Skip to main content
Log in

What makes unique hues unique?

  • S.I.: Neuroscience and Its Philosophy
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

There exist two widely used notions concerning the structure of phenomenal color space. The first is the notion of unique/binary hue structure, which maintains that there are four unique hues from which all other hues are composed. The second notion is the similarity structure of hues, which describes the interrelations between the hues and hence does not divide hues into two types as the first notion does. Philosophers have considered the existence of the unique/binary hue structure to be empirically and phenomenally well-grounded, and the structure has been considered to be primary because this can account for the similarity structure. Consequently, the unique/binary hue structure has played a central role in color philosophy. This calls for the assessment of the justification for its existence carried out in this paper. It is concluded that, despite the prevalent view among philosophers, none of their reasons for endorsing the existence of the unique/binary hue structure are justified. Since the notion of the unique/binary hue structure appears intuitively plausible for many, however, a sketch explaining this intuition is outlined at the end.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The structure of phenomenal color space concerns colors as experienced. Therefore, it should not be confused with different color models that make use of primary colors from which other colors can be combined.

  2. Rather than adding “unique” for each occurrence of “unique red”, I simply refer to it as “red” (and inter alia for other unique hues) in Sects. 2, 3, 4 and 5, which focus on the unique/binary hue structure.

  3. It is often taught that red, yellow, and blue are the only basic hues and that other hues can be mixed from them. The previous may explain paint-bias (Miller 1997), which is the common error of excluding green from the unique hues since it is true that green can be mixed from yellow and blue when the discussion concerns commonly used pigments. Yet this does not imply that green is any more a phenomenally composed color than red.

  4. This analogy is obviously not perfect, given that warmth is not a circular qualitative space while colors are. Nevertheless, this difference does not have a bearing on the issue of phenomenal composition.

  5. The third prominent theory of color during the first part of the twentieth century was Christine Ladd-Franklin’s (1916, 1929) theory of color sensations. It unified Helmholtz’s and Hering’s theories by incorporating the ideas of three types of receptors (Helmholtz) and four opponent colors (Hering). Ladd-Franklin was first to provide an explanation of the evolutionary development of color vision in humans too. Her theory is not elaborated on because it can be seen to anticipate Hurvich and Jameson’s theory of opponent-processes and the interest towards Ladd-Franklin’s theory decreased significantly once their theory was presented.

  6. It is interesting to note that the same conclusion can be drawn from the history of describing the colors of the rainbow. If making judgments about one’s own color experiences were easy, one would assume that this is a matter in which people would have approximately the same opinions. Yet, the number of colors perceived in the rainbow have been claimed to be three (e.g., Aristotle, later Thomas Young), six (e.g., Aëtius, Ammianus Marcellinus), seven (Sir Isaac Newton’s assistant), eleven (Sir Isaac Newton), and too many to count (e.g., Ovid, Virgil) (Gage 1999; Newton 1704/1952).

  7. As the discussion on Helmholtz implied, he was explicit in not linking properties of chromatic processing with hues as experienced. Instead, unique hues became explicitly linked to neurophysiological mechanisms only after the opponent-processes were discovered in LGN. As will be discussed shortly, such an idea is no longer generally endorsed, as there is no physiological evidence for the existence of primary axes of opponent processes that match unique hues.

  8. Moreover, Bosten and Boehm’s results showed that what subjects identified as a unique hue shifted significantly as a function of the color terms used in the instructions. This in part causes one to “question subjects’ abilities to identify certain hues as unique.” (Bosten and Boehm 2014, p. A385)

  9. For example, they do not separate blue and green, but they have a separation that does not exist in English (see the study for details).

  10. It is worth noticing that, while the graphical multiscaling result gave reasons to accept the presented interpretation of the original Dani experiment (Heider and Olivier 1972), the interpretation can be questioned too. This is because the statistical measures used by Heider and Olivier gave conflicting results by also suggesting that the performance of the Dani people is best explained by linguistic and cognitive factors. For some reason, the first measure was accepted while an explanation for the second measure is still missing.

  11. Indeed, excluding yellow, unique hues are not more salient in search tasks than binary hues (Wool et al. 2015).

  12. This is in accordance with the earlier study showing that the preferred hues of color-selective neurons (those that respond almost only to colors) cover nearly all color space and thus show no preference for unique hues (Komatsu et al. 1992).

  13. For a very thorough discussion on how this could be done, see (Clark 1993).

  14. It should be remembered that this analogy is only partial because warmth does not form a circular qualitative space. This difference is not crucial here, however, because the issue at hand concerns similarity judgments, not the linearity or circularity of a quality space per se, and we can make such judgments for both colors and warmth.

  15. At the same time, this plasticity of the basic hue categories would explain the larger color vocabulary of visual artists and their reluctance to regard only red, green, yellow, and blue as basic hues (and unique hues). Since most people do not need such a refined color vocabulary, they consider fewer hues as basic hues.

  16. They can be perceived together in special circumstances (Crane and Piantanida 1983) and this has been used in an argument against color objectivism (e.g., Arstila 2003).

  17. As an analogy, consider a line in which we arbitrarily mark some basic points. Every non-basic point is then close to only two basic points and becomes defined in relation to them and not to the other basic points. The same thing holds for color space, and that is why every “composed” hue can only be composed of two hues.

  18. I am grateful to Austen Clark, Franklin Scott, Kalle Pihlainen and Susanne Uusitalo, as well as for the anonymous reviewers for their generous and constructive comments on prior versions of the manuscript.

References

  • Abramov, I., & Gordon, J. (1994). Color appearance: On seeing red-or yellow, or green, or blue. Annual Review of Psychology, 45, 451–485. doi:10.1146/annurev.ps.45.020194.002315.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arstila, V. (2003). True colours, false theories. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 81(1), 41–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berlin, B., & Kay, P. (1969). Basic color terms: Their universality and evolution. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bosten, J. M., & Boehm, A. E. (2014). Empirical evidence for unique hues? Journal of the Optical Society of America A, 31(4), A385–A393.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bosten, J., & Lawrance-Owen, A. (2014). No difference in variability of unique hue selections and binary hue selections. Journal of the Optical Society of America, 31(4), A357–A364.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bradley, P., & Tye, M. (2001). Of colors, kestrels, caterpillars, and leaves. Journal of Philosophy, 98, 469–487.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brentano, F. (1979). Vom Phänomenalen Grün. In F. Brentano (Ed.), Untersuchungen zur Sinnespsychologie. Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Byrne, A. (2003). Color and similarity. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research., LXVI, 641–665.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Byrne, A., & Hilbert, D. R. (1997). Colors and reflectances. In A. Byrne & D. R. Hilbert (Eds.), Readings on color, volume 1: The philosophy of color (pp. 263–288). Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Byrne, A., & Hilbert, D. R. (2003). Color realism and color science. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 26, 3–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chichilnisky, E. J., & Wandell, B. A. (1999). Trichromatic opponent color classification. Vision Research, 39, 3444–3458.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. (2005). Chimerical colors: Some phenomenological predictions from cognitive neuroscience. Philosophical Psychology, 18(5), 527–560.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (1993). Sensory Qualities. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, J. (2003). On the structural properties of the colors. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 81, 78–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Conway, B. R., & Stoughton, C. M. (2009). Response: Towards a neural representation for unique hues. Current Biology, 19(11), R442–R443. doi:10.1016/j.cub.2009.04.056.

  • Conway, B. R., & Tsao, D. Y. (2009). Color-tuned neurons are spatially clustered according to color preference within alert macaque posterior inferior temporal cortex. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 106(42), 18034–18039. doi:10.1073/pnas.0810943106.

  • Crane, H. D., & Piantanida, T. P. (1983). On seeing reddish green and yellowish blue. Science, 221(4615), 1078–1080.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidoff, J., Davies, I., & Roberson, D. (1999). Colour categories in a stone-age tribe. Nature, 398(6724), 203–4.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Valois, R. L., De Valois, K. K., Switkes, E., & Mahon, L. (1997). Hue scaling of isoluminant and cone-specific lights. Vision Research, 37(7), 885–897.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gage, J. (1999). Color and culture: Practice and meaning from antiquity to abstraction. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hardin, C. L. (1988). Color for philosophers, unweaving the rainbow. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hardin, C. L. (2003). A spectral reflectance doth not a color make. The Journal of Philosophy, 100(4), 191–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heider, E. R. (1972). Universals in color naming and memory. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 93(1), 10–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heider, E. R., & Olivier, D. C. (1972). The structure of the color space in naming and memory for two languages. Cognitive Psychology, 3(2), 337–354.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hering, E. (1878). Zur lehre vom lichtsinne (on the theory of sensibility to light). Wien: Carl Gerold’s Sohn.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hilbert, D. R. (1992). What is color vision? Philosophical Studies, 68, 351–370.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hurvich, L., & Jameson, D. (1957). An opponent-process theory of color vision. Psychological Review, 64(6), 384–404.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jameson, K. (2005a). On the role of culture in color naming: Remarks on the articles of Paramei, Kay, Roberson, and Hardin on the topic of cognition, culture, and color experience. Cross Cultural Research, 39(1), 88–106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jameson, K. (2005b). Culture and cognition: What is universal about the representation of color experience? Journal of Cognition and Culture, 5(3–4), 293–347.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jameson, K. (2010). Where in the world color survey is the support for the hering primaries as the basis for color categorization? In J. Cohen & M. Matthen (Eds.), Color ontology and color science (pp. 179–202). Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Jameson, K., & Alvarado, N. (2003). Differences in color naming and color salience in Vietnamese and English. Color Research and Application, 28(2), 113–138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jameson, K., & D’Andrade, R. G. (1997). It’s not really red, green, yellow, blue: An inquiry into cognitive color space. In C. L. Hardin & L. Maffi (Eds.), Color categories in thought and language (pp. 295–319). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Johnston, M. (1992). How to speak of the color. Philosophical Studies, 68, 221–263.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kay, P., & Regier, T. (2003). Resolving the question of color naming universals. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 100(15), 9085–9089.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kiper, D. C., Fenstemaker, S. B., & Gegenfurtner, K. R. (1997). Chromatic properties of neurons in macaque area V2. Visual Neuroscience, 14(6), 1061–1072. doi:10.1017/S0952523800011779.

  • Komatsu, H., Ideura, Y., Kaji, S., & Yamane, S. (1992). Color selectivity of neurons in the inferior temporal cortex of the awake macaque monkey. The Journal of Neuroscience, 12(2), 408–424.

  • Krauskopf, J., Williams, D. R., & Heeley, D. W. (1982). Cardinal directions of color space. Vision Research, 22, 1123–1131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuehni, R. G. (2005). Focal color variability and unique hue stimulus variability. Journal of Cognition and Culture, 5(3), 409–426. doi:10.1163/156853705774648554.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ladd-Franklin, C. (1916). On color theories and chromatic sensations. Psychological Review, 23(3), 237–249.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ladd-Franklin, C. (1929). Colour and colour theories. New York: Harcourt, Brace & Company Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lennie, P., Krauskopf, J., & Sclar, G. (1990). Chromatic mechanisms in striate cortex of macaque. The Journal of Neuroscience, 10(2), 649–669.

  • Malkoc, G., Kay, P., & Webster, M. A. (2005). Variations in normal color vision. IV. Binary hues and hue scaling. Journal of the Optical Society of America A, 22(10), 2154–2168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, D. (1997). Beyond the elements: Investigations of hue. In C. L. Hardin & L. Maffi (Eds.), Color categories in thought and language. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mollon, J. D. (2009). A neural basis for unique hues? Current Biology, 19(11), R441–R442.

  • Newton, I. (1704/1952). Opticks. London: Smith & Walford/Dover.

  • Regier, T., Kay, P., & Khetarpal, N. (2007). Color naming reflects optimal partitions of color space. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA, 104(4), 1436–1441.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Regier, T., Kay, P., & Khetarpal, N. (2009). Color naming and the shape of color space. Language, 85(4), 884–892.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roberson, D., Davidoff, J., Davies, I., & Shapiro, L. (2005). Color categories: Evidence for the cultural relativity hypothesis. Cognitive Psychology, 50, 378–411.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roberson, D., Davies, I., & Davidoff, J. (2000). Colour categories are not universal: Replications and new evidence from a stone-age culture. Journal of Experimental Psychology General, 129, 369–398.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saunders, B. A. C., & van Brakel, J. (1997). Are there nontrivial constraints on colour categorization. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 20, 167–179.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schein, S. J., & Desimone, R. (1990). Spectral properties of V4 neurons in the macaque. The Journal of Neuroscience, 10(10), 3369–3389.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sternheim, C. E., & Boynton, R. M. (1966). Uniqueness of perceived hues investigated with a continuous judgmental technique. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 72, 770–776.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stoughton, C. M., & Conway, B. R. (2008). Neural basis for unique hues. Current Biology, 18(16), R698–R699. doi:10.1016/j.cub.2008.06.018.

  • Suarez, J., & Nida-Rümelin, M. (2009). Reddish–green: A challenge for modal claims about phenomenal structure. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 78, 346–391.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Brakel, J. (1994). The ignis fatuus of semantic universalia: The case of colour. British Journal of Philosophy of Science, 45, 770–783.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • von Goethe, J. W. (1810). Zur Farbenlehre (Theory of Colours). Tübingen.

  • von Helmholtz, H. L. F. (1867). Handbuch der physiologischen optik (handbook of physiological optics). Leipzig: von Leopold Voss.

    Google Scholar 

  • Webster, M. A., Miyahara, E., Malkoc, G., & Raker, V. E. (2000). Variations in normal color vision. II. Unique hues. Journal of Optical Society of America, A 17(9), 1545–1555.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Winawer, J., Witthoft, N., Frank, M. C., Wu, L., Wade, A. R., & Boroditsky, L. (2007). Russian blues reveal effects of language on color discrimination. PNAS, 104, 7780–7785.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wool, L. E., Komban, S. J., Kremkow, J., Jansen, M., Alonso, J.-M., Li, X., et al. (2015). Salience of unique hues and implications for color theory. Journal of Vision, 15(2), 1–11.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wooten, B., & Miller, D. L. (1997). The psychophysics of color. In C. L. Hardin & L. Maffi (Eds.), Color categories in thought and language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright, W. (forthcoming). Eliminativism. In D. Brown & F. Macpherson (Eds.), The Routledge handbook of philosophy of color. Routledge.

  • Wright, W. (2013). Psychologically pure colors. In R. Luo (Ed.), Encyclopedia of color science and technology (pp. 1–4). New York: Springer. doi:10.1007/978-3-642-27851-8_78-8.

    Google Scholar 

  • Xiao, Y., Wang, Y., & Felleman, D. (2003). A spatially organized representation of colour in macaque cortical area V2. Nature, 421, 535–539. doi:10.1038/nature01372.

  • Zeki, S. (1983). Colour coding in the celebral cortex: the reaction of cells in monkey visual cortex to wavelenghts and colours. Neuroscience, 9, 741–765.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zeki, S., & Marini, L. (1998). Three cortical stages of colour processing in the human brain. Brain, 121, 1669–1685.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Valtteri Arstila.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Arstila, V. What makes unique hues unique?. Synthese 195, 1849–1872 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1313-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1313-3

Keywords

Navigation