Skip to main content
Log in

The topological realization

  • S.I.: Mechanistic & Topological
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper, I argue that the newly developed network approach in neuroscience and biology provides a basis for formulating a unique type of realization, which I call topological realization. Some of its features and its relation to one of the dominant paradigms of realization and explanation in sciences, i.e. the mechanistic one, are already being discussed in the literature. But the detailed features of topological realization, its explanatory power and its relation to another prominent view of realization, namely the semantic one, have not yet been discussed. I argue that topological realization is distinct from mechanistic and semantic ones because the realization base in this framework is not based on local realisers, regardless of the scale (because the local vs global distinction can be applied at any scale) but on global realizers. In mechanistic approach, the realization base is always at the local level, in both ontic (Craver 2007, 2014) and epistemic accounts (Bechtel and Richardson 2010). The explanatory power of realization relation in mechanistic approach comes directly from the realization relation-either by showing how a model is mapped onto a mechanism, or by describing some ontic relations that are explanatory in themselves. Similarly, the semantic approach requires that concepts at different scales logically satisfy microphysical descriptions, which are at the local level. In topological framework the realization base can be found at different scales, but whatever the scale the realization base is global, within that scale, and not local. Furthermore, topological realization enables us to answer the “why” questions, which according to Polger 2010 make it explanatory. The explanatoriness of topological realization stems from understanding mathematical consequences of different topologies, not from the mere fact that a system realizes them.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The nodes in this case are the states, not what is in a state.

  2. The rich-club organization is characterized by the fact that network hubs are densely interconnected to one another.

  3. This is a technical term that denotes the subjective qualities of conscoius experience, or the properties of what it is like to be in some conscious states.

References

  • Achard, S., Salvador, R., Whitcher, B., Suckling, J., & Bullmore, E. D. (2006). A resilient, low-frequency, small-world human brain functional network with highly connected association cortical hubs. The Journal of Neuroscience, 26(1), 63–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alexander-Bloch, A. F., Vértes, P. E., Stidd, R., Lalonde, F., Clasen, L., Rapoport, J., & Gogtay, N. (2012). The anatomical distance of functional connections predicts brain network topology in health and schizophrenia. Cerebral cortex, bhr388.

  • Barabási, A. L. (2002). Linked: How everything is connected to everything else and what it means. New York: Plume Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bassett, D. S., & Siebenhühner, F. (2013). Multiscale network organization in the human brain. Multiscale analysis and nonlinear dynamics: From genes to the brain (pp. 179–204).

  • Bassett, D. S., & Bullmore, E. D. (2006). Small-world brain networks. The Neuroscientist, 12(6), 512–523.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., & Richardson, R. C. (2010). Discovering complexity: Decomposition and localization as strategies in scientific research (2nd ed.). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press/Bradford Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Block, N., & Stalnaker, R. (1999). Conceptual analysis, dualism, and the explanatory gap. Philosophical Review, 108(1), 1–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blondel, V. D., Sontag, E. D., Vidyasagar, M., & Willems, J. C. (Eds.). (2012). Open problems in mathematical systems and control theory. New York: Springer Science & Business Media.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bressler, S. L. (1995). Large-scale cortical networks and cognition. Brain Research Reviews, 20(3), 288–304.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, M. (2003). Nexus: Small worlds and the groundbreaking theory of networks. New York: WW Norton & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (2010). The two-dimensional argument against materialism. In B. P. McLaughlin & S. Walter (Eds.), Oxford handbook to the philosophy of mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F. (2007). Explaining the brain: Mechanisms and the mosaic unity of neuroscience. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F. (2014). The ontic account of scientific explanation. Explanation in the Special Sciences (pp. 27–52). Netherlands: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F. (2016). The Explanatory Power of Network Models. Philosophy of Science (forthcoming).

  • Darrason, M. (2015). Mechanistic and topological explanations in medicine: the case of medical genetics and network medicine. Synthese. doi:10.1007/s11229-015-0983-y.

  • Dowell, J. (2008). A priori entailment and conceptual analysis: Making room for type-C physicalism. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 86, 93–111.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Endicott, R. (2005). Multiple realizability. The encyclopedia of philosophy (2nd ed.). New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fortunato, S. (2010). Community detection in graphs. Physics Reports, 486(3–5), 75–174.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gillett, C. (2010). Moving beyond the subset model of realization: The problem of qualitative distinctness in the metaphysics of science. Synthese, 177(2), 165–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gu, S., Pasqualetti, F., Cieslak, M., Telesford, Q. K., Alfred, B Yu., Kahn, A. E., et al. (2015). Controllability of structural brain networks. Nature Communications, 6, 8414.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Honey, C. J., Kötter, R., Breakspear, M., & Sporns, O. (2007). Network structure of cerebral cortex shapes functional connectivity on multiple time scales. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 104(24), 10240–10245.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Honey, C. J., Thivierge, J. P., & Sporns, O. (2010). Can structure predict function in the human brain? Neuroimage, 52(3), 766–776.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huneman, P. (2015). Diversifying the picture of explanations in biological sciences: ways of combining topology with mechanisms. Synthese. doi:10.1007/s11229-015-0808-z

  • Huneman, P. (2010). Topological explanations and robustness in biological sciences. Synthese, 177, 213–245.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hutchison, R. M., Womelsdorf, T., Allen, E. A., Bandettini, P. A., Calhoun, V. D., Corbetta, M., et al. (2013). Dynamic functional connectivity: Promise, issues, and interpretations. Neuroimage, 80, 360–378.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. M. (2011). Explanation and description in computational neuroscience. Synthese, 183, 339–373.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leith, D. J., & Leithead, W. E. (2000). Survey of gain-scheduling analysis and design. International Journal of Control, 73(11), 1001–1025.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levine, J. (2001). Purple haze: The puzzle of conscious experience. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Levy, A., & Bechtel, W. (2013). Abstraction and the organization of mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 80(2), 241–261.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machamer, P., Darden, L., & Craver, C. F. (2000). Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 67, 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McClelland, J. L. (1988). Connectionist models and psychological evidence. Journal of Memory and Language, 27(2), 107–123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meunier, D., Lambiotte, R., Fornito, A., Ersche, K. D., & Bullmore, E. T. (2010). Hierarchical modularity in human brain functional networks. Hierarchy and dynamics in neural networks, 1, 2.

  • Mirollo, R. E., & Strogatz, S. H. (1990). Synchronization of pulse-coupled biological oscillators. SIAM Journal on Applied Mathematics, 50(6), 1645–1662.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Muldoon, S., & Bassett, D. (2016). Network and multilayer network approaches to understanding human brain dynamics. Philosophy of Science (forthcoming).

  • Newman, M. (2010). Networks: An introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pasqualetti, F., Zampieri, S., & Bullo, F. (2014). Controllability metrics, limitations and algorithms for complex networks. IEEE Transactions on Control of Network Systems, 1(1), 40–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Polger, T. W. (2010). Mechanisms and explanatory realization relations. Synthese, 177(2), 193–212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ponten, S. C., Daffertshofer, A., Hillebrand, A., & Stam, C. J. (2010). The relationship between structural and functional connectivity: Graph theoretical analysis of an EEG neural mass model. Neuroimage, 52(3), 985–994.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Power, J. D., Cohen, A. L., Nelson, S. M., Wig, G. S., Barnes, K. A., Church, J. A., et al. (2011). Functional network organization of the human brain. Neuron, 72(4), 665–678.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rathkopf, C. (2015). Network representation and complex systems. Synthese,. doi:10.1007/s11229-015-0726-0.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seung, S. H. (2012). Connectome: How the brain’s wiring makes us who we are. New York: Houghton Mifflin Harcourt Trade.

    Google Scholar 

  • Silberstein, M., & Chemero, A. (2013). Constraints on localization and decomposition as explanatory strategies in the biological sciences. Philosophy of Science, 80(5), 958–970.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sporns, O. (2012). Discovering the human connectome. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sporns, O., Tononi, G., & Kötter, R. (2005). The human connectome: A structural description of the human brain. PLoS Computational Biology, 1(4), e42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strogatz, S. (2003). Sync: The emerging science of spontaneous order. Chicago: Hyperion.

    Google Scholar 

  • Watts, D. J., & Strogatz, S. H. (1998). Collective dynamics of ‘small-world’ networks. Nature, 393(6684), 440–442.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, R. A., & Craver, C. F. (2006). Realization: Metaphysical and scientific perspectives. Philosophy of psychology and cognitive science. Amsterdam: North Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2013). Mechanistic explanation: Its scope and limits. Aristotelian Society Supplementary, 87(1), 39–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am very much indebted for their tremendously helpful discussions and comments on various versions of this paper to: Charles Rathkopf, Raphael van Riel, and Duško Prelević. I would like to emphasize my enormous gratitude for their support and discussions of these ideas to: Philippe Huneman and Carl F. Craver. I thank two anonymous reviewers for their very insightful and helpful comments that helped me make this paper much better. A version of this paper was presented at the conference Mind and Life: Mechanistic and Topological Perspectives, University of Belgrade, May, 2013, and I’d also like to thank the audience at the conference for their input.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Daniel Kostić.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Kostić, D. The topological realization. Synthese 195, 79–98 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1248-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1248-0

Keywords

Navigation