmonte, M. K. (2005). Autism: A window onto the development of the social and the analytic brain. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 28(1), 109–126.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. (2009). Explanation: Mechanism, modularity, and situated cognition. In P. Robbins & M. Aydede (Eds.), The Cambridge handbook of situated cognition (pp. 155–170). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bedo, N., Ribary, U., Ward, L. M., & Valdes-Sosa, P. A. (2014). Fast dynamics of cortical functional and effective connectivity during word reading. PLoS One, 9(2), 1–13.

  • Ben-Shachar, M., Dougherty, R. F., Deutsch, G. K., & Wandell, B. A. (2011). The development of cortical sensitivity to visual word forms. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 23(9), 2387–2399.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R., Richerson, P. J., & Henrich, J. (2011). The cultural niche: Why social learning is essential for human adaptation. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 108(Supplement 2), 10918–10925.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brem, S., Bach, S., Kucian, K., Guttorm, T. K., Martin, E., Lyytinen, H., et al. (2010). Brain sensitivity to print emerges when children learn letter-speech sound correspondences. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 107(17), 7939–7944.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brock, J., & Caruana, N. (2014). Reading for sound and reading for meaning in autism: Frith and Snowling (1983) revisited. In J. Arciuli & J. Brock (Eds.), Communication in autism: Trends in language acquisition research (pp. 125–145). Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, J. S., Collins, A., & Duguid, P. (1989). Situated cognition and the culture of learning. Educational Researcher, 18(1), 32–42.

    Google Scholar 

  • Casey, B. J., Tottenham, N., Liston, C., & Durston, S. (2005). Imaging the developing brain: What have we learned about cognitive development? Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 9(3), 104–110.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (1997). Being there: Putting brain, body, and world together again (2nd ed.). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2006). Language, embodiment, and the cognitive niche. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 10(8), 370–374.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2008). Supersizing the mind: Embodiment, action, and cognitive extension. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2013a). Whatever next? Predictive brains, situated agents, and the future of cognitive science. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 36(03), 181–204. doi:10.1017/S0140525X12000477.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2013b). The many faces of precision (Replies to commentaries on “Whatever next? Neural prediction, situated agents, and the future of cognitive science”). Frontiers in Psychology. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00270.

  • Clark, A. (2014). Mindware: An introduction to the philosophy of cognitive science (2nd ed.). Oxford, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2015). Embodied prediction. In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds.), Open MIND (pp. 1–21). Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2016a). Surfing uncertainty: Prediction, action, and the embodied mind. Oxford, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2016b). Busting out: Predictive brains, embodied minds, and the puzzle of the evidentiary veil. Noûs.

  • Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58(1), 7–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, M. X. (2011). It’s about time. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 5, 1–15.

  • Colombo, M., & Wright, C. (2017). Explanatory pluralism: An unrewarding prediction error for free energy theorists. Brain and Cognition, 112, 3–12.

  • Craver, C., & Bechtel, W. (2006). Mechanism. In S. Sarkar & J. Pfeifer (Eds.), The philosophy of science: An encyclopedia (pp. 469–478). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Csibra, G., & Gergely, G. (2009). Natural pedagogy. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 13(4), 148–153.

    Google Scholar 

  • Csibra, G., & Gergely, G. (2011). Natural pedagogy as evolutionary adaptation. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 366(1567), 1149–1157.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dale, R. (2008). The possibility of a pluralist cognitive science. Journal of Experimental & Theoretical Artificial Intelligence, 20(3), 155–179.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dale, R., Dietrich, E., & Chemero, A. (2009). Explanatory pluralism in cognitive science. Cognitive Science, 33(5), 739–742.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Bruin, L., & Michael, J. (2017). Prediction error minimization: Implications for embodied cognition and the extended mind hypothesis. Brain and Cognition, 112, 58–63.

  • Dehaene, S. (2005). Evolution of human cortical circuits for reading and arithmetic: The “neuronal recycling” hypothesis. In S. Dehaene, J.-R. Duhamel, M. D. Hauser, & G. Rizzolatti (Eds.), From monkey brain to human brain. A Fyssen Foundation symposium (pp. 133–157). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dehaene, S. (2010). Reading in the brain: The new science of how we read. New York: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dehaene, S., & Cohen, L. (2011). The unique role of the visual word form area in reading. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 15(6), 254–262.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dehaene, S., Cohen, L., Sigman, M., & Vinckier, F. (2005). The neural code for written words: A proposal. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 9(7), 335–341.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dehaene, S., Pegado, F., Braga, L. W., Ventura, P., Filho, G. N., Jobert, A., et al. (2010). How learning to read changes the cortical networks for vision and language. Science, 330(6009), 1359–1364.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Jong, H. L. (2001). Introduction: A symposium on explanatory pluralism. Theory & Psychology, 11(6), 731–735.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1969). Content and consciousness. London, NY: Routledge & K. Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, J. (1896). The reflex arc concept in psychology. Psychological Review, 3(4), 357–370.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dounskaia, N., van Gemmert, A. W. A., & Stelmach, G. E. (2000). Interjoint coordination during handwriting-like movements. Experimental Brain Research, 135(1), 127–140.

    Google Scholar 

  • Downey, G., & Lende, D. H. (2012). Neuroanthropology and the encultured brain. In D. H. Lende & G. Downey (Eds.), The encultured brain: An introduction to neuroanthropology (pp. 23–65). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Drayson, Z. (2012). The uses and abuses of the personal/subpersonal distinction. Philosophical Perspectives, 26(1), 1–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • Drayson, Z. (2014). The personal/subpersonal distinction. Philosophy Compass, 9(5), 338–346.

    Google Scholar 

  • DSM-5 American Psychiatric Association. (2013). Diagnostic and statistical manual of mental disorders (5th ed.). Arlington: American Psychiatric Publishing.

  • Dutilh Novaes, C. (2012). Formal languages in logic: A philosophical and cognitive analysis. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dutilh Novaes, C. (2013). Mathematical reasoning and external symbolic systems. Logique & Analyse, 221, 45–65.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feldman, H., & Friston, K. J. (2010). Attention, uncertainty, and free-energy. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience. doi:10.3389/fnhum.2010.00215.

  • Fletcher, P. C., & Frith, C. D. (2009). Perceiving is believing: A Bayesian approach to explaining the positive symptoms of schizophrenia. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 10(1), 48–58.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friston, K. (2005). A theory of cortical responses. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 360(1456), 815–836.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friston, K. (2010). The free-energy principle: A unified brain theory? Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 11(2), 127–138.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friston, K., Adams, R. A., Perrinet, L., & Breakspear, M. (2012). Perceptions as hypotheses: Saccades as experiments. Frontiers in Psychology. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2012.00151.

  • Friston, K., & Buzsáki, G. (2016). The functional anatomy of time: What and when in the brain. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 20(7), 500–511.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friston, K., & Frith, C. (2015). Active inference, communication and hermeneutics. Cortex, 68, 129–143.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friston, K. J., Lawson, R., & Frith, C. D. (2013). On hyperpriors and hypopriors: Comment on Pellicano and Burr. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 17(1), 1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friston, K., Sengupta, B., & Auletta, G. (2014). Cognitive dynamics: From attractors to active inference. Proceedings of the IEEE, 102(4), 427–445.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frith, U. (1985). Beneath the surface of developmental dyslexia. In K. E. Patterson, J. C. Marshall, & M. Coltheart (Eds.), Surface dyslexia: Neuropsychological and cognitive studies of phonological reading (pp. 301–330). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frith, U. (2003). Autism: Explaining the enigma (2nd ed.). Malden, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frith, U., & Snowling, M. (1983). Reading for meaning and reading for sound in autistic and dyslexic children. British Journal of Developmental Psychology, 1(4), 329–342.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaillard, R., Naccache, L., Pinel, P., Clémenceau, S., Volle, E., Hasboun, D., et al. (2006). Direct intracranial, fMRI, and lesion evidence for the causal role of left inferotemporal cortex in reading. Neuron, 50(2), 191–204.

    Google Scholar 

  • Happé, F. G. E. (1997). Central coherence and theory of mind in autism: Reading homographs in context. British Journal of Developmental Psychology, 15(1), 1–12.

    Google Scholar 

  • Happé, F., & Frith, U. (2006). The weak coherence account: Detail-focused cognitive style in autism spectrum disorders. Journal of Autism and Developmental Disorders, 36(1), 5–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Happé, F., & Frith, U. (2009). The beautiful otherness of the autistic mind. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 364(1522), 1345–1350.

    Google Scholar 

  • Happé, F., Ronald, A., & Plomin, R. (2006). Time to give up on a single explanation for autism. Nature Neuroscience, 9(10), 1218–1220.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harkness, D. L. (2015). From explanatory ambition to explanatory power: A commentary on Jakob Hohwy. In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds.), Open MIND (pp. 1–9). Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hellendoorn, A., Wijnroks, L., & Leeseman, P. P. (2015). Unraveling the nature of autism: Finding order amid change. Frontiers in Psychology, 6, 1–16.

  • Heyes, C. (2012). Grist and mills: On the cultural origins of cultural learning. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 367(1599), 2181–2191.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hohwy, J. (2011). Phenomenal variability and introspective reliability. Mind & Language, 26(3), 261–286. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0017.2011.01418.x.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hohwy, J. (2012). Attention and conscious perception in the hypothesis testing brain. Frontiers in Psychology. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2012.00096.

  • Hohwy, J. (2013). The predictive mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hohwy, J. (2015a). The neural organ explains the mind. In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds.) Open MIND (pp. 1–22). Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group.

  • Hohwy, J. (2015b). Prediction error minimization, mental and developmental disorder, and statistical theories of consciousness. In R. J. Gennaro (Ed.), Philosophical psychopathology. Disturbed consciousness. New essays on psychopathology and theories of consciousness (pp. 293–324). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hohwy, J. (2016). The self-evidencing brain. Noûs, 50(2), 259–285.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hohwy, J., Paton, B., & Palmer, C. (2016). Distrusting the present. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 15(3), 315–335.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hohwy, J., Roepstorff, A., & Friston, K. (2008). Predictive coding explains binocular rivalry: An epistemological review. Cognition, 108(3), 687–701.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huemer, S. V., & Mann, V. (2010). A comprehensive profile of decoding and comprehension in autism spectrum disorders. Journal of Autism and Developmental Disorders, 40(4), 485–493.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huestegge, L., Radach, R., Corbic, D., & Huestegge, S. M. (2009). Oculomotor and linguistic determinants of reading development: A longitudinal study. Vision Research, 49(24), 2948–2959.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jones, C. R. G., Happé, F., Golden, H., Marsden, A. J. S., Tregay, J., Simonoff, E., et al. (2009). Reading and arithmetic in adolescents with autism spectrum disorders: Peaks and dips in attainment. Neuropsychology, 23(6), 718–728.

    Google Scholar 

  • Joseph, H. S. S. L., & Liversedge, S. P. (2013). Children’s and adults’ on-line processing of syntactically ambiguous sentences during reading. PLoS One, 8(1), e54141.

    Google Scholar 

  • Just, M. A., Cherkassky, V. L., Keller, T. A., & Minshew, N. J. (2004). Cortical activation and synchronization during sentence comprehension in high-functioning autism: Evidence of underconnectivity. Brain, 127(8), 1811–1821.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kana, R. K., Keller, T. A., Cherkassky, V. L., Minshew, N. J., & Just, M. A. (2006). Sentence comprehension in autism: Thinking in pictures with decreased functional connectivity. Brain, 129(9), 2484–2493.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kellert, S., Longino, H., & Waters, C. K. (2006). Introduction: The pluralist stance. In C. K. Kellert, S. Longino, & C. K. Waters (Eds.), Minnesota studies in philosophy of science, vol. 19: Scientific pluralism (pp. vii–xxix). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

  • Kendal, J. R. (2011). Cultural niche construction and human learning environments: Investigating sociocultural perspectives. Biological Theory, 6(3), 241–250.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kherif, F., Josse, G., & Price, C. J. (2011). Automatic top-down processing explains common left occipito-temporal responses to visual words and objects. Cerebral Cortex, 21(1), 103–114.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kiebel, S. J., Daunizeau, J., & Friston, K. J. (2008). A hierarchy of time-scales and the brain. PLoS Computational Biology, 4(11), 1–12.

  • Kim, J. (2005). Physicalism, or something near enough. New Jersey: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kline, M. A. (2015). How to learn about teaching: An evolutionary framework for the study of teaching behavior in humans and other animals. Behavioral and Brain Sciences. doi:10.1017/S0140525X14000090.

  • Laland, K. N., & O’Brien, M. J. (2011). Cultural niche construction: An introduction. Biological Theory, 6(3), 191–202.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawson, R. P., Rees, G., & Friston, K. J. (2014). An aberrant precision account of autism. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience. doi:10.3389/fnhum.2014.00302.

  • MacKinnon, K. C., & Fuentes, A. (2012). Primate social cognition, human evolution, and niche construction: A core context for neuroanthropology. In D. H. Lende & G. Downey (Eds.), The encultured brain: An introduction to neuroanthropology (pp. 67–102). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maurer, U., Brem, S., Kranz, F., Bucher, K., Benz, R., Halder, P., et al. (2006). Coarse neural tuning for print peaks when children learn to read. NeuroImage, 33(2), 749–758.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCandliss, B. D., Cohen, L., & Dehaene, S. (2003). The visual word form area: Expertise for reading in the fusiform gyrus. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 7(7), 293–299.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menary, R. (2006). Attacking the bounds of cognition. Philosophical Psychology, 19(3), 329–344.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menary, R. (2007). Cognitive integration: Mind and cognition unbounded. Basingstoke, NY: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menary, R. (2009). Intentionality, cognitive integration and the continuity thesis. Topoi, 28(1), 31–43.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menary, R. (Ed.). (2010). The extended mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menary, R. (2010a). Cognitive integration and the extended mind. In R. Menary (Ed.), The extended mind (pp. 227–243). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menary, R. (2010b). Dimensions of mind. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 9(4), 561–578. doi:10.1007/s11097-010-9186-7.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menary, R. (2010c). The holy grail of cognitivism: A response to Adams and Aizawa. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 9(4), 605–618. doi:10.1007/s11097-010-9185-8.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menary, R. (2012). Cognitive practices and cognitive character. Philosophical Explorations, 15(2), 147–164.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menary, R. (2013a). Cognitive integration, enculturated cognition and the socially extended mind. Cognitive Systems Research, 25–26, 26–34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menary, R. (2013b). The enculturated hand. In Z. Radman (Ed.), The hand, an organ of the mind: What the manual tells the mental (pp. 561–593). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menary, R. (2014). Neural plasticity, neuronal recycling and niche construction. Mind & Language, 29(3), 286–303.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menary, R. (2015a). Mathematical cognition: A case of enculturation. In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds.), Open MIND (pp. 1–20). Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group.

  • Menary, R. (2015b). What? Now: Predictive coding and enculturation. In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds.), Open MIND. Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group.

  • Menary, R. (2016). Pragmatism and the pragmatic turn in cognitive science. In D. Engel, K. Andreas, K. Friston, & Kragic (Eds.), Where is the action? The pragmatic turn in cognitive science (pp. 219–237). Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menary, R., & Kirchhoff, M. (2014). Cognitive transformations and extended expertise. Educational Philosophy and Theory, 46(6), 610–623.

  • Metzinger, T. (2013). The myth of cognitive agency: Subpersonal thinking as a cyclically recurring loss of mental autonomy. Frontiers in Psychology, 4, 1–19.

  • Müller, R.-A., Shih, P., Keehn, B., Deyoe, J. R., Leyden, K. M., & Shukla, D. K. (2011). Underconnected, but how? A survey of functional connectivity MRI studies in autism spectrum disorders. Cerebral Cortex, 21(10), 2233–2243.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nation, K., Clarke, P., Wright, B., & Williams, C. (2006). Patterns of reading ability in children with autism spectrum disorder. Journal of Autism and Developmental Disorders, 36(7), 911–919.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newman, T. M., Macomber, D., Naples, A. J., Babitz, T., Volkmar, F., & Grigorenko, E. L. (2007). Hyperlexia in children with autism spectrum disorders. Journal of Autism and Developmental Disorders, 37(4), 760–774.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Connor, I. M., & Klein, P. D. (2004). Exploration of strategies for facilitating the reading comprehension of high-functioning students with autism spectrum disorders. Journal of Autism and Developmental Disorders, 34(2), 115–127.

    Google Scholar 

  • Odling-Smee, J., & Laland, K. N. (2011). Ecological inheritance and cultural inheritance: What are they and how do they differ? Biological Theory, 6(3), 220–230.

    Google Scholar 

  • Palmer, C. J., Paton, B., Hohwy, J., & Enticott, P. G. (2013). Movement under uncertainty: The effects of the rubber-hand illusion vary along the nonclinical autism spectrum. Neuropsychologia, 51(10), 1942–1951.

    Google Scholar 

  • Palmer, C. J., Paton, B., Kirkovski, M., Enticott, P. G., & Hohwy, J. (2015). Context sensitivity in action decreases along the autism spectrum: A predictive processing perspective. In Proceedings of the royal society B: Biological sciences, 282(1802). doi:10.1098/rspb.2014.1557.

  • Palmer, C. J., Seth, A., & Hohwy, J. (2015). The felt presence of other minds: Predictive processing, counterfactual predictions, and mentalising in autism. Consciousness and Cognition, 36, 376–389.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pellicano, E., & Burr, D. (2012). When the world becomes ‘too real’: A Bayesian explanation of autistic perception. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 16(10), 504–510.

    Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, J. G., Ogeil, R. P., & Best, C. (2009). Motor constancy and the upsizing of handwriting. Human Movement Science, 28(5), 578–587.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piccinini, G., & Craver, C. (2011). Integrating psychology and neuroscience: Functional analyses as mechanism sketches. Synthese, 183(3), 283–311.

    Google Scholar 

  • Price, C. J., & Devlin, J. T. (2003). The myth of the visual word form area. NeuroImage, 19(3), 473–481. doi:10.1016/S1053-8119(03)00084-3.

    Google Scholar 

  • Price, C. J., & Devlin, J. T. (2004). The pro and cons of labelling a left occipitotemporal region “the visual word form area”. NeuroImage, 22(1), 477–479.

    Google Scholar 

  • Price, C. J., & Devlin, J. T. (2011). The interactive account of ventral occipitotemporal contributions to reading. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 15(6), 246–253.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quattrocki, E., & Friston, K. (2014). Autism, oxytocin and interoception. Neuroscience & Biobehavioral Reviews, 47, 410–430.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rayner, K. (1998). Eye movements in reading and information processing: 20 years of research. Psychological Bulletin, 124(3), 372–422. doi:10.1037/0033-2909.124.3.372.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rayner, K. (2009). Eye movements and attention in reading, scene perception, and visual search. The Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 62(8), 1457–1506. doi:10.1080/17470210902816461.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rayner, K., Cook, A. E., Juhasz, B. J., & Frazier, L. (2006). Immediate disambiguation of lexically ambiguous words during reading: Evidence from eye movements. British Journal of Psychology, 97(4), 467–482.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rayner, K., Foorman, B. R., Perfetti, C. A., Pesetsky, D., & Seidenberg, M. S. (2001). How psychological science informs the teaching of reading. Psychological Science in the Public Interest, 2(2), 31–74. doi:10.1111/1529-1006.00004.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rayner, K., Juhasz, B. J., & Pollatsek, A. (2007). Eye movements during reading. In M. J. Snowling & C. Hulme (Eds.), Blackwell handbooks of developmental psychology. The science of reading: A handbook (pp. 79–97). Malden, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, A. (2009). Writing and script?: A very short introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands, M. (1999). The body in mind: Understanding cognitive processes. Cambridge studies in philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rupert, R. D. (2004). Challenges to the hypothesis of extended cognition. Journal of Philosophy, 101(8), 389–428.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sansosti, F. J., Was, C., Rawson, K. A., & Remaklus, B. L. (2013). Eye movements during processing of text requiring bridging inferences in adolescents with higher functioning autism spectrum disorders: A preliminary investigation. Research in Autism Spectrum Disorders, 7(12), 1535–1542.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seassau, M., Bucci, M.-P., & Paterson, K. (2013). Reading and visual search: A developmental study in normal children. PLoS One, 8(7). doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0070261.

  • Seth, A. K. (2013). Interoceptive inference, emotion, and the embodied self. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 17(11), 565–573.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seth, A. K. (2015). The cybernetic Bayesian brain: From interoceptive inference to sensorimotor contingencies. In T. Metzinger & J. M. Windt (Eds.), Open MIND (pp. 1–24). Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shimahara, N. (1970). Enculturation—A reconsideration. Current Anthropology, 11(2), 143–154.

    Google Scholar 

  • Silberman, S. (2015). Neurotribes: The legacy of autism and the future of neurodiversity. New York: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Snowling, M. J. (2000). Dyslexia (2nd ed.). Malden, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. (2003). Thought in a hostile world: The evolution of human cognition. Malden, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K. (2012). The evolved apprentice: How evolution made humans unique. The Jean Nicod lectures (Vol. 2012). Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stotz, K. (2010). Human nature and cognitive-developmental niche construction. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 9(4), 483–501. doi:10.1007/s11097-010-9178-7.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stotz, K. (2014). Extended evolutionary psychology: The importance of transgenerational developmental plasticity. Frontiers in Psychology. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00908.

  • Supekar, K., Uddin, L. Q., Khouzam, A., Phillips, J., Gaillard, W. D., Kenworthy, L. E., et al. (2013). Brain hyperconnectivity in children with autism and its links to social deficits. Cell Reports, 5(3), 738–747.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tatone, D., & Csibra, G. (2015). Learning in and about opaque worlds. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 38, 49–50.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. (2011). Living ways of sense making. Philosophy Today, 55, 114–123.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turing, A. M. (1936). On computable numbers, with an application to the Entscheidungsproblem. Proceedings of the London Mathematical Society, 42, 230–265.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turkeltaub, P. E., Gareau, L., Flowers, D. L., Zeffiro, T. A., & Eden, G. F. (2003). Development of neural mechanisms for reading. Nature Neuroscience, 6(7), 767–773.

    Google Scholar 

  • Uddin, L. Q., Supekar, K., & Menon, V. (2013). Reconceptualizing functional brain connectivity in autism from a developmental perspective. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience. doi:10.3389/fnhum.2013.00458.

  • van Atteveldt, N., & Ansari, D. (2014). How symbols transform brain function: A review in memory of Leo Blomert. Trends in Neuroscience and Education, 3(2), 44–49.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Bouwel, J., Weber, E., & de Vreese, L. (2011). Indispensibility arguments in favour of reductive explanations. Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 42(1), 33–46.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Boxtel, J. J. A., & Lu, H. (2013). A predictive coding perspective on autism spectrum disorders. Frontiers in Psychology. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2013.00019.

  • van de Cruys, S., Evers, K., van der Hallen, R., van Eylen, L., Boets, B., de-Wit, L., et al. (2014). Precise minds in uncertain worlds: Predictive coding in autism. Psychological Review, 221(4), 649–675.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vinckier, F., Dehaene, S., Jobert, A., Dubus, J. P., Sigman, M., & Cohen, L. (2007). Hierarchical coding of letter strings in the ventral stream: Dissecting the inner organization of the visual word-form system. Neuron, 55(1), 143–156.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vogel, A. C., Church, J. A., Power, J. D., Miezin, F. M., Petersen, S. E., & Schlaggar, B. L. (2013). Functional network architecture of reading-related regions across development. Brain and Language, 125(2), 231–243. doi:10.1016/j.bandl.2012.12.016.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vogel, A. C., Petersen, S. E., & Schlaggar, B. L. (2014). The VWFA: It’s not just for words anymore. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience. doi:10.3389/fnhum.2014.00088.

  • Vygotsky, L. S. (1978). Mind in society: The development of higher psychological processes. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wells, A. J. (2002). Gibson’s affordances and Turing’s theory of computation. Ecological Psychology, 14(3), 140–180.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wood, D., Bruner, J., & Ross, G. (1976). The role of tutoring in problem solving. Journal of Child Psychology, 17(2), 89–100.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ziegler, J. C., & Goswami, U. (2006). Becoming literate in different languages: Similar problems, different solutions. Developmental Science, 9(5), 429–436.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank two anonymous reviewers for their constructive comments on this paper. Furthermore, I am grateful to Richard Menary, Thomas Metzinger, and Jakob Hohwy for various helpful discussions along the way. Part of this work was funded by the Barbara Wengeler Foundation.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Regina E. Fabry.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Fabry, R.E. Betwixt and between: the enculturated predictive processing approach to cognition. Synthese 195, 2483–2518 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1334-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1334-y

Keywords

Navigation