Skip to main content
Log in

Anchoring in ecosystemic kinds

  • S.I.: Causation in Metaphysics
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The world contains many different types of ecosystems. This is something of a commonplace in biology and conservation science. But there has been little attention to the question of whether such ecosystem types enjoy a degree of objectivity—whether they might be natural kinds. I argue that traditional accounts of natural kinds that emphasize nomic or causal–mechanistic dimensions of “kindhood” are ill-equipped to accommodate presumptive ecosystemic kinds. In particular, unlike many other kinds, ecosystemic kinds are “anchored” to the contingent character of species and higher taxa and their abiotic environments. Drawing on Slater (Br J Philos Sci 66(2):375–411, 2015a), I show how we can nevertheless make room for such contingent anchoring in an account of natural kinds of ecosystems kinds.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I will not have much to say about the first question for want of space and because it seems to me that the questions are perpendicular to each other, addressing very different theoretical desiderata; for more discussion, see Sect. 2 below.

  2. I take a similar approach to the reality of biological species in Chap. 6 of Slater (2013a). I have no particular view about whether we should see particular ecosystems as individuals (for useful discussion, see Odenbaugh 2007; Bryant 2012).

  3. More precisely: it is often hypothesized that requisite levels of non-contingency for natural kinds are only secured by appropriate causal relations or connections to natural laws.

  4. It is not quite as clear that the reverse possibility holds. Can there be types of ecosystems without particular ecosystems, a forest with no trees? I happen to think that the answer to this question is ‘yes’, though I won’t defend this line in any detail here; instead, I will simply presume that there are particular ecosystems (in whatever sense is workable) in asking whether there are also ecosystemic types.

  5. Variations on this basic theme can also be found in Dupré (1993) and Rosenberg (2001).

  6. Despite taking a fairly strict stance on the connection between kinds and laws (see above), Lange (1995, 2004) provides resources that I believe will be quite useful for making sense of ecosystemic kinds and natural kinds more generally. I’ll come back to this point in Sect. 5.

  7. For other articulations and elaborations of the HPC view, see Kornblith (1993), Griffiths (1997, 1999), Wilson (1999, 2005), Wilson et al. 2007, Slater (2015a). More epistemically-oriented accounts of natural kinds likewise opt to forge conceptual connections with causal rather than nomic concepts (Magnus 2012; Khalidi 2013). My attention here will be on Boyd’s view as (loosely) representative of the general strategy; for brief discussion of Magnus and Khalidi, see Slater (2013b, 2015b).

  8. For more detail about and defense of these claims, see Slater (2015a). In that paper, I make the suggestion (omitted here for brevity’s sake) that rather than attempting to think of natural kinds as an ontological category to be univocally characterized (as in Lowe 2006; Bird 2007, 2011), we should see “natural kindness” as a sort of status that different categories can enjoy in view of their stability and hence aptness for inference/explanation. This is presumably not a view that Lange would go in for, for as we’ve seen, Lange takes a particularly strong view of the relationship between laws and natural kinds; kinds must be, in a sense, governed by meta-laws.

References

  • Beatty, J. (1995). The evolutionary contingency thesis. In G. Wolters & J. G. Lennox (Eds.), Concepts, theories, and rationality in the biological sciences (pp. 45–81). Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Begon, M., Townsend, C. R., & Harper, J. L. (2006). Ecology: From individuals to ecosystems (4th ed.). Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Belyea, L. R., & Lancaster, J. (1999). Assembly rules within a contingent ecology. Oikos, 86, 402–416.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A. (2007). Nature’s metaphysics: Laws and properties. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A. (2011). Are any kinds ontologically fundamental? In T. Tahko (Ed.), Contemporary aristotelian metaphysics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1991). Realism, anti-foundationalism and the enthusiasm for natural kinds. Philosophical Studies, 61, 127–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. (1999). Homeostasis, species, and higher taxa. In R. A. Wilson (Ed.), Species: New interdisciplinary essays. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brett, C. E. (2012). Coordinated stasis reconsidered: A perspective at fifteen years. In J. A. Talent (Ed.), Earth and life: Global biodiversity, extinction intervals and biogeographic perturbations through time (pp. 23–36). Dordrecht: Springer.

  • Brett, C. E., Ivany, L. C., & Schopf, K. M. (1996). Coordinated stasis: An overview. Palaeogeography, 127, 1–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brinson, M. M., & Verhoeven, J. (1999). Riparian forests. In M. L. Hunter (Ed.), Maintaining biodiversity in forest ecosystems. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bryant, R. (2012). What if ecological communities are not wholes? In W. P. Kabasenche, M. O’Rourke, & M. H. Slater (Eds.), The environment: Philosophy, science, and ethics. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Budiansky, S. (1995). Nature’s keepers: The new science of nature management. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chakravartty, A. (2007). A metaphysics for scientific realism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Clements, F. (1916). Plant Succession: An analysis of the development of vegetation, Publication no. 242. Washington, DC: Carnegie Institution of Washington.

  • Cody, M., & Diamond, J. (1975). Ecology and evolution of communities. Cambridge: Belknap Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cooper, G. J. (2003). The science of the struggle for existence: On the foundations of ecology. Cambridge: Cambridge Unviersity Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F. (2009). Mechanisms and natural kinds. Philosophical Psychology, 22(5), 575–594.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F. (2013). In search of mechanisms: Discoveries across the life sciences. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M. (2008). Resurrecting biological essentialism. Philosophy of Science, 75(3), 344–382.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dodds, W. K. (2009). Laws, theories, and patterns in ecology. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dupré, J. (1993). The disorder of things. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, B. (2001). Scientific essentialism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ginzburg, L., & Colyvan, M. (2004). Ecological orbits: How planets move and populations grow. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gleason, H. A. (1917). The structure and development of the plant association. Bulletin of the Torrey Botanical Club, 53, 463–481.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gleason, H. A. (1926). The individualistic concept of the plant association. Bulletin of the Torrey Botanical Club, 53, 7–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gleason, H. A. (1939). The individualistic concept of the plant association. American Midland Naturalist, 21, 92–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Golley, F. B. (1993). A history of the ecosystem concept in ecology: More than the sum of the parts. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S. J. (1989). Wonderful life. New York: W. W. Norton & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P. E. (1997). What emotions really are: The problem of psychological categories. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P. E. (1999). Squaring the circle: Natural kinds with historical essences. In R. A. Wilson (Ed.), Species: New interdisciplinary essays. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Häggqvist, S. (2005). Kinds, projectibility and explanation. Croatian Journal of Philosophy, 5(13), 71–87.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haufe, C. (2013). From necessary chances to biological laws. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 64, 279–295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. G. (1965). Fundamentals of taxonomy. Reprinted in his Aspects of Scientific Explanation (pp. 137–154). New York: Free Press.

  • Holdridge, L. R. (1947). Determination of world plant formations from simple climatic data. Science, 105, 367–368.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holdridge, L. R. (1967). Life zone ecology. San Jose: Tropical Science Center.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ivany, L. C., Brett, C. E., Wall, H. L. B., Wall, P. D., & Handley, J. C. (2009). Relative taxonomic and ecologic stability in Devonian marine faunas of New York State: A test of coordinated stasis. Paleobiology, 35(4), 499–524.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Khalidi, M. A. (2013). Natural categories and human kinds. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1984). Species. Philosophy of Science, 51, 308–333.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kornblith, H. (1993). Inductive inference and its natural ground. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lange, M. (1995). Are there natural laws concerning particular biological species. Journal of Philosophy, 92(8), 430–451.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lange, M. (2000). Natural laws in scientific practice. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lange, M. (2004). The autonomy of functional biology: A reply to Rosenberg. Biology and Philosophy, 19, 93–109.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lange, M. (2005). Ecological laws: What would they be and why would they matter? Oikos, 110(2), 394–403.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lange, M. (2009). Laws and lawmakers. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawton, J. H. (1999). Are there general laws in ecology. Oikos, 84, 177–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lipton, P. (1996). Review of Kornblith, inductive Inference and its natural ground. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 56(2), 492–494.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lowe, E. J. (2006). The four-category ontology: A metaphysical foundation for natural science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lugo, A. E., Brown, S. L., Dodson, R., Smith, T. S., & Shugart, H. H. (1999). The Holdridge life zones of the conterminous United States in relation to ecosystem mapping. Journal of Biogeography, 26, 1025–1038.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacArthur, R. H., & Wilson, E. O. (1967). The theory of island biogeography. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnus, P. D. (2012). Scientific enquiry and natural kinds: From planets to mallards. London: Palgrave-Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mikkelson, G. M. (2003). Ecological kinds and ecological laws. Philosophy of Science, 70, 1390–1400.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, S. (2000). Dimensions of scientific law. Philosophy of Science, 67, 242–265.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mitchell, S. (2002). Contingent generalizations: Lessons from biology. In R. Mayntz (Ed.), Akteure–Mechanismen–Modelle. Frankfurt: Campus Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morin, P. J. (2011). Community ecology (2nd ed.). Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Morris, P. J., Ivany, L. C., & Schopf, K. M. (1995). The challenge of paleoecological stasis: Reassessing sources of evolutionary stability. Proceedings of the National Academy of Science, 92, 11269–11273.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mumford, S. (2005). Kinds, essences, powers. Ratio, 18(4), 420–436.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, E. (1961). The structure of science: Problems in the logic of scientific explanation. New York: Harcort, Brace, and World.

    Google Scholar 

  • Odenbaugh, J. (2007). Seeing the forest and the trees: Realism about communities and ecosystems. Philosophy of Science, 74, 628–641.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Odum, E. P. (1953). Fundamentals of ecology. Philadelphia: W.B. Saunders.

    Google Scholar 

  • Okasha, S. (2002). Darwinian metaphysics: Species and the question of essentialism. Synthese, 131, 191–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Palik, B., & Engstrom, R. T. (1999). Species composition. In M. L. Hunter (Ed.), Maintaining biodiversity in forest ecosystems. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975). Is semantics possible?. Reprinted in his Mind, Language and reality: Philosophical papers (Vol. 2). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Rosenberg, A. (2001). How is biological explanation possible? British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 52, 735–760.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simberloff, D. S. (1974). Equilibrium theory of island biogeography and ecology. Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics, 5, 161–182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simberloff, D. S. (2004). Community ecology: Is it time to move on? The American Naturalist, 163(6), 787–799.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Slater, M. H. (2013a). Are species real?. London: Palgrave-Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Slater, M. H. (2013b). Review of scientific enquiry and natural kinds, Notre Dame philosophical reviews. http://ndpr.nd.edu/news/40779-scientific-enquiry-and-natural-kinds-from-planets-to-mallards/

  • Slater, M. H. (2015a). Natural kindness. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 66(2), 375–411.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Slater, M. H. (2015b). Review of natural categories and human kinds. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 66, 1017–1023.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (1980). Evolution, population thinking, and essentialism. Philosophy of Science, 47, 350–383.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (1997). Two outbreaks of lawlessness in recent philosophy of biology. Philosophy of Science, 64, S458–467.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tansley, A. G. (1935). The use and abuse of vegetational terms and concepts. Ecology, 16, 284–307.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Whittaker, R. H., & Niering, W. A. (1965). Vegetation of the Santa Catalina Mountains, Arizona: A gradient analysis of the south slope. Ecology, 46, 429–452.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wieder, R. K., & Vitt, D. H. (Eds.). (2006). Boreal peatland ecosystems. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, R. A. (1999). Realism, essence, and kind: Resuscitating species essentialism? In R. A. Wilson (Ed.), Species: New interdisciplinary essays. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, R. A. (2005). Genes and the agents of life. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, R. A., Barker, M. J., & Brigandt, I. (2007). When traditional essentialism fails: Biological natural kinds. Philosophical Topics, 35(1/2), 189–215.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2001). Law and explanation in biology: Invariance is the kind of stability that matters. Philosophy of Science, 68, 1–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zimmerman, E., Davis, T., Podniesinski, G., Furedi, M., McPherson, J., & Seymour, S. (Eds.). (2012). Terrestrial and palustrine plant communities of Pennsylvania (2nd ed.). Harrisburg, PA: Pennsylvania Natural Heritage Program, Pennsylvania Department of Conservation and Natural Resources.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thanks to audiences at the IHPST workshop on “Causation and Metaphysics” organized by Andrew McFarland (particularly Andrew, P.D. Magnus, Thomas Reydon) and at POBAM2014 (particularly Matt Barker, Matt Haber, Roberta Millstein, Elliott Sober, and Joel Velasco) for helpful suggestions. Thanks also to two anonymous referees for Synthese for constructive criticism and Jay Odenbaugh and Jeff Trop for sound advice on earlier drafts.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Matthew H. Slater.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Slater, M.H. Anchoring in ecosystemic kinds. Synthese 195, 1487–1508 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1302-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1302-y

Keywords

Navigation